The Money Request Game: Evaluating the Upper Bound of k-level Reasoning

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "The Money Request Game: Evaluating the Upper Bound of k-level Reasoning"

Transcription

1 The Money Request Game: Evaluating the Upper Bound of k-level Reasoning Ayala Arad School of Economics, Tel Aviv University Ariel Rubinstein University of Tel Aviv Cafes School of Economics, Tel Aviv University Department of Economics, New York University Abstract We study experimentally a two-player game which we find ideal for investigating k-level reasoning. Each player requests an amount of money between 11 and 20 shekels. He receives the amount that he requests and if he requests exactly one shekel less than the other player, he receives an additional 20 shekels. The best response function in this game is straightforward, the k-level strategies are invariant to the two prominent level-0 specifications (randomization or attraction to salience) and the situation calls for self-interest behavior only. Therefore, we propose the game as a test for the "upper bound" for the depth of k-level reasoning in a population. We support this conjecture by studying several variations of the game which manipulate the attractiveness of the level-0 strategy and the monetary cost of undercutting the other player. Keywords: level-k thinking, salience, iterative reasoning We wish to thank Eli Zvuluny for managing the website used in this study and to Aviad Shany for classifying the subjects explanations. We are grateful to Anat Bracha, Vincent Crawford and Pedro Rey Biel for their valuable comments. We acknowledge financial support from the Center for Experimental Social Science at New York University and the Israeli Science Foundation, grant no. 259/08 and The Foerder Institute for Economic Research. Page 1

2 1.Introduction When a symmetric two-player game is played only once, the concept of Nash equilibrium often fails (dramatically) to describe the experimental results. A major task of the experimental game-theoretic literature is to provide better tools for explaining behavior in such situations. Prominent in this literature is the concept of k-level reasoning, first introduced in Stahl and Wilson (1994,1995) and Nagel (1995). A standard k-level model assumes that the population is partitioned into types, which differ in their depth of reasoning. A level-0 type is non-strategic and follows a simple decision rule. A level-k type (Lk), for any k 1, behaves as if he best responds to the belief that all other players are level k 1 types. Thus, a model is characterized by: (1) an L0 behavior (which is the starting point for iterative reasoning) and (2) a distribution of types. A typical study of k-level reasoning collects experimental data of a game and looks for the best fit to the data. That is, it finds an ex-post specification of an L0 strategy and a distribution of k-level types that best explain the results in a statistical sense. Only a few papers have attempted to elicit subjects actual levels of reasoning by analyzing other kinds of data in addition to the observed choice data. Examples include Costa-Gomes, Crawford and Broseta (2001) and Costa-Gomes and Crawford (2006) who examined data on information search behavior recorded using MouseLab; Bosch-Domenech, Montalvo, Nagel and Satorra (2002) and Arad (2009) who used ex-post explanations of their choices; and Burchardiy and Penczynski (2010) who analyzed subjects arguments while attempting to convince their teammates to follow their advice. However, most of the studies simply searched for the best fit to the data, after having assumed the level-0 behavior (which is sometimes specified after having observed the data). This research approach has also been applied to games in which the k-level procedure is not so natural, or in which the assumed L0 strategy is not common knowledge. An example is Crawford and Iriberri (2007) which analyzed the hide-and-seek game introduced in Rubinstein, Tversky and Heller (1996). Crawford and Iriberri (2007) found that given their assumptions on the level-0 behavior, the distribution of types that best fits the data included many level-3 and level-4 types. In contrast, Burchardiy and Penczynski (2010) s analysis of subjects arguments in the same hide-and-seek game suggests that subjects do not have a common starting point for iterated reasoning (i.e. level-0) and only few subjects practice more than two steps of reasoning given their own starting point. Not surprisingly, the distributions of k-level types differ between games. The fact that the Page 2

3 L0 parameter cannot always be clearly identified and that the distribution of types is variable creates doubt whether one can use k-level reasoning to predict behavior in a new game. In this paper, we study a very simple novel game, which is an ideal setting for applying a level-k procedure. We view the obtained distribution of k-level types in this game as an "upper bound" on the distributions of this population s actual level-k types in other one-shot games. This can be used (i) to narrow the predicted range of behavior in strategic situations that have not yet been studied and (ii) to examine whether a distribution of types found to best fit the data for a particular game is also reasonable as an actual explanation of subjects behavior in that game. Note, however, that we cannot expect the distribution of levels of reasoning to be identical across different populations. For example, students who have studied game theory are likely to apply higher levels of reasoning than students in the humanities. We therefore suggest the game as a tool for evaluating the upper bound on the k-level reasoning given a population. Following is a description of the basic version of the game, which we will refer to as the game: You and another student are playing a game in which each player requests an amount of money. The amount must be an integer between 11 and 20 shekels. Each player will receive the amount he requests. A player will receive an additional 20 shekels if he asks for exactly one shekel less than the other player. What amount of money would you request? There are five main aspects of the game that make it particularly suitable for studying k-level reasoning: (i) The level-0 type specification is intuitively appealing: The choice of 20 is a natural anchor for an iterative reasoning process. It is the instinctive choice when choosing a sum of money between 11 and 20 shekels (20 is clearly the salient number in this set and "the more money the better"). 1 Furthermore, the choice of 20 is not entirely naive: if a player does not want to take any risk or prefers to avoid strategic thinking, he might give up the attempt to win the additional 20 shekels and simply request the highest certain amount. (ii) Best-responding is straightforward: Given the anchor 20, best-responding to any level-k action is very simple and leaves no room for error. The strategy 19 is the best Page 3

4 response to 20, 18 is the best response to 19 and so on (it is less straightforward that the strategy 20 is a best response to 11). (iii) Robustness to the level-0 specification: The choice of 19, which is our level-1 strategy, is the unique best response to a wide range of reasonable beliefs on level-0 behavior including: (a) all distributions in which 20 is the most frequent choice and (b) the uniform distribution and a class of beliefs that are close to it. This makes the analysis robust to the specification of the level-0 behavior. (iv) Using k-level reasoning is very natural: The game s payoffs are described using the best response function explicitly, a characteristic that triggers iterative reasoning. Moreover, it is hard to think of alternative decision rules for this game. There is no pure-strategy Nash equilibrium and the game lacks dominated strategies. In fact, all strategies are contained within the support of the unique Nash equilibrium (described later). The only other conceivable rules of behavior would be randomly choosing a strategy or arbitrarily guessing the other player s strategy and best-responding to it. (v) Clear payoffs: Unlike some other games which also trigger iterative reasoning (such as Rosenthal (1981) s Centipede Game and Basu (1984) s Traveler s Dilemma), this game does not call for social preferences. In particular, if a player believes that his opponent will choose 20 (or some other amount), then requesting one shekel less will give him a bonus of 20 shekels but not at the expense of the other player. The above characteristics make the use of k-level reasoning in this game very appealing. It is hard to think of situations in which a player will employ a higher k-level reasoning than in this game. By analyzing two additional versions of the game, we confirm that enhancing the anchor for iterative reasoning and eliminating the monetary cost of undercutting the other player does not increase the depth of reasoning. Thus, given a population, we nominate the distribution of k-level types in the game as an upper bound for the distributions of types in other games. 2. The game Experimental Design: The subjects consisted of five classes of undergraduate economics students at Tel Aviv University (four classes of intermediate microeconomics and one class of the introductory course). The subjects had not studied game theory prior to the experiment (this topic is introduced only in a more advanced microeconomics course). Students were offered the opportunity to participate in a short experiment with monetary prizes during class time. All the students in each class decided to participate. Subjects Page 4

5 were asked to arrange themselves in the classroom so as not to be able to see their classmates answers. Three different forms, which corresponded to three versions of the game, were randomly distributed among the subjects (one form to each subject). In this section, we report only on the results for the basic version of the game (described in the introduction), which was played by 108 subjects out a total of 207. The instructions for each game appeared on the forms; no additional instructions were provided. After all the subjects had made their decision, they were asked to write an explanation of their choice on the back of the form. They did not know in advance that they would be asked to do so. After all the forms had been collected, each one was randomly matched to another and each subject received his resulting payoff. Results: Table 1 presents the unique Nash equilibrium distribution (assuming that players maximize expected payoff) and the actual distribution of choices in the experiment: Action Equilibrium 25% 25% 20% 15% 10% 5% Results 4% 0% 3% 6% 1% 6% 32% 30% 12% 6% Table 1: The game (n 108) The subjects behavior cannot be explained by the Nash equilibrium. The strategy 20 was chosen by 6% of the subjects which is almost identical to the equilibrium prediction. However, only 7% chose the strategies 15 and 16 which is far from the equilibrium prediction of 50%. The vast majority of subjects (74%) chose the actions which seem to exhibit levels of reasoning respectively, whereas in equilibrium they should have been chosen by only 45% of subjects. Every strategy in this game is by definition a level-k strategy for some k, but it does not necessarily mean that it actually reflects k-level reasoning. We interpret the choices in this game by analyzing the subjects ex-post explanations of their strategies 2. The students explanations of the choices of 19, 18 and 17 almost unanimously reflect one, two and three iterations, respectively (starting from the anchor of 20). Only 16% of the subjects chose one of the five strategies We think that such a choice was seldom an outcome of 4-8 iterations. This intuition is supported by the subjects explanations. There were no cases in which the choice of an action in the range was explained as a 5-8-level of reasoning and only one subject described the strategy 16 as an outcome of the forth level of Page 5

6 reasoning. The strategy 11 could be an outcome of a different kind of reasoning based on an open ended interative process. However, since only four subjects have chosen this strategy we defer the discussion on this strategy to another version of the game where it was more popular. The strategies were frequently described as guesses ("It is just a guess"). Few explanations explicitly mentioned best-responding to a specific belief without describing the belief s origin. In contrast, almost all the subjects who chose a strategy in the range explained their choices as an outcome of k-level reasoning ("I request 18 since many people believe that the majority requests 20 and thus request 19"). Such arguments were a little less frequent (77%) among subjects who chose 17. A typical explanation for the choice of 20 was "The chances to play against someone who requests one shekel more than me is very low. Therefore, I prefer to receive the highest sum for certain". The proportion of subjects who go through a k-level reasoning process obviously depends on the characteristics of the game and the population. However, we speculate that in game experiments with similar monetary incentives and subjects (i.e. economics students prior to taking a course in game theory) the distribution of level-k types would be first-order "stochastic-dominated" by the one we identify here 3. In other words, in other games we would not find: (i) a significant proportion of subjects who choose the level-4 or higher strategies, (ii) that significantly more than 80% of subjects 4 choose the strategies corresponding to levels 1, 2 or 3, (iii) that significantly more than 32% of the population chooses the level-3 strategy and (iv) that significantly more than 62% chooses the level-2 or level-3 strategies. Needless to say, we are not suggesting that this study projects on the maximal number of steps of iterated elimination of dominated strategies in games where such a procedure is possible. Studies of other games in the literature found that it is rare to explicitly observe subjects who practice more than three steps of iterative reasoning. However, one could think that it is due to the difficulty in using the level-k procedure in these games and in particular the complexity of the best-response function. In some other games, such as the Centipede Game and the Traveler s Dilemma, the behavior of many subjects is driven by social preferences which makes the use of iterative reasoning redundant. 5 Our most striking finding is that despite the simplicity of the iterative reasoning process and the implausibility of social preferences considerations in our game, about three-quarters of the choices seem to reflect up to three levels of reasoning. Note that the level of reasoning attributed to a player is the number of steps carried out from the starting point. It is possible that some subjects realized that the iterative process cycles and returned to the starting point of 20 on reaching strategy 11. In fact, this argument Page 6

7 appeared in only six explanations. The bottom line is that despite this understanding, they chose to conduct only up to three steps of reasoning from the starting strategy. The third version of the game which is reported on later, confirmed that this is not due to the "cost" of choosing a number lower than 17. The statement we attribute to a level-1 type is "I think that [he is doing something]". The statement we attribute to a level-2 type is "I think that [he thinks that I am doing something]", in which the level-1 statement is embedded. Expressing explicitly the considerations of a level-4 type would involve three such embedments. Whether these considerations are implicit or explicit, it seems that behavior which is consistent with such considerations is unnatural. This may be rooted in a more fundamental phenomenon observed by psychologists. Kinderman, Dunbar and Bentall (1998) found that most subjects do not understand a sentence such as: A thinks that B thinks that A thinks that B thinks that A is doing something", which is attributed to our level-4 type. (Almost all subjects understand sentences which we attribute to lower levels). They claim that this kind of sentence goes beyond the limit of reasoning normally used in real life and that most everyday situations probably do not require more than second-order intentionality. Literary scholars have also recently argued that "the zone of cognitive comfort" seems to be very limited. Zunshine (forthcoming) claims that using sentences with a higher number of embedments than in the sentence "I know that you think that he wants you to believe that she was angry at him" is rare and appears in the literature as a challenge to the reader. Thus, the scarcity of level-4 types seems to be in line with the findings in literature regarding the cognitive limit on the number of embedments and the rare use of high-order intentionality in everyday situations. An alternative interpretation of the results: In this paper, we have adopted the definition of a level-k type as a player who best-responds to the belief that the other player is a level k 1 type. Another version of the k-level model is that of the Cognitive Hierarchy model introduced by Camerer, Ho and Chong (2004), in which the level-k type best-responds to the conditional distribution of lower types and the distribution of types is assumed to be Poisson with parameter. Given the anchor of 20, the strategy 19 would be the choice of this model s level-1 type. Given the distribution of strategies in the experiment, the strategy 18 would be the best response to the conditional distribution of the lower types (who choose the strategies 19 and 20) and the strategy 17 would be the best response to the conditional distribution of 18, 19 and 20. Thus, the specification of levels 1-3 according to this model would be the same as before. The difference between the models emerges from the fact Page 7

8 that the strategy 17 is also a best response to the actual conditional distribution of the strategies Thus, the strategy 17 could also be interpreted as the choice of any type higher than 3. We did not find any support in our subjects explanations for the reasoning behind this alternative model. However, if we adopted this approach, we would look for the parameter that best fits the data (which would require additional assumptions on noise) and our study would suggest a tool for evaluating the upper limit of the parameter. 3. The Cycle Version The following version of the game was designed to show that enhancing the "status" of the L0 action does not increase the depth of level-k reasoning: You and another student are playing a game in which each player requests an amount of money. The amount must be an integer between 11 and 20 shekels. Each player will receive the amount of money he requests. A player will receive an additional amount of 20 shekels if: (i) he asks for exactly one shekel less than the other player, or (ii) he asks for 20 shekels and the other player asks for 11 shekels. What amount of money would you request? This version was assigned randomly to 72 subjects from the same pool and the experimental design remains the same (as described in section 2). Table 2 presents the equilibrium distribution and the results. For the purpose of comparison, the results of the basic version are presented here again. Action Equilibrium 25% 25% 20% 15% 10% 5% Cycle version 1% 1% 0% 1% 0% 4% 10% 22% 47% 13% game 4% 0% 3% 6% 1% 6% 32% 30% 12% 6% Table 2: The cycle version (n 72) The cycle version differs from the basic version in one crucial detail. In the basic version, a player who chooses 20 could not receive the bonus whereas in this version he can (if the other player chooses 11). Thus, the choice of 20 is even more attractive and justifiable than Page 8

9 before. We hypothesized that this would strengthen the role of 20 as a prominent starting point for iterative reasoning and will alter the distribution of strategies. In the results for this version, the strategy 20 is indeed more popular than in the basic version (13% vs. 6%, a difference which is significant at the 10% level). One might have expected that the use of level-k strategies (for k 0) would increase due to the enhancement of the level-0 strategy. However, the proportion of subjects who used a strategy in the range did not change significantly (it only increased from 74% to 79%). The explanations of the strategies in this range were very similar to those provided in the basic version. Level-k arguments appeared in all the explanations of the subjects who chose 18 and 19 and in 4 out of the 7 explanations of subjects who chose 17. On the other hand, now most of the choices in this range were of the strategy 19, which is the level-1 strategy. Furthermore, the difference between the conditional distributions of the low level-k types was significant. In other words, enhancing the L0 strategy induced subjects who used k-level reasoning to use fewer steps of iterative reasoning. To summarize, the role of the strategy 20 as the L0 was enhanced in this version and indeed the proportion of subjects who chose the L0 strategy doubled (though it remained small). This could have no effect on the distribution of k-level types. We found that the proportion of subjects who chose the L1, L2 and L3 strategies altogether did not change. However, the proportion of subjects who chose the L1 strategy increased dramatically while the proportion of those who chose L3 decreased. It seems that many potential low level-k types, compared to the basic version, recognized the extra-justifiability of L0 and expected it to be chosen frequently. We speculate that in other games, in which the L0 strategy is not as clear as in the basic version, we would not find levels of reasoning higher than those in the game. It is more likely that the level-k decision rules will be less frequent in such games and the use of other decision rules (that are not based on iterative reasoning) will be more common. 4. The Costless Iterations Version The following version of the game was designed to show that eliminating the cost of undercutting the other player does not increase the depth of level-k reasoning: You and another student are playing a game in which each player chooses an integer in the range A player who chooses 20 will receive 20 shekels (regardless of the other player s choice). A player who chooses any other number in this range will receive 3 shekels less than in Page 9

10 the case where he chooses 20. However, he can receive an additional amount of 20 shekels if he chooses a number that is lower by exactly one than the number chosen by the other player. Which number would you choose? Recall that in the basic version of the game, best-responding to 20 required giving up one "certain" shekel in the attempt to win an additional 20 shekels. In the same manner, performing another iteration and choosing 18 required giving up an additional shekel. One could suspect that the cost of additional iterations in the basic version is why subjects stop there at the level-3 strategy (17) and do not perform another iteration (which would require giving up an additional certain shekel). In the third version of the game, there is no cost to performing an additional iteration. The cost of choosing any integer in the range [11,19] is identical: instead of receiving 20 shekels for certain, each of these numbers guarantees only 17 shekels for certain. Therefore, when considering a strategy within the range [11,19], a player only considers the probability of winning the additional 20 shekels. This version was randomly assigned to 27 subjects from the same subject pool of the two other versions. Table 3 presents the equilibrium predictions and the actual distribution of strategies in this version: Action Equilibrium 10% 15% 15% 15% 15% 15% 15% Experiment 0% 0% 0% 8% 3.5% 3.5% 11% 26% 41% 7% Table 3: The costless iterations version (n 27) The distribution of choices is far from equilibrium, as in the other two versions, while it is very similar to that obtained in the cycle version (probably due to the framing which emphasizes the level-0 strategy). A vast majority of the subjects (85%) chose the strategies corresponding to L0, L1, L2 or L3. According to the subjects explanations, the choices of (by 78% of the subjects) generally involved an iterative process, whereas the choices of (by 15% of the subjects) were arbitrary guesses. Despite the small sample, it is reasonable to conclude that the cost of performing an additional iteration (i.e. losing another certain shekel) is not the reason that subjects do not perform more than three iterations in the other two versions of the game. The results for another variation, which were obtained using a very large sample, are Page 10

11 reported in the next section and provide further support for this conclusion. In that variation, the cost of an iteration is negligible in comparison to the potential bonus. Nevertheless, subjects tended to adopt a very low level of iterative reasoning. 5. The versions In this section, we report on experiments involving variations of the basic version and the cycle version with the following differences: (i) The amounts of shekels were replaced with dollars (the bonus was changed from 20 shekels to 100 dollars), (ii) The experiments were conducted on-line, without monetary incentives, and (iii) The subjects were mostly undergraduate students in various countries who were studying game theory. The didactic website at gametheory.tau.ac.il served as the experimental platform. The site is used by teachers of game theory courses to assign virtual games and decision-theoretical problems to their students. The results obtained at the site are typically similar to those in laboratory experiments with monetary incentives (see Rubinstein (2007)). Our subjects originated from Argentine, Canada, China, Columbia, Denmark, Italy, Korea, the Slovak Republic, Spain, Switzerland and the US. Table 4 presents the mixed strategy equilibria distributions and the experimental results for each of the two versions: Version Equilibrium Basic 55% 9% 8% 7% 6% 5% 4% 3% 2% 1% Cycle 5.5% 14.5% 13.5% 12.5% 11.5% 10.5% 9.5% 8.5% 7.5% 6.5% Experimental results Basic 26% 3% 3% 4% 6% 2% 6% 20% 17% 13% Cycle 15% 4% 3% 1% 3% 3% 2% 11% 34% 24% Table 4: The Basic version (n 666) and the Cycle version (n 186) of the game As in the experiments of the versions, which were conducted with monetary incentives, the majority of subjects in both of the versions reported here are concentrated in Page 11

12 the level-0, level-1, level-2 and level-3 strategies (100, 99, 98, 97). However, there are three main differences: (i) The proportion of subjects who chose the highest number is larger in the on-line experiments. Our conjecture is that the strategy 100 is more salient in this range as is 20 in the range It is also possible that the lack of monetary incentives increased the proportion of subjects who chose the instinctive action. (ii) The proportion of subjects who chose the level-3 strategy was much smaller than in the versions. (iii) In both versions, a significantly higher proportion of subjects chose the lowest possible number (91) as compared to the proportion who chose 11 in the versions. In this population, there were more subjects who are familiar with iterative elimination of dominated strategies and perhaps had been exposed to games such as the Traveler s Dilemma, in which the choice of the lowest number is the unique equilibrium. The choice of 91 may be an outcome of the similarity that they saw (mistakenly) between these games and the games. We do not believe that a subject who chose 91 actually performed nine explicit iterations. It is more likely that he performed a few iterations and then continued the iterative process by induction to what he considered to be the end. Recall, however, that the best response to 91 is the strategy 100. We suspect that in the cycle version many subjects who practiced the open-ended process realized that it does not end at 91 and restarted the process from 100 (since in the cycle version the strategy 100 was described explicitly as a best response to 91). This is consistent with the lower frequency of the strategy 91 in the cycle version as compared to the basic version (15% vs. 26%). We also conducted an on-line experiment (without monetary incentives) of a different version of the money request game in which a subject requests an amount of money in the range [$1,$100] and receives an additional $100 if he requests exactly one dollar less than the other player. The subjects consisted of 135 students in various countries who had studied game theory. The results are presented in Table 5. Action Results 7% 6% 1% 1% 6% 22% 26% 30% Table 5: Behavior in the game (n 135) The vast majority of the subjects (84%) chose one of the four strategies 97, 98, 99 and Page 12

13 100. Only 7% chose the unreasonable strategy 1. The rest (8%) were widely distributed within the range These results provide support for our interpretation of choices in the range in the basic version as reflecting arbitrary guesses rather than high levels of iterative reasoning. If, in contrast to our intuition, the choices in the range (made by 18% of the subjects) in the game reflected between 4 and 8 levels of reasoning, then the strategies should have been just as popular in the game. However, only 2% of the subjects in the version chose those strategies. 6. Conclusion In this short paper, we have presented a simple game that provides an ideal test for the bounds on the depth of iterative reasoning in games. The game is easily understood and the k-level reasoning process is both intuitive and unambiguously specified. Nevertheless, subjects did not use more than three steps of reasoning. We conjecture that the distribution of level-k types in the game can provide an upper bound on the distributions of types in other games. We do not argue that the distribution of types detected here is universal since it is likely to depend on the characteristics of the subjects. However, we do believe that the game reveals the upper distribution of k-level types within a population and can be used to identify the maximum depth of reasoning within the individuals level. To make our case more convincing, we studied several variations of the game and demonstrated that: (1) enhancing the L0 strategy does not increase the use of level-k strategies (for k 0) overall and lowers the levels conditional of using these level-k strategies, and (2) subjects do not use more than 3 steps of reasoning even when the monetary cost of each level of reasoning (for k 0) is the same. Page 13

14 References Arad, Ayala (2009). "The Tennis Coach problem: A Game-Theoretic and Experimental Study", The Foerder Institute for Economic Research, Working Paper no Basu, Kaushik (1994). "The Traveler s Dilemma: Paradoxes of Rationality in Game Theory". American Economic Review, 84, Branas-Garza, Pablo and Maria Paz Espinosa and Pedro Rey-Biel (2009). "Travelers Types" Barcelona Economics Working Paper Series Working Paper no 407. Bosch-Domenech Antoni, Jose G. Montalvo, Rosmerie Nagel and Albert Satorra (2002). One, Two, (Three), Infinity : Newspaper and Lab Beauty-Contest Experiments, American Economic Review, 92, Burchardiy, Konrad B. and Stefan P. Penczynski (2010). "Out Of Your Mind: Estimating The Level-k Model" Working Paper. Camerer, Colin F. Teck-Hua Ho and Juin-Kuan Chong (2004). "Cognitive Hierarchy Model of Games". Quarterly Journal of Economics, 119, Costa-Gomes, Migual. A., Vincent. P. Crawford and Bruno Broseta (2001). "Cognition and Behavior in Normal-Form Games: an Experimental Study". Econometrica, 69, Costa-Gomes, Miguel A. and Vincent P. Crawford (2006). "Cognition and Behavior in Two-Person Guessing Games: An Experimental Study." American Economic Review, 96, Crawford, Vincent and Nagore Iriberri (2007). "Fatal Attraction: Salience, Naivete, and Sophistication in Experimental Hide-and-Seek Games", American Economic Review 97, Kinderman, Peter, Robin Dunbar, and Richard, P. Bentall (1998). "Theory-of-Mind Deficits and Casual Attributions", British Journal of Psychology, 89, Nagel, Rosmarin (1995). "Unraveling in Guessing Games: An Experimental Study". American Economic Review 85, Rubinstein, Ariel (2007). "Instinctive and Cognitive Reasoning: A Study of Response Page 14

15 Times". Economic Journal, 117, Rubinstein, Ariel, Amos Tversky and Dana Heller (1996). "Naive Strategies in Competitive Games". Understanding Strategic Interaction - Essays in Honor of Reinhard Selten, Eds: Albers, W. et al, Springer-Verlag, Rosenthal, Robert. (1981). "Games of Perfect Information, Predatory Pricing, and the Chain Store," Journal of Economic Theory 25, Stahl, Dale O. and Paul W.Wilson (1994). "Experimental Evidence on Players Models of Other Players". Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 25, Stahl, Dale O. and Paul W.Wilson (1995). On Players Models of Other Players: Theory and Experimental Evidence, Games and Economic Behavior, 10, Zunshein, Lisa (forthcoming) : Theory of Mind, Social Hierarchy, and the Emergence of Narrative Subjectivity. The Emergence of Mind: Representations of Consciousness in Narrative Discourse in English, 700 the Present. Ed. David Herman. Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press. Page 15

16 Footnotes 1. The number 20 is also the focal point in the range in the following sense: If two people play a different game, in which each chooses a number in this range and is awarded a prize only if both choose the same number, then clearly they would choose Subjects explanations were classified by a research assistant who otherwise was not involved in the research. The research assistant chose the categories himself. The classification was straightforward and we have also confirmed that we agree with his analysis. 3. Economics students at Tel Aviv University are considered to be fairly sophisticated subjects and one would expect that a different population, with less analytic ability, would tend to use lower levels of iterative reasoning. 4. The upper bound of the 95% confidence interval. 5. Braoas-Garza, Espinosa and Rey-Biel (2009) study a version of the Traveler s Dilemma framed as firms price competition. They analyzed subjects explanations and indeed found that only 30% of the explanations included undercutting arguments, which are in the spirit of the level-k reasoning process (mostly level-1 and in a few cases level-2). Page 16

Volume 30, Issue 3. Boundary and interior equilibria: what drives convergence in a beauty contest'?

Volume 30, Issue 3. Boundary and interior equilibria: what drives convergence in a beauty contest'? Volume 30, Issue 3 Boundary and interior equilibria: what drives convergence in a beauty contest'? Andrea Morone University of Bari & University of Girona Piergiuseppe Morone University of Foggia Abstract

More information

The Tennis Coach Problem: A Game-Theoretic and Experimental Study

The Tennis Coach Problem: A Game-Theoretic and Experimental Study The Tennis Coach Problem: A Game-Theoretic and Experimental Study Ayala Arad Abstract The paper introduces a new allocation game, related to Blotto games: each tennis coach assigns his four different skilled

More information

Strategic Reasoning in Hide and Seek Games: A Note. Timo Heinrich and Irenaeus Wolff

Strategic Reasoning in Hide and Seek Games: A Note. Timo Heinrich and Irenaeus Wolff University of Konstanz Dep artment of Economics Strategic Reasoning in Hide and Seek Games: A Note Timo Heinrich and Irenaeus Wolff Working Paper Series 2012 11 http://www.wiwi.uni konstanz.de/forschung/

More information

Keywords: behavioral game theory, experimental game theory, strategic thinking, level-k models, coordination, salience

Keywords: behavioral game theory, experimental game theory, strategic thinking, level-k models, coordination, salience A Comment on How Portable is Level-0 Behavior? A Test of Level-k Theory in Games with Non-neutral Frames by Heap, Rojo-Arjona, and Sugden Vincent P. Crawford 1 10 July 2014 Abstract: Rubinstein and Tversky

More information

Level-k Thinking in Games with Non-neutral Frames. Vincent P. Crawford September 2018

Level-k Thinking in Games with Non-neutral Frames. Vincent P. Crawford September 2018 Level-k Thinking in Games with Non-neutral Frames Vincent P. Crawford 1 17 September 2018 Abstract: Traditional game theory assumes that if framing does not affect a game s payoffs, it cannot influence

More information

Cognitive Ability in a Team-Play Beauty Contest Game: An Experiment Proposal THESIS

Cognitive Ability in a Team-Play Beauty Contest Game: An Experiment Proposal THESIS Cognitive Ability in a Team-Play Beauty Contest Game: An Experiment Proposal THESIS Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Master of Mathematical Sciences in the Graduate School

More information

Fatal Attraction and Level-k Thinking in Games with Non-neutral Frames. Vincent P. Crawford September 2018; revised 17 October 2018

Fatal Attraction and Level-k Thinking in Games with Non-neutral Frames. Vincent P. Crawford September 2018; revised 17 October 2018 Fatal Attraction and Level-k Thinking in Games with Non-neutral Frames Vincent P. Crawford 1 17 September 2018; revised 17 October 2018 Abstract: Traditional game theory assumes that if framing does not

More information

A Cognitive Model of Strategic Deliberation and Decision Making

A Cognitive Model of Strategic Deliberation and Decision Making A Cognitive Model of Strategic Deliberation and Decision Making Russell Golman (rgolman@andrew.cmu.edu) Carnegie Mellon University, Pittsburgh, PA. Sudeep Bhatia (bhatiasu@sas.upenn.edu) University of

More information

Comparing Models of Strategic Thinking in Van Huyck, Battalio, and Beil s Coordination Games

Comparing Models of Strategic Thinking in Van Huyck, Battalio, and Beil s Coordination Games Comparing Models of Strategic Thinking in Van Huyck, Battalio, and Beil s Coordination Games By Miguel A. Costa-Gomes, Vincent P. Crawford, and Nagore Iriberri 1 Revised 23 August 2008 Abstract: This paper

More information

Irrationality in Game Theory

Irrationality in Game Theory Irrationality in Game Theory Yamin Htun Dec 9, 2005 Abstract The concepts in game theory have been evolving in such a way that existing theories are recasted to apply to problems that previously appeared

More information

Instinctive and Cognitive Reasoning : Response Times Study

Instinctive and Cognitive Reasoning : Response Times Study Instinctive and Cognitive Reasoning : Response Times Study Ariel Rubinstein School of Economics Tel Aviv University Tel Aviv, Israel 69978 and Department of Economics New York University New York, NY 10003

More information

Reasoning about Others Reasoning

Reasoning about Others Reasoning Reasoning about Others Reasoning Larbi Alaoui Antonio Penta December 24, 2017 Abstract Recent experiments suggest that level-k behavior is often driven by subjects beliefs, rather than their binding cognitive

More information

Behavioral Game Theory

Behavioral Game Theory Outline (September 3, 2007) Outline (September 3, 2007) Introduction Outline (September 3, 2007) Introduction Examples of laboratory experiments Outline (September 3, 2007) Introduction Examples of laboratory

More information

Beliefs and Endogenous Cognitive Levels: an Experimental Study

Beliefs and Endogenous Cognitive Levels: an Experimental Study Beliefs and Endogenous Cognitive Levels: an Experimental Study Marina Agranov CESS & Elizabeth Potamites Mathematica Andrew Schotter CESS & California Institute of Technology 111 East Wacker Drive, Suite

More information

On the Evolution of Choice Principles

On the Evolution of Choice Principles On the Evolution of Choice Principles Michael Franke 1 and Paolo Galeazzi 2 1 Department of Linguistics, University of Tübingen 2 Institute for Logic, Language and Computation, Universiteit van Amsterdam

More information

A POPPERIAN TEST OF LEVEL-K THEORY

A POPPERIAN TEST OF LEVEL-K THEORY CBESS Discussion Paper 12-06 A POPPERIAN TEST OF LEVEL-K THEORY By Shaun Hargreaves Heap*, David Rojo Arjona** and Robert Sugden* * School of Economics, University of East Anglia **Economic Science Institute,

More information

A Typology of Players: between Instinctive and Contemplative

A Typology of Players: between Instinctive and Contemplative A Typology of Players: between Instinctive and Contemplative Ariel Rubinstein* Tel Aviv University and New York University First version: July 214 Revision: September 215 Abstract A new typology of players

More information

Behavioral Game Theory

Behavioral Game Theory School of Computer Science, McGill University March 4, 2011 1 2 3 4 5 Outline Nash equilibria One-shot games 1 2 3 4 5 I Nash equilibria One-shot games Definition: A study of actual individual s behaviors

More information

Noisy Introspection in the Game

Noisy Introspection in the Game Noisy Introspection in the 11 20 Game Jacob K. Goeree, Philippos Louis, and Jingjing Zhang February 10, 2014 Abstract Arad and Rubinstein (American Economic Review, 102(7), 2012, 3561 3573) recently proposed

More information

A Comment on the Absent-Minded Driver Paradox*

A Comment on the Absent-Minded Driver Paradox* Ž. GAMES AND ECONOMIC BEHAVIOR 20, 25 30 1997 ARTICLE NO. GA970508 A Comment on the Absent-Minded Driver Paradox* Itzhak Gilboa MEDS KGSM, Northwestern Uni ersity, E anston, Illinois 60201 Piccione and

More information

Some Thoughts on the Principle of Revealed Preference 1

Some Thoughts on the Principle of Revealed Preference 1 Some Thoughts on the Principle of Revealed Preference 1 Ariel Rubinstein School of Economics, Tel Aviv University and Department of Economics, New York University and Yuval Salant Graduate School of Business,

More information

A Typology of Players: between Instinctive and Contemplative

A Typology of Players: between Instinctive and Contemplative A Typology of Players: between Instinctive and Contemplative Ariel Rubinstein* Tel Aviv University and New York University First version: July 24 Revision: February 25 Abstract A new typology of players

More information

The Keynesian Beauty Contest: Economic System, Mind, and Brain

The Keynesian Beauty Contest: Economic System, Mind, and Brain The Keynesian Beauty Contest: Economic System, Mind, and Brain Rosemarie Nagel (ICREA-UPF-BGSE) Felix Mauersberger (University Bonn) Christoph Bühren (University Kassel) Prepared for the Conference on

More information

The Game Prisoners Really Play: Preference Elicitation and the Impact of Communication

The Game Prisoners Really Play: Preference Elicitation and the Impact of Communication The Game Prisoners Really Play: Preference Elicitation and the Impact of Communication Michael Kosfeld University of Zurich Ernst Fehr University of Zurich October 10, 2003 Unfinished version: Please do

More information

Rational Reasoning or Adaptive Behavior?

Rational Reasoning or Adaptive Behavior? Rational Reasoning or Adaptive Behavior? Evidence from Two Person Beauty Contest Games Brit Grosskopf Texas A&M University Rosemarie Nagel Universitat Pompeu Fabra June 2007 Abstract Many experiments have

More information

Koji Kotani International University of Japan. Abstract

Koji Kotani International University of Japan. Abstract Further investigations of framing effects on cooperative choices in a provision point mechanism Koji Kotani International University of Japan Shunsuke Managi Yokohama National University Kenta Tanaka Yokohama

More information

An Experimental Investigation of Self-Serving Biases in an Auditing Trust Game: The Effect of Group Affiliation: Discussion

An Experimental Investigation of Self-Serving Biases in an Auditing Trust Game: The Effect of Group Affiliation: Discussion 1 An Experimental Investigation of Self-Serving Biases in an Auditing Trust Game: The Effect of Group Affiliation: Discussion Shyam Sunder, Yale School of Management P rofessor King has written an interesting

More information

Why do Psychologists Perform Research?

Why do Psychologists Perform Research? PSY 102 1 PSY 102 Understanding and Thinking Critically About Psychological Research Thinking critically about research means knowing the right questions to ask to assess the validity or accuracy of a

More information

Predictive Game Theory* Drew Fudenberg Harvard University

Predictive Game Theory* Drew Fudenberg Harvard University * Drew Fudenberg Harvard University Abstract: Game theory is used in a variety of field inside and outside of social science. The standard methodology is to write down a description of the game and characterize

More information

Clicker quiz: Should the cocaine trade be legalized? (either answer will tell us if you are here or not) 1. yes 2. no

Clicker quiz: Should the cocaine trade be legalized? (either answer will tell us if you are here or not) 1. yes 2. no Clicker quiz: Should the cocaine trade be legalized? (either answer will tell us if you are here or not) 1. yes 2. no Economic Liberalism Summary: Assumptions: self-interest, rationality, individual freedom

More information

Emanuela Carbonara. 31 January University of Bologna - Department of Economics

Emanuela Carbonara. 31 January University of Bologna - Department of Economics Game Theory, Behavior and The Law - I A brief introduction to game theory. Rules of the game and equilibrium concepts. Behavioral Games: Ultimatum and Dictator Games. Entitlement and Framing effects. Emanuela

More information

Testing models with models: The case of game theory. Kevin J.S. Zollman

Testing models with models: The case of game theory. Kevin J.S. Zollman Testing models with models: The case of game theory Kevin J.S. Zollman Traditional picture 1) Find a phenomenon 2) Build a model 3) Analyze the model 4) Test the model against data What is game theory?

More information

Who is Strategic? Daniel T. Knoepfle Uber Muriel Niederle Stanford University, NBER and SIEPR. December 11, 2016

Who is Strategic? Daniel T. Knoepfle Uber Muriel Niederle Stanford University, NBER and SIEPR. December 11, 2016 Who is Strategic? Daniel E. Fragiadakis Texas A&M University Daniel T. Knoepfle Uber Muriel Niederle Stanford University, NBER and SIEPR December 11, 2016 Abstract Behavioral game theory models are important

More information

RES Easter School: Behavioural Economics Brasenose College Oxford, March 2015 Measuring cognition in economic decisions: How and why?

RES Easter School: Behavioural Economics Brasenose College Oxford, March 2015 Measuring cognition in economic decisions: How and why? RES Easter School: Behavioural Economics Brasenose College Oxford, 22-25 March 2015 Measuring cognition in economic decisions: How and why? II: Studying cognition via information search in game experiments

More information

Lecture 2: Learning and Equilibrium Extensive-Form Games

Lecture 2: Learning and Equilibrium Extensive-Form Games Lecture 2: Learning and Equilibrium Extensive-Form Games III. Nash Equilibrium in Extensive Form Games IV. Self-Confirming Equilibrium and Passive Learning V. Learning Off-path Play D. Fudenberg Marshall

More information

Are Behaviours in the Game Well Explained by the level-k Model?

Are Behaviours in the Game Well Explained by the level-k Model? MPRA Munich Personal RePEc Archive Are Behaviours in the 11-20 Game Well Explained by the level-k Model? Lawrence C.Y Choo and Todd R. Kaplan University of Exeter, University of Haifa 9. February 2014

More information

TITLE: MEN ARE FROM MARS, WOMEN FROM VENUS, ONLY WITH INCENTIVES

TITLE: MEN ARE FROM MARS, WOMEN FROM VENUS, ONLY WITH INCENTIVES TITLE: MEN ARE FROM MARS, WOMEN FROM VENUS, ONLY WITH INCENTIVES AUTOR: NOELIA LÓPEZ-MOLINA GRAU: ADMINISTRACIÓ I DIRECCIÓ D EMPRESES - ANGLÈS TUTOR: PEDRO REY-BIEL DATA: MAY 30 th 2015 ABSTRACT This paper

More information

Irrational diversication in multiple decision problems

Irrational diversication in multiple decision problems European Economic Review 46 (2002) 1369 1378 www.elsevier.com/locate/econbase Irrational diversication in multiple decision problems Ariel Rubinstein a;b; a School of Economics, Tel Aviv University, 69978

More information

Jakub Steiner The University of Edinburgh. Abstract

Jakub Steiner The University of Edinburgh. Abstract A trace of anger is enough: on the enforcement of social norms Jakub Steiner The University of Edinburgh Abstract It is well documented that the possibility of punishing free-riders increases contributions

More information

SUPPLEMENTARY INFORMATION

SUPPLEMENTARY INFORMATION Supplementary Statistics and Results This file contains supplementary statistical information and a discussion of the interpretation of the belief effect on the basis of additional data. We also present

More information

Comparative Ignorance and the Ellsberg Paradox

Comparative Ignorance and the Ellsberg Paradox The Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 22:2; 129 139, 2001 2001 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Manufactured in The Netherlands. Comparative Ignorance and the Ellsberg Paradox CLARE CHUA CHOW National University

More information

Sequential Decision and Strategy Vector Methods in Ultimatum Bargaining: Evidence on the Strength of Other- Regarding Behavior

Sequential Decision and Strategy Vector Methods in Ultimatum Bargaining: Evidence on the Strength of Other- Regarding Behavior Department of Economics Discussion Paper 2004-04 Sequential Decision and Strategy Vector Methods in Ultimatum Bargaining: Evidence on the Strength of Other- Regarding Behavior Robert J. Oxoby University

More information

Abhimanyu Khan, Ronald Peeters. Cognitive hierarchies in adaptive play RM/12/007

Abhimanyu Khan, Ronald Peeters. Cognitive hierarchies in adaptive play RM/12/007 Abhimanyu Khan, Ronald Peeters Cognitive hierarchies in adaptive play RM/12/007 Cognitive hierarchies in adaptive play Abhimanyu Khan Ronald Peeters January 2012 Abstract Inspired by the behavior in repeated

More information

Belief Formation in a Signalling Game without Common Prior: An Experiment

Belief Formation in a Signalling Game without Common Prior: An Experiment Belief Formation in a Signalling Game without Common Prior: An Experiment Alex Possajennikov University of Nottingham February 2012 Abstract Using belief elicitation, the paper investigates the formation

More information

Behavioral Game Theory

Behavioral Game Theory Behavioral Game Theory Experiments in Strategic Interaction Colin F. Camerer Russell Sage Foundation, New York, New York Princeton University Press, Princeton, New Jersey Preface Introduction 1.1 What

More information

Epistemic Game Theory

Epistemic Game Theory Epistemic Game Theory Adam Brandenburger J.P. Valles Professor, NYU Stern School of Business Distinguished Professor, NYU Tandon School of Engineering Faculty Director, NYU Shanghai Program on Creativity

More information

Book review: The Calculus of Selfishness, by Karl Sigmund

Book review: The Calculus of Selfishness, by Karl Sigmund Book review: The Calculus of Selfishness, by Karl Sigmund Olle Häggström Leading game theorist Karl Sigmund calls his latest book The Calculus of Selfishness, although arguably The Calculus of Cooperation

More information

Assignment 4: True or Quasi-Experiment

Assignment 4: True or Quasi-Experiment Assignment 4: True or Quasi-Experiment Objectives: After completing this assignment, you will be able to Evaluate when you must use an experiment to answer a research question Develop statistical hypotheses

More information

Dominance-Solvable Games

Dominance-Solvable Games Dominance-Solvable Games Joseph Tao-yi Wang 10/13/2010 Dominance Dominance Strategy A gives you better payoffs than Strategy B regardless of opponent strategy Dominance Solvable A game that can be solved

More information

An Experiment on Intercultural Tacit Coordination - Preliminary Report

An Experiment on Intercultural Tacit Coordination - Preliminary Report MPRA Munich Personal RePEc Archive An Experiment on Intercultural Tacit Coordination - Preliminary Report Pablo Abitbol Witten/Herdecke University, Germany October 2009 Online at http://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/23474/

More information

Towards a Justification the Principle of Coordination

Towards a Justification the Principle of Coordination TI 2000-017/1 Tinbergen Institute Discussion Paper Towards a Justification the Principle of Coordination Maarten C.W. Janssen Tinbergen Institute The Tinbergen Institute is the institute for economic research

More information

Noisy Introspection in the Game

Noisy Introspection in the Game Noisy Introspection in the 11 20 Game Jacob K. Goeree, Philippos Louis, and Jingjing Zhang August 18, 2015 Abstract Previous experiments based on the 11-20 game have produced evidence for the level-k model

More information

Introduction to Game Theory Autonomous Agents and MultiAgent Systems 2015/2016

Introduction to Game Theory Autonomous Agents and MultiAgent Systems 2015/2016 Introduction to Game Theory Autonomous Agents and MultiAgent Systems 2015/2016 Ana Paiva * These slides are based on the book by Prof. M. Woodridge An Introduction to Multiagent Systems and the online

More information

Value Function Elicitation: A Comment on Craig R. Fox & Amos Tversky, "A Belief-Based Account of Decision under Uncertainty"

Value Function Elicitation: A Comment on Craig R. Fox & Amos Tversky, A Belief-Based Account of Decision under Uncertainty Value Function Elicitation: A Comment on Craig R. Fox & Amos Tversky, "A Belief-Based Account of Decision under Uncertainty" Craig R. Fox Peter P. Wakker Fuqua School of Business, Duke University Box 90120,

More information

Introduction to Behavioral Economics Like the subject matter of behavioral economics, this course is divided into two parts:

Introduction to Behavioral Economics Like the subject matter of behavioral economics, this course is divided into two parts: Economics 142: Behavioral Economics Spring 2008 Vincent Crawford (with very large debts to Colin Camerer of Caltech, David Laibson of Harvard, and especially Botond Koszegi and Matthew Rabin of UC Berkeley)

More information

The False Beliefs of Women - How Women Believe Their Male Counterparts to Be Better Than Themselves

The False Beliefs of Women - How Women Believe Their Male Counterparts to Be Better Than Themselves The False Beliefs of Women - How Women Believe Their Male Counterparts Be Better Than Themselves Chrisph Stumm (Chrisph.Stumm@rub.de) January 12 University of Passau Abstract: By conducting a P-Beauty

More information

The effect of decision frame and decision justification on risky choice

The effect of decision frame and decision justification on risky choice Japanese Psychological Research 1993, Vol.35, No.1, 36-40 Short Report The effect of decision frame and decision justification on risky choice KAZUHISA TAKEMURA1 Institute of Socio-Economic Planning, University

More information

Equilibrium Selection In Coordination Games

Equilibrium Selection In Coordination Games Equilibrium Selection In Coordination Games Presenter: Yijia Zhao (yz4k@virginia.edu) September 7, 2005 Overview of Coordination Games A class of symmetric, simultaneous move, complete information games

More information

Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium

Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium Econ 400 University of Notre Dame Econ 400 (ND) Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium 1 / 27 Our last equilibrium concept The last equilibrium concept we ll study after Nash eqm, Subgame

More information

Adjustment Patterns and Equilibrium Selection in Experimental Signaling Games

Adjustment Patterns and Equilibrium Selection in Experimental Signaling Games Adjustment Patterns and Equilibrium Selection in Experimental Signaling Games Jordi Brandts Charles A. Holt ABSTRACT This paper examines the relation between adjustment patterns and equilibrium selection

More information

Recognizing Ambiguity

Recognizing Ambiguity Recognizing Ambiguity How Lack of Information Scares Us Mark Clements Columbia University I. Abstract In this paper, I will examine two different approaches to an experimental decision problem posed by

More information

Self-Serving Assessments of Fairness and Pretrial Bargaining

Self-Serving Assessments of Fairness and Pretrial Bargaining Self-Serving Assessments of Fairness and Pretrial Bargaining George Loewenstein Samuel Issacharoff Colin Camerer and Linda Babcock Journal of Legal Studies 1993 報告人 : 高培儒 20091028 1 1. Introduction Why

More information

Experimental Testing of Intrinsic Preferences for NonInstrumental Information

Experimental Testing of Intrinsic Preferences for NonInstrumental Information Experimental Testing of Intrinsic Preferences for NonInstrumental Information By Kfir Eliaz and Andrew Schotter* The classical model of decision making under uncertainty assumes that decision makers care

More information

Beliefs and (In)Stability in Normal-Form Games

Beliefs and (In)Stability in Normal-Form Games Beliefs and (In)Stability in Normal-Form Games Kyle Hyndman Maastricht University, k.hyndman@maastrichtuniversity.nl, http://www.personeel.unimaas.nl/k-hyndman Antoine Terracol Paris School of Economics

More information

Identifying Predictable Players: Relating Behavioral Types and Subjects with Deterministic Rules

Identifying Predictable Players: Relating Behavioral Types and Subjects with Deterministic Rules Identifying Predictable Players: Relating Behavioral Types and Subjects with Deterministic Rules Daniel E. Fragiadakis Stanford University Daniel T. Knoepfle Stanford University Muriel Niederle Stanford

More information

Games With Incomplete Information: Bayesian Nash Equilibrium

Games With Incomplete Information: Bayesian Nash Equilibrium Games With Incomplete Information: Bayesian Nash Equilibrium Carlos Hurtado Department of Economics University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign hrtdmrt2@illinois.edu June 29th, 2016 C. Hurtado (UIUC - Economics)

More information

thurgauwissenschaft Research Paper Series Thurgau Institute of Econom cs and Department of Economics at the University of Konstanz

thurgauwissenschaft Research Paper Series Thurgau Institute of Econom cs and Department of Economics at the University of Konstanz Research Paper Series Thurgau Institute of Econom cs and Department of Economics at the University of Konstanz Konstanzer Online-Publikations-System (KOPS) URL: http://nbn-resolving.de/urn:nbn:de:bsz:352-0-322043

More information

An Experiment to Evaluate Bayesian Learning of Nash Equilibrium Play

An Experiment to Evaluate Bayesian Learning of Nash Equilibrium Play . An Experiment to Evaluate Bayesian Learning of Nash Equilibrium Play James C. Cox 1, Jason Shachat 2, and Mark Walker 1 1. Department of Economics, University of Arizona 2. Department of Economics, University

More information

Nash Equilibrium and Dynamics

Nash Equilibrium and Dynamics Nash Equilibrium and Dynamics Sergiu Hart September 12, 2008 John F. Nash, Jr., submitted his Ph.D. dissertation entitled Non-Cooperative Games to Princeton University in 1950. Read it 58 years later,

More information

Essays on Behavioral and Experimental Game Theory. Ye Jin. A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the. requirements for the degree of

Essays on Behavioral and Experimental Game Theory. Ye Jin. A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the. requirements for the degree of Essays on Behavioral and Experimental Game Theory by Ye Jin A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Economics in the Graduate Division

More information

Behavioural Economics: Strategic Thinking. University of Oxford, Michaelmas Term 2014

Behavioural Economics: Strategic Thinking. University of Oxford, Michaelmas Term 2014 Behavioural Economics: Strategic Thinking University of Oxford, Michaelmas Term 2014 Vincent P. Crawford, University of Oxford, All Souls College, and University of California, San Diego (with thanks to

More information

CAE Working Paper # Experiments with the Traveler s Dilemma: Welfare, Strategic Choice and Implicit Collusion

CAE Working Paper # Experiments with the Traveler s Dilemma: Welfare, Strategic Choice and Implicit Collusion ISSN 1936-5098 CAE Working Paper #08-07 Experiments with the Traveler s Dilemma: Welfare, Strategic Choice and Implicit Collusion by Kaushik Basu Leonardo Becchetti and Luca Stanca October 2008 Experiments

More information

Unlike standard economics, BE is (most of the time) not based on rst principles, but on observed behavior of real people.

Unlike standard economics, BE is (most of the time) not based on rst principles, but on observed behavior of real people. Behavioral Economics Lecture 1. Introduction and the Methodology of Experimental Economics 1. Introduction Characteristica of Behavioral Economics (BE) Unlike standard economics, BE is (most of the time)

More information

Confidence in Sampling: Why Every Lawyer Needs to Know the Number 384. By John G. McCabe, M.A. and Justin C. Mary

Confidence in Sampling: Why Every Lawyer Needs to Know the Number 384. By John G. McCabe, M.A. and Justin C. Mary Confidence in Sampling: Why Every Lawyer Needs to Know the Number 384 By John G. McCabe, M.A. and Justin C. Mary Both John (john.mccabe.555@gmail.com) and Justin (justin.mary@cgu.edu.) are in Ph.D. programs

More information

Uncertainty about Rationality.

Uncertainty about Rationality. Uncertainty about Rationality. Separating Optimality from Cognitive Ability in Models of Strategic Reasoning Marzena J. Rostek This draft: October 2006 Abstract Uncertainty about the rationality of others

More information

Effects of Sequential Context on Judgments and Decisions in the Prisoner s Dilemma Game

Effects of Sequential Context on Judgments and Decisions in the Prisoner s Dilemma Game Effects of Sequential Context on Judgments and Decisions in the Prisoner s Dilemma Game Ivaylo Vlaev (ivaylo.vlaev@psy.ox.ac.uk) Department of Experimental Psychology, University of Oxford, Oxford, OX1

More information

Non-Equilibrium Play in Centipede Games

Non-Equilibrium Play in Centipede Games Non-Equilibrium Play in Centipede Games Bernardo García-Pola Nagore Iriberri Jaromír Kovářík May 23, 2016 Abstract Centipede games represent a classic example of a strategic situation, where the equilibrium

More information

A Prediction Tournament Paradox

A Prediction Tournament Paradox A Prediction Tournament Paradox David J. Aldous University of California Department of Statistics 367 Evans Hall # 3860 Berkeley CA 94720-3860 https://www.stat.berkeley.edu/ aldous/ February 25, 2018 Abstract

More information

Mutual knowledge rationality among international policy elites

Mutual knowledge rationality among international policy elites Mutual knowledge rationality among international policy elites Brad L. LeVeck Department of Political Science, University of California, Merced, CA, USA correspondence: bleveck@ucmerced.edu In game theoretic

More information

The Evolution of Cooperation: The Genetic Algorithm Applied to Three Normal- Form Games

The Evolution of Cooperation: The Genetic Algorithm Applied to Three Normal- Form Games The Evolution of Cooperation: The Genetic Algorithm Applied to Three Normal- Form Games Scott Cederberg P.O. Box 595 Stanford, CA 949 (65) 497-7776 (cederber@stanford.edu) Abstract The genetic algorithm

More information

Performance in competitive Environments: Gender differences

Performance in competitive Environments: Gender differences Performance in competitive Environments: Gender differences Uri Gneezy Technion and Chicago Business School Muriel Niederle Harvard University Aldo Rustichini University of Minnesota 1 Gender differences

More information

WORKING PAPER SERIES

WORKING PAPER SERIES DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS UNIVERSITY OF MILAN - BICOCCA WORKING PAPER SERIES Experiments with the Traveler's Dilemma: Welfare, Strategic Choice and Implicit Collusion Kaushik Basu, Leonardo Becchetti, Luca

More information

MASSACHUSETTS INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY

MASSACHUSETTS INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY MASSACHUSETTS INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY HARRY DI PEI harrydp@mit.edu OFFICE CONTACT INFORMATION 77 Massachusetts Avenue, E52-301 harrydp@mit.edu http://economics.mit.edu/grad/harrydp MIT PLACEMENT OFFICER

More information

Comments on Neuroeconomics Ariel Rubinstein The University of Tel Aviv Cafes and Department of Economics, New York University

Comments on Neuroeconomics Ariel Rubinstein The University of Tel Aviv Cafes and Department of Economics, New York University Comments on Neuroeconomics Ariel Rubinstein The University of Tel Aviv Cafes and Department of Economics, New York University version: March 27th, 2008 Abstract Neuroeconomics is examined critically using

More information

Topic 3: Social preferences and fairness

Topic 3: Social preferences and fairness Topic 3: Social preferences and fairness Are we perfectly selfish and self-centered? If not, does it affect economic analysis? How to take it into account? Focus: Descriptive analysis Examples Will monitoring

More information

NEW DIRECTIONS FOR POSITIVE ECONOMICS

NEW DIRECTIONS FOR POSITIVE ECONOMICS part iv... NEW DIRECTIONS FOR POSITIVE ECONOMICS... CAPLIN: CHAP10 2008/1/7 15:51 PAGE 247 #1 CAPLIN: CHAP10 2008/1/7 15:51 PAGE 248 #2 chapter 10... LOOK-UPS AS THE WINDOWS OF THE STRATEGIC SOUL... vincent

More information

The Common Priors Assumption: A comment on Bargaining and the Nature of War

The Common Priors Assumption: A comment on Bargaining and the Nature of War The Common Priors Assumption: A comment on Bargaining and the Nature of War Mark Fey Kristopher W. Ramsay June 10, 2005 Abstract In a recent article in the JCR, Smith and Stam (2004) call into question

More information

How financial incentives and cognitive abilities. affect task performance in laboratory settings: an illustration

How financial incentives and cognitive abilities. affect task performance in laboratory settings: an illustration How financial incentives and cognitive abilities affect task performance in laboratory settings: an illustration Ondrej Rydval, Andreas Ortmann CERGE-EI, Prague, Czech Republic April 2004 Abstract Drawing

More information

HOT VS. COLD: SEQUENTIAL RESPONSES AND PREFERENCE STABILITY IN EXPERIMENTAL GAMES * August 1998

HOT VS. COLD: SEQUENTIAL RESPONSES AND PREFERENCE STABILITY IN EXPERIMENTAL GAMES * August 1998 HOT VS. COLD: SEQUENTIAL RESPONSES AND PREFERENCE STABILITY IN EXPERIMENTAL GAMES * August 1998 Jordi Brandts Instituto de Análisis Económico (CSIC) Barcelona and University of California Berkeley (jbrandts@econ.berkeley.edu)

More information

Thoughts on Social Design

Thoughts on Social Design 577 Center for Mathematical Economics Working Papers September 2017 Thoughts on Social Design Walter Trockel and Claus-Jochen Haake Center for Mathematical Economics(IMW) Bielefeld University Universitätsstraße

More information

Using Your Brain -- for a CHANGE Summary. NLPcourses.com

Using Your Brain -- for a CHANGE Summary. NLPcourses.com Using Your Brain -- for a CHANGE Summary NLPcourses.com Table of Contents Using Your Brain -- for a CHANGE by Richard Bandler Summary... 6 Chapter 1 Who s Driving the Bus?... 6 Chapter 2 Running Your Own

More information

Today s lecture. A thought experiment. Topic 3: Social preferences and fairness. Overview readings: Fehr and Fischbacher (2002) Sobel (2005)

Today s lecture. A thought experiment. Topic 3: Social preferences and fairness. Overview readings: Fehr and Fischbacher (2002) Sobel (2005) Topic 3: Social preferences and fairness Are we perfectly selfish? If not, does it affect economic analysis? How to take it into account? Overview readings: Fehr and Fischbacher (2002) Sobel (2005) Today

More information

Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition

Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition Conflict and Bias in Heuristic Judgment Sudeep Bhatia Online First Publication, September 29, 2016. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/xlm0000307

More information

Evaluation Models STUDIES OF DIAGNOSTIC EFFICIENCY

Evaluation Models STUDIES OF DIAGNOSTIC EFFICIENCY 2. Evaluation Model 2 Evaluation Models To understand the strengths and weaknesses of evaluation, one must keep in mind its fundamental purpose: to inform those who make decisions. The inferences drawn

More information

Further Properties of the Priority Rule

Further Properties of the Priority Rule Further Properties of the Priority Rule Michael Strevens Draft of July 2003 Abstract In Strevens (2003), I showed that science s priority system for distributing credit promotes an allocation of labor

More information

Running Head: NARRATIVE COHERENCE AND FIDELITY 1

Running Head: NARRATIVE COHERENCE AND FIDELITY 1 Running Head: NARRATIVE COHERENCE AND FIDELITY 1 Coherence and Fidelity in Fisher s Narrative Paradigm Amy Kuhlman Wheaton College 13 November 2013 NARRATIVE COHERENCE AND FIDELITY 2 Abstract This paper

More information

ULTIMATUM GAME. An Empirical Evidence. Presented By: SHAHID RAZZAQUE

ULTIMATUM GAME. An Empirical Evidence. Presented By: SHAHID RAZZAQUE 1 ULTIMATUM GAME An Empirical Evidence Presented By: SHAHID RAZZAQUE 2 Difference Between Self-Interest, Preference & Social Preference Preference refers to the choices people make & particularly to tradeoffs

More information

Level-k Reasoning in a Generalized Beauty Contest

Level-k Reasoning in a Generalized Beauty Contest Level-k Reasoning in a Generalized Beauty Contest Dmitry Shapiro Xianwen Shi Artie Zillante First Version: October 2009 This Version: March 2014 Abstract We study how the predictive power of level-k models

More information

Multiple Equilibria in Tullock Contests *

Multiple Equilibria in Tullock Contests * Multiple Equilibria in Tullock Contests * Subhasish M. Chowdhury a and Roman M. Sheremeta b a School of Economics, Centre for Competition Policy, and Centre for Behavioral and Experimental Social Science,

More information

Volume 36, Issue 3. David M McEvoy Appalachian State University

Volume 36, Issue 3. David M McEvoy Appalachian State University Volume 36, Issue 3 Loss Aversion and Student Achievement David M McEvoy Appalachian State University Abstract We conduct a field experiment to test if loss aversion behavior can be exploited to improve

More information