Expectations and fairness in a modified Ultimatum game

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Expectations and fairness in a modified Ultimatum game"

Transcription

1 JOURNAL OF ELSEVIER Journal of Economic Psychology 17 (1996) Expectations and fairness in a modified Ultimatum game Ramzi Suleiman * Department of Psvchology Unicersity of Ha~fil. Haifil Israel Received 7 February 1995; revised 10 January 1996 Abstract Non-cooperative game theory predicts that Allocators in Ultimatum games will take almost all the 'cake'. Experimental evidence is in sharp contrast with this prediction, as several experiments show that the modal offer is the even split. Interpretations of such results usually make reference to two competing explanations. One invokes the notion of fairness; the second argues that in the absence of common knowledge of the rationality and beliefs of Recipients, Allocators raise their offers because they expect that non-satisfactory offers might be rejected, Although several experiments have been successful in inducing more selfish offers by manipulating the Allocators' expectations, they have done so predominantly by means of extrinsic manipulations that are not accounted for by game theory. The present study introduces a minor variation of the Ultimatum game by implanting a discounting factor, 6 (0 < 6 < 1), in the standard game. Whereas game theory is indifferent to this modification, experimental results from the modified game show that by continuously changing 6, it is possible to induce systematic changes in Allocators' and Recipients' behaviors and beliefs. These results are used to competitively test the fairness and expectations hypotheses. PsyclNFO classification." 3020 Kevwords: Bargaining: Expectations; Fairness; Ultimatum game * rsps854@uvm.haifa.ac.il, Fax: , Tel.: /96/$15.00 Published by Elsevier Science B.V. PII S (96)

2 532 R. Suleiman / Journal of E~'onomic Psychology 17 (1996) Introduction The standard Ultimatum game can be described as follows: an amount of money, M, is to be divided between two subjects: Player 1 and Player 2. Player 1 is designated the role of the Allocator and Player 2 the role of the Recipient. The Allocator can propose any split of the amount M, say M-x for himself, and x for the Recipient. The Recipient can either accept the offer, in which case the proposed split is implemented, or reject it, in which case both players get nothing. The Ultimatum game is perhaps the simplest strictly competitive game. Like the prisoner's Dilemma, it captures a minimal situation suitable for studying competitive behavior. The prediction of non-cooperative game theory for the Ultimatum game is straightforward. If the two players are rational (in the sense that their utility functions are monotonically increasing), then the Allocator should propose M- e for himself, and e for the Recipient, where e is an infinitesimally small positive number. The Recipient should agree to any amount e, no matter how small, since any e > 0 is better than nothing. In an attempt to test this prediction, Giith et al. (1982) created a situation in which all subjects were seated in one room where they could see one another, but no subject could recognize his/her partner in the dyad. The Allocators' offers and the Recipients' replies (accept/reject) were made by written messages, and all earnings were paid in cash. The results showed that very few behaved in accordance with the game theoretic prediction, and that the modal offer was the equal split. Many subsequent studies tried to gain support for the game-theoretic prediction. Typically, these studies implemented exogenous manipulations designed to motivate Allocators to exploit their strategic advantage. Giith and Tietz (1986) used the second highest price auction (Vickrey, 1961) to determine who wins the Allocator role in a subsequent Ultimatum game. Hoffman et al. (1994) tried to enforce the Allocators' 'property rights' by having subjects win the Allocator's position by scoring high on a general knowledge quiz, and by stressing their property rights through the instructions. Other manipulations for eliciting selfish demands are 'framing' the bargaining situation in economic terms of a 'buyer' and a 'seller', using a double anonymity procedure (Hoffman et al., 1994), and selecting subjects who are motivated to win money (Forsythe et al., 1988). By and large, such manipulations were successful in decreasing both the number of equal split offers and the mean proportion Allocators offered to their Recipients. Nevertheless, they all fell short of validating the game-theoretic prediction. The mean offer in the Giith and Tietz (1986) experiment ranged from

3 R. Suleiman / Journal of Economic Psychology 17 (1996) % for a DM 15 pie, to 35% for a DM 100 pie; and many studies replicated the finding of Giith et al. (1982) that the modal offer was the equal split. (cf. Gtith and Tietz, 1986; Forsythe et al., 1988; Bolle, 1990; Prasnikar and Roth, 1992). One explanation for such results invokes the notion of fairness. Based on experimental results, Kahneman et al. (1986) posit that the major reason for more equitable offers in the first stages of bargaining games can be related to a concern for the Recipients' well-being. To test the relative importance of fairness in explaining the Allocators' behavior in the Ultimatum game, Forsythe et al. (1988) and Hoffman et al. (1994) compared Allocators' offers in the Ultimatum and Dictator games. In the latter game, the Allocator makes his decision on how to split the pie and the game ends. If fairness is the major factor behind equitable allocations, then allocations should be similar in the two games. Results from the two studies cited above showed that this was not the case. Instead, they showed that subjects in the Dictator game play more egoistically, demanding significantly more for themselves. For example, in the Hoffman et al. study, 70% of the Dictator games played under the double anonymity condition ended with the first mover demanding the whole 'cake'. Hoffman et al. (1994) and Harrison and McCabe (1992) strongly reject the fairness explanation. Instead, they posit that non-strategic offers in Ultimatum games are driven primarily by the expectations held by Allocators regarding the reservation values of the Recipients. According to this explanation, a rational Allocator, who cannot assume that the Recipient is rational, might reason that positive but insufficient offers are likely to be rejected. Such reasoning will lead him to offer at least what he believes is the Recipient's reservation value. In the Hoffman et al. (1994) study, expectations were manipulated by stressing the property rights of the Allocators (primarily by having subjects 'win' the Allocator's position). Although successful, this manipulation (and similar ones like the Gfith and Tietz (1986) auctioning procedure) does not allow for a satisfactory degree of control and manipulation of the players' expectations. Such control was more convincingly achieved by Harrison and McCabe (1992), whose subjects played Ultimatum games against automata programmed to play strategically. They were thus able to manipulate the subjects' expectations, and subsequently their behaviors, closer to the game-theoretic prediction. The authors conclude by refuting the fair-share hypothesis and asserting that Allocators do not exploit their strategic advantage because they do not have common knowledge of the rationality, beliefs and motives of other players. Weg and Smith (1993) make an appealing distinction between framing and structural incentives for encouraging greedy behavior in bargaining games. According to this distinction, the auctioning procedure (Giith and Tietz, 1986),

4 534 R. Suleiman / Journal ~[' Eco,omic Psychology 17 (1996) the use of market terminology, the double-anonymity procedure, and the winning of property rights to Allocate (Hoffman et al., 1994) are all examples of framing incentives because they are external to the description of the game. On the other hand, an incentive is structural if it is embedded in the game form. Examples of simple games with structural incentives are the two-period Ultimatum game with discounting proposed by Binmore et al. (1985), and the Weg and Smith (1993) costless two-period games. In the Binmore et al. game, a rejection in the first period extends the game to a second period, during which the players alternate roles and Player 2 offers an allocation of a discounted 'cake'. The discount factor in the Binmore et al. study was 0.25, for which case the game-theoretic solution predicts that Player 1 should propose Player 2 about 25% of the 'cake'. As in many Ultimatum games, the results showed that the modal opening offer in this study was the even split. On the other hand, the results of a follow-up study in which the Recipients of the first study assumed the roles of Allocators showed that the modal opening offer was 25%, as predicted by game theory. Binmore et al. concluded that when faced with a new problem, subjects choose the 'equal division' because it is an 'obvious' and 'acceptable' compromise, and that "such considerations are easily displaced by calculations of strategic advantage, once players fully appreciate the structure of the game" (Binmore et al., 1985, p. 1180). Weg and Smith (1993) devised and tested two modified Ultimatum games, which they call the OneOne and the OneTwo Ultimatum games. The two games are two-period costless games. In the OneOne game, Player 1 is given two opportunities to propose, while in the OneTwo game, the two players alternate playing the Allocator role. A strategic analysis of the OneOne game shows that Player 1 retains his power, and can demand the whole 'cake' for himself, whereas a similar analysis of the OneTwo game shows that Player 2 should get the entire 'cake'. The experimental results of Weg and Smith contrasted sharply with the game-theoretic predictions. The authors concluded by arguing that "as long as one player can veto any offer by the other, shares tend to be more even than is predicted by the standard game-theoretic model" (Weg and Smith, 1993, p. 17). It is worthwhile to stress that although studies that used framing incentives were usually successful in encouraging greedy allocations, this success should not be taken as supportive of the strategic model, because these extrinsic manipulations are not accounted for by game theory. Auctioning the positions (Giith and Tietz, 1986), or winning the property rights to Allocate (Hoffman et al., 1994) involve, by their nature, intervening variables that are extrinsic to the game which are not alluded to by game theory. In contrast, modified games that

5 R. Suleiman / Journal of Economic Psychology 17 (1996) manipulate structural incentives, like the Binmore et al. (1985), and the Weg and Smith (1993) modified Ultimatum games, manipulate structural variables that are accounted for by standard game theory. Therefore the effects of such manipulations seem more appropriate for testing the theory. The present research constitutes an additional effort to understand the behaviors of Allocators and Recipients in the Ultimatum game. Following Weg and Smith (1993), the main objective of this research is to test the hypothesis that the expectations held by Allocators regarding the reservation values of the Recipients, as well as the Recipients' positive reservation values, constitute a 'correct' response to the structure of the game that is not captured by the subgame-perfect equilibrium. A modified ultimatum game, called the 6-Ultimatum game, is proposed and tested in the present study. Section 2 provides a brief description of the new game. Section 3 details the research hypotheses. Section 4 describes the experiment set to test the hypotheses and details its results. Section 5 is a concluding discussion. 2. The 6-Ultimatum game The modified Ultimatum game, which I call the 8-Ultimatum game, could be described as follows: Player 1 is assigned the role of an Allocator of a 'cake' of size M between himself and player 2 (the Recipient). To any offer [M- x, x] stating the Allocator's and Recipient's shares respectively, the Recipient can reply by either accepting or rejecting. If he accepts, the offer is realized. But if he rejects, he imposes the outcomes (M- x)* 8 and x * 8 (for the Allocator and Recipient respectively), where 8 is a commonly known discount factor (0_< 8_< 1). Whereas a rejection results in shrinking the shares of both players by a factor of 6, the relative share allocation x/(m-x) is unaffected by the Recipient's response. This means that although the Recipient has some control over the absolute sizes of the offers, his reply cannot affect the relative allocation. Note that unlike previous structural modifications of the Ultimatum game, the 8-Ultimatum game is a single-period game. Also note that for 6 = 0, the 8-Ultimatum game reduces to the standard Ultimatum game, while for the other extreme, 8 = 1, it reduces to the Dictator game. Thus, the two games can be viewed as special cases constituting the two end points of the continuum of all possible 8-Ultimatum games. The game-theoretic prediction for the &Ultimatum game is straightforward: common knowledge regarding the rationality of both players will lead the

6 536 R. Suleiman / Journal of Economic Psychology 17 (1996) Allocator to demand the whole 'cake' minus an infinitesimally small e (e > 0). The Recipient, being rational, must accept this offer, since a rejection from her side might cause her share to shrink by 6 ( 6 < 1). For the case where 6 = 1, the Recipient will be indifferent between accepting or rejecting any offer. The Allocator in this case is practically a Dictator, and a rejection from the Recipient does not affect the allocation. Although the subgame-perfect equilibrium is indifferent to 6, it makes sense to conjecture that the expectation of the Allocator regarding a Recipient's possible rejection will depend on the latter's efficacy in determining the final allocation, which, in turn, is a function of 6. Specifically, it is reasonable to assume that when playing under low 6 conditions, Allocators will be more afraid to make low offers than when playing under high 6 conditions, and that this fear will cause them to raise their offers. Moreover, it is reasonable to assume that the efficacy of the Recipient (as determined by 6) will influence her level of aspiration regarding what she might consider as an acceptable share, and consequently the probability that she will accept or reject any certain offer. If these conjectures are valid, then by continuously changing ~ one can manipulate the players' expectations, aspiration levels, and behaviors. The conjectures regarding the Allocators' offers are supported by results from previous experiments which compared offers made under the extreme cases of 3 = 0 (standard Ultimatum) and 6 = 1 (Dictator) conditions (Forsythe et al., 1988; Hoffman et al., 1994). It is important to stress that since 6 is a structural factor, any obtained effect will be due to structural incentives that are embedded in the game form. This implies that the confirmation of the above conjectures will call into question the appropriateness of the subgame perfectness for the 8- (and standard) Ultimatum games. 3. Hypotheses Based on the previous analysis, the following hypotheses can be formulated: HI: H2: Allocators' offers in /~-Ultimatum games are inversely related to 8, such that 'strong' Recipients playing under small 6 conditions will receive higher offers than 'weak' Recipients playing under large 6 conditions. Recipients' rates of rejection are inversely related to 6, such that for a certain offer, higher rates will occur under lower 6 conditions and vice versa.

7 R. Suleiman /Journal of Economic Psychology 17 (1996) H3: For the same offers, Allocators will give higher estimates that their offers will be rejected when playing under low 6 conditions (i.e., with a 'strong' Recipient) than under high 6 conditions (i.e., with a 'weak' Recipient). H4: 'Weak' Recipients (playing under higher /~ conditions) will be more satisfied by a certain offer than will 'strong' Recipients (playing under lower 6 conditions). 4. The experiment 4.1. Method Subjects Three hundred subjects, all students at the University of Haifa, participated in the experiment. They all responded by writing their names and telephone numbers on a notice inviting students to participate in an 'economic experiment'. They where told that they could earn as much as NIS 40 (about $13) depending on their performance Equipment A DEC PDP 11/73 computer was used to conduct the experiment. The computer controlled four CRT terminals, each located in a private and soundproof booth. A fifth terminal was used by the experimenter to monitor the experiment Procedure Subjects were invited to the laboratory in groups of four. On arrival, each subject was admitted separately, seated in a booth, and given detailed written instructions (see Appendix A). Special efforts were made to prevent subjects from meeting or even seeing each other before the experiment. Following the arrival of the fourth participant, the computerized experiment started. First, the experimenter made sure that all participants completely understood the game. Then the four participants were randomly paired into two dyads, and in each dyad one participant was randomly ascribed the role of Allocator, and the other the role of Recipient. Each dyad then played a one shot 6-Ultimatum game, for a 'cake' of NIS 40 and one of five 6 values: 6= 0, 0.2, 0.5, 0.8, and 1. Following the Allocator's offer and the Recipient's reply (accept/reject), each participant responded to ten computerized questions.

8 538 R. Suleiman / Journal of Economic Psychology 17 (1996) The questions for the Allocator were: la. What are the chances (in %), in your opinion, that the Recipient will accept the offer? 2a-9a. What is the likelihood that the Recipient would have accepted an offer of NIS x? (with x equalling 2, 4, 6, 8, 10, 12, 15, and 20, for questions 2a to 9a respectively). 10a. If you were in the Recipient's place, what amount you would have wanted to be offered? The questions for the Recipient were: lr. How satisfied are you (on a scale of 1-10) by the offer that was made to you? 2r-9r. How satisfied you would have been if the Allocator was to offer you NIS y? (with y equalling 20, 15, 12, 10, 8, 6, 4, and 2, for questions 2r to 9r respectively). 10r. If you were in the Allocator's place, what is the amount in NIS that you would have offered the other participant? Thirty dyads were randomly assigned to each one of the five 6 conditions, for a total of 150 dyads. When the experiment ended, each participant was informed via the CRT about his or her earnings. All participants were requested to wait patiently for the experimenter, who then paid each one in his or her booth, and released him or her from the laboratory. Care was taken that participants be sent out one at a time, thus preventing them from meeting after the experiment Results Analysis of the Allocators' offers HI predicted that Allocators' offers will decrease with 6. Fig. 1 depicts the frequency distributions of the offers under the five 6 conditions. The dark segments of the bars in each panel of Fig. 1 represent accepted offers, while the shaded segments represent rejected ones. As the panels show, the modal offer under all 6 conditions is NIS 20, the split. The percentages of Allocators who offered their counterparts at least 50% of the 'cake' were 54%, 60%, 54%, 34%, and 30% under 6 conditions 0, 0.2, 0.5, 0.8 and 1 respectively. Note that while for 6 = 0 and ~ = 0.2 no offers were made that were below NIS 5, there were several zero and below NIS 5 offers for = 0.5, 0.8 and As shown, almost all zero and very small offers in the

9 R. Suleiman / Journal of Economic Psychology 17 (1996) a=o0 6=02 ~ Rejected =Accepted] fg ~.,0I 6 'T i+~... =.I. Offer (NIS) I t2 ~o~! ml,,i,~.~+ ~,m, 0,, ~[~,,,I......, t6 1; 1~ Offer (NIS) I 6=05 5=08 is,- 14 lz ~-, r. '" e t O 22 Offer (NIS) ~=10 l,,,,,.,,... I,, 1 2 G G 1/; 18 1~ 2o 22 Offer (NIS) IS e 4 2 O Offer (NIS) Fig. 1. The frequency distributions of offers under each 6 condition. = 0.5 and 6 = 0.8 conditions were rejected. (No rejections could be made at the 6 = 1 condition, since this is a Dictator game.) A quantitative comparison among all five pairs of distributions in Fig. 1 was

10 540 R. Suleiman / Journal of Economic Psychology 17 (1996) ~ m+ + 15i... :: C m 14~ ;\ ; 13~.~ ~.~] I Condition Fig. 2. Mean offers as a function of 6. performed using the Kalmagorov-Smirnov test. The comparisons revealed significant differences (p = 0.05) between each of the two distributions corresponding to offers under smallest 6 conditions (6 = 0 and 6 = 0.2) and the distribution under the 6 = 0.8 condition. When tested under a significance level of p = 0.1 (instead of 0.05), the two smallest 6 distributions are also significantly different from the distribution corresponding to 6 = 1. Fig. 2 depicts the mean offer as a function of 3. Although Fig. 2 looks somewhat like an inverse s-shaped function, its main tendency is supportive of H1. Notwithstanding the violations at both ends of the graph, the mean offer exhibits a noticeable decrease as 6 increases from 0.2 to 0.5, and then to 0.8. The mean offers for the five 6 conditions 0, 0.2, 0.5, 0.8, 1 are NIS 16.70, 17.03, 13.47, 10.77, and respectively. A one-way ANOVA on the offers with 6 as the independent variable revealed a significant effect (F(4,145) = 5.24, p < 0.01). A Student-Newman- Keuls test revealed significant differences between each of the mean offers for the lowest 3 conditions (6 = 0 and 6 = 0.2) on one hand, and the mean offers for the two highest 6 conditions (6 = 0.8 and 6 = 1). It is interesting to note that the mean proportion offered under the standard Ultimatum condition (3 = 0) is 16.7/40 = , an almost identical result to the one reported by Giith et al. (1982), who reported a mean offer to Recipients of It is also very close to the results obtained by Kahneman et al. (1986) of 0.476, 0.447, and 0.421, for the Psych/Psych, Psych/Commerce, and Commerce/Psych conditions respectively. Hence, the robustness of the mean offer result is shown to hold under a variety of designs, 'cake' sizes, and cultural backgrounds.

11 R. Suleiman / Journal of Economic Psychology 17 (1996) Analysis of the Recipients' replies Table 1 summarizes the rejection rates (number of rejections divided by number of offers) by condition, 6, and size of offer, x, in NIS. For the sake of convenience, the offers are grouped in categories of NIS 3 each, except for the last category, which includes all rejections for offers of NIS 12 or more. H2 predicted that for a given offer, higher rates of rejection will occur under lower 6 conditions. Unfortunately, the rejections data do not allow this hypothesis to be tested, because no small offers were made under low 6 conditions. The results presented in Table 1 show that the overall rejection rate for a -- 0 is only about 7%, a result quite similar to the 8.3% reported by Hoffman et al. (1994) under the random condition. As 6 increases, the rejection rate increases monotonically, reaching a relatively high rate of about 37% under the 6 = 0.8 condition. A chi-square test on the frequencies of rejections resulted in the rejection of the null hypothesis stating that the rejections are evenly distributed across the 6 conditions (X2(3)= 10.4, p < 0.05). A simple examination of Table 1 (or Fig. 1, middle panels) shows that the high rejection rates at the two largest 6 values (0.5 and 0.8) occurred for relatively small offers, in the range of 0-2. Two complementary explanations may account for this result. First, one can argue that Allocators erroneously expected that Recipients would recognize their 'weak' position and accept very small offers. Second, one can argue that Allocators were not seriously concerned by the possibility that Recipients would reject small or even zero offers, since this would still leave them with a considerable amount of the 'cake'. This is especially true for the 'almost Dictator' condition at 6 = 0.8, under which an almost certain rejection of a zero offer resulted in a reduction of the Allocator's maximal gain by only NIS 8. A highly self-interested and risk-averse individual may be willing to pay that price for the 'riskless option' of offering zero to the Recipient (and expecting certain Table 1 Rejection rates by condition (6) and size of offer (x) Offer (x) (NIS) Condition (6) Overall /0 0/0 6/7 8/8 14/15 (93%) / 1 0/0 0/0 1/3 2/4 (50%) 6-8 0/1 1 / 1 0/0 0/0 1/2 (50%) /3 2/4 2/4 2/6 6/17 (35%) /25 1/25 1/19 0/13 3/82 (4%) Overall 2/30 4/30 9/30 11/30 26/50 (17%) (7%) (13%) (30%) (37%)

12 542 R. Suleiman / Journal ~" Economic Psychology 17 (1996) rejection), rather than allocating more fairly while incurring the risk that such offers may still be rejected. The first explanation, alluding to faulty expectations, is partially supported by the estimates data analyzed in the following section, but it seems less likely for the case of zero offers, which constitute the bulk of rejected offers as can be seen from Fig Analysis of Players' estimates Question 10a elicited the Allocator's aspired demand (AD) from the 'cake', had he been in the Recipient's place, and Question 10r elicited the Recipient's hypothetical offer (RO) to his counterpart had he played the role of the Allocator. Table 2 depicts the means and standard deviations of AD, RO, and the actual offer x, for each 6 condition and across conditions. The table shows that although the means of the Allocator's demand (AD) and the Recipient's hypothetical offer (RO) exhibit some tendency to decrease with 6, this tendency is considerably less than the decrease in the actual offers. The results of two separate one-way analyses of variance for AD and RO showed that the effect of 3 on the means of AD and RO was not significant (p > 0.1). The Pearson correlation coefficients between x and RO, and between AD and RO, were zero. The Pearson correlation between x and AD was It seems that although there was some consistency between Allocators' offers and their expectations regarding how much they would expect to get as Recipients, they aspired that they would be treated more fairly than they actually treated their counterparts. This is especially evident in conditions ~ = 0.8 and 1, under which the Recipient can barely influence the final allocation. In the same line, the Recipients' 'generous' hypothetical offers (RO's) under all 6 conditions do not seem highly credible when compared with actual offers. Question 1 to the Allocator asked her to estimate the likelihood (in %) that the Recipient would accept her offer, and Question 1 to the Recipient asked her Table 2 Means (and standard deviations) of Allocators' aspired demands and Recipients' hypothetical offers Condition ( 6 ) Overall Offer (x) (4.47) (4.07) (8.02) (8.05) (4.46) (7.07) Allocator's aspired demand (AD) (3.52) (3.95) (7.06) (8.63) (7.92) (6.59) Recipient's hypothetical offer (RO) (5.85) (5.28) (6.11) (8.95) (7.31) (6.88)

13 R. Suleiman / Journal of Economic Psychology 17 (1996) to state her level of satisfaction (on a 1-10 scale) with the offer she received. Table 3 summarizes the means and standard deviations of the Allocators' Estimates of Acceptance (EA), and the Recipients' Levels of Satisfaction (LS) for each 6 condition, and across conditions. In addition to total means, the table details separate results for accepted and for rejected offers. The total means for the Estimates of Acceptance (EA) show that on average, the Allocator's estimate that the Recipient will accept her offer decreases as 6 increases. This is quite consistent with the decrease in the mean offer. The Pearson correlation coefficient between the Allocator's offers and her estimates of acceptance is.59 (0.53 and 0.59 for accepted and rejected offers, respectively). A comparison of the overall mean Estimates of Acceptance for accepted and rejected offers (82.6% and 55.6%, respectively) indicates that, to some degree, Allocators were able to predict their counterparts' replies. To test the above observations, a 4 X 2 MANOVA was performed on EA, with ~ and the Recipient's reply (accept/reject) as independent factors. The analysis revealed two significant main effects (F(3,112) = 3.36, p < 0.05, and F(1,112) = 15.75, p < 0.01 for 3 and the reply respectively). The interaction between the two variables was not significant (F(3,112) = 1.11, p > 0.1). A Student-Newman-Keuls test for comparison between the means revealed significant differences between each of the Estimate of Acceptance means corresponding to the two lowest 6 (6 = 0 and 8 = 0.2) and the two Estimates of Table 3 Means (and standard deviations) of Allocators' estimates of acceptance and Recipients' levels of satisfaction Condition ( 6 ) Overall Allocator estimate of acceptance (EA) in % Accepted offers ] a 85.5[26] ] ] Rejected offers 85.0 [2] 71.3 [4] 47.1 [9] 51.6 [11] Total (16.7) b (18.8) (33.5) (35.4) (28.1) Recipient let,el of satisfaction (LS) (Scale 0 10) Accepted offers 7.1 [ [26] 7.9 [21] 6.6 [191 - Rejected offers 1.5 [2] 1.0 [4] 1.4 [9] 0.6 [11] - Total (3.3) (3.2) (4.2) (3.9) (3.9) The figures in brackets indicate frequencies of accepted or rejected offers. b The figures in parentheses are standard deviations. 7.4 (2.9) 3.0 (3.6) 5.8 (3.8)

14 544 R. Suleiman / Journal of Economic Psychology 17 (1996) Acceptance corresponding to the higher 6 values ( 6 = 0.5 and 6 = 0.8). Recall that a similar significance pattern was found between the mean offers. Turning to the Recipients' mean Level of Satisfaction (LS), it is immediately noticeable that they rank in exactly the same order as the mean offers. The Pearson correlation coefficient between the Level of Satisfaction and the offer is 0.88 (0.86 for accepted offers and 0.82 for rejected offers). A $ by Recipient's reply MANOVA revealed a significant effect for the reply (accept/reject) (F(1,141) = 81.31, p < 0.01), as well as for 6 (F(4,141) = 4.71 p < 0.01). The interaction between the two variables was not significant (F < 1). The comparison between mean Levels of Satisfaction (LS) for the various 6 conditions using the Student-Newman-Keuls test revealed significant differences between the Level of Satisfaction means corresponding to 6 = 0 and 6 = 0.2, and the means corresponding to 6 = 0.8, and 6 = 1. The picture emerging from the analysis of Allocators' Estimates of Acceptance and the Recipients' Levels of Satisfaction is fairly simple. Under the larger 8 conditions, Allocators offer, on average, smaller portions of the 'cake' and consistently report lower likelihoods that their offers will be accepted. These estimates are quite consistent with the Recipients' Levels of Satisfaction. I turn now to summarizing data from questions 2a to 9a, concerning the Allocators' estimates that the Recipients will accept each one of eight hypothetical offers in the range 2-20, and from questions 2r to 9r, concerning the Recipients' self-reported Levels of Satisfaction with the same offers. Fig. 3 depicts, for each ~ condition, the means of the Allocators' Estimates of Acceptance for Hypothetical Offers (EAHO) as a function of the Hypothetical 100~... ~ ~ 60-0 m E 3o!/ ii ~ J~- 1 t~ lo! o!! Size of hypothtical offer (NIS) Fig. 3. Means of Allocators' estimates of acceptance for each ~ condition, as a function of hypothetical offers.

15 R. Suleiman / Journal of Economic Psychology 17 (1996) _=_ C 0.2 o 0.5 ~ 0.8 ~ 1.0 "i i Size of hypothetical offer (NIS) Fig. 4. Means of Recipients' level of satisfaction for each ~ condition, as a function of hypothetical offers. Offer Size (HO), and Fig. 4 depicts the means of the Recipients' Levels of Satisfaction with the same offers (LSHO). Fig. 3 clearly shows that the mean Estimate of Acceptance for Hypothetical Offers (EAHO) for ~ = 0.8 is noticeably larger than the corresponding mean EAHO obtained under the remaining 6 conditions. A 6 X Hypothetical Offer 4 X 8 analysis of variance on EAHO, with 6 as a between subject condition, and Hypothetical Offer as a within subject condition, revealed a significant effect for 6, in addition to the obvious main effects for HO (F(3,116)= 3.76, p < 0.01, and F(7,812) = , p < 0.01 respectively). The interaction between these two factors was also significant (F(21,812)= 2.35, p < 0.05). A comparison between EAHO means for the different ~ conditions using the Neuman-Keuls method showed that the mean EAHO for 6 = 0.8 is significantly higher (p = 0.05) than the mean EAHOs for the other three 6 conditions (6 = 0.0, 0.2, and 0.5). Separate comparisons for each one of the eight hypothetical offer values replicated the above finding for Hypothetical Offer values NIS 2, 4, 6, and 8. For Hypothetical Offer values NIS 10 and NIS 12, the comparisons revealed a significant difference between the mean EAHO for 6 = 0.8 and the mean EAHOs for 6 = 0.2 and 0.5, but not for the differences between the means for 6 = 0.8 and 6 = 0.0. All other differences were not significant. A similar analysis conducted on the Recipients' Levels of Satisfaction with Hypothetical Offers (LSHO) revealed a significant effect for the hypothetical offer, as expected (F(7,1015) = , p < 0.01). On the other hand, the effect of 6 was barely significant (F(4,145)= 2.15, p < 0.07), and the interaction

16 546 R. Suleiman / Journal of Economic Psychology 17 (1996) between these two factors was not significant (F(28,1015) , p > 0.1). Separate comparisons for each one of the eight Hypothetical Offer values (despite the non-significant interaction), revealed a significant difference at HO = NIS 8 between the Recipient's mean Level of Satisfaction at 3 = 1 and the corresponding means obtained at t5 = 0.2 and ~ = 0.5. Another significant difference emerged for HO = NIS 10 between the mean LSHO at 6 = 1 and the corresponding means obtained at 6 = 0.0, 0.2, and 0.5. The results of the above analysis are only partially supportive of H3 and H4. The prediction that compared to Allocators playing under low 6 conditions, Allocators playing under high 6 conditions would estimate that Recipients would be more accepting of a certain offer received partial support. Specifically, this prediction held true only for the comparison of the estimates given by Allocators playing under the 6 = 0.8 condition with the estimates of Allocators playing under all the lower ~ conditions. Similarly, only Recipients playing under the t5 = 1 (Dictator) condition, and to some extent Recipients playing under the ~ = 0.8 condition, reported Levels of Satisfaction that were significantly higher than the Levels of Satisfaction reported by Recipients playing under smaller ~ conditions. 5. Discussion Studies of Ultimatum games make reference to three major hypotheses: the game-theoretic hypothesis predicting that the Allocator will behave strategically and demand the whole 'cake' for himself; the fair-share hypothesis predicting that the Allocator will split the 'cake' equally between himself and the Recipient; and the 'expectations' hypothesis predicting that the Allocator will base his behavior on his expectations and common knowledge regarding likely responses by the Recipient. Giith and Tietz (1986), and more recently Hoffman et al. (1994) have shown that equitable or 'fair' offers can be significantly reduced by asserting the property rights of the Allocators. Based on their results, Hoffman et al. concluded that the Allocators' offers are "due to strategic and expectations considerations" (Hoffman et al., 1994, p. 346). It is argued here that in spite of the success of property rights manipulations in inducing more strategic offers, their appropriateness for testing noncooperative game theory predictions regarding Allocators' offers is questionable. As noted by Hoffman et al., "noncooperative, nonrepeated game theory is about strangers with no shared history... they meet, interact strategically in their individual self-interest according to well-specified rules and payoffs, and never meet again. These stark conditions

17 R. Suleiman / Journal of Economic Psychology 17 (1996) are necessary to assure that the noncooperative, nonrepeated game theoretic prediction for the interaction is not part of a sequence with a past and a future" (Hoffman et al., 1994, p. 347). With this in mind, it seems reasonable to assume that property rights manipulations violate these conditions, since they inevitably introduce some form of 'history' to the players' relationships even when the game is played once and the players remain completely anonymous to each other. Property rights manipulations are also inappropriate for testing the expectations hypothesis regarding the Allocators' offers in standard Ultimatum games. This is due to the fact that the establishment of the first mover property right requires that both players update their aspiration levels, and consequently their expectations, in favor of the right holder. As such, property rights manipulations induce different expectations than those derived intrinsically from the structure of the game. The modified ultimatum game implemented in the present study overcomes the two shortcomings of property rights manipulations. The 6 parameter introduced to the game constitutes a mere structural modification that does not violate the basic assumptions of noncooperative game theory. Not only does this modification not impose any 'history' or future on the game form, but it also enables to manipulate the Allocators' expectations intrinsically, thus allowing a more appropriate test of the expectations hypothesis. The results of the present study strongly refute the prediction of the noncooperative game theoretical model, and add evidence to a considerable body of research that clearly shows that the standard strategic model simply does not work. Allocators offered substantial portions of the 'cake' under all 3 conditions and their offers were strongly dependent on the size of 3, all in contrast to the game-theoretic prediction of practically zero offers under all 6 conditions. As in many previous studies (Giith and Tietz, 1986; Forsythe et al., 1988; Bolle, 1990; Carter and Irons, 1991; Prasnikar and Roth, 1992), the modal allocation in the present study was the split under all 6 conditions. The mean proportional offer for the standard Ultimatum condition was about 42% of the 'cake', a result that seems quite stable across various experimental conditions (Gtith et al., 1982; Kahneman et al., 1986; Bolle, 1990). Although these results can be taken as supportive of a fairness explanation, a careful examination of the results raises at least two reservations regarding such a conclusion. First, note that although the equal split was the modal offer for all 6 conditions, the percentage of Allocators who offered an even split decreased significantly with 6 (from 54% for 6 = 0.0 and /~ = 0.5, and 60% for 6 = 0.2 to 34% for 6 = 0.8 and 30% for 6 = 1). If fairness alone were the motive behind such offers, then the percentage of Allocators offering even splits should be

18 548 R. Suleiman / Journal c~]" Economic Psychology 17 (1996) invariant with 6. Secondly, although Allocators playing under conditions 6 = 0.0 and 0.2 made no offers below NIS 5 (12.5% of the 'cake'), many offers made under higher 6 conditions were zero or very small (7 (23%) for 6 = 0.5 and = 1, and 8 (27%) for ~ = 0.8). This indicates that when playing with 'weak' Recipients, with whom Allocators do not have to fear the consequences of rejection, a substantial number of Allocators showed no benevolence at all. Notwithstanding the fact that norms of fairness cannot be ruled out as an explanation, most of the results of the present study seem to favor an 'expectations' explanation for the Allocators' offers. As indicated earlier, the results clearly show that the Allocators' mean offers, as well as the percentage of Allocators who offered equal splits, were strongly related to 6. Although less conclusive, the analysis of the Levels of Satisfaction with Hypothetical Offers (LSHO) adds support to the expectations hypothesis by showing that Allocators predicted that Recipients playing under the ~ = 0.8 conditions would be more satisfied with a certain offer than would Recipients playing under smaller 6 conditions (see Fig. 3). The results of the Recipients' Levels of Satisfaction from Hypothetical Offers were partially supportive of H4, that predicted that 'weak' Recipients playing under higher ~ conditions would be more satisfied by a certain offer than would 'strong' Recipients playing under lower 6 conditions. Unlike the data from the Allocators' offers, the Recipients' data were insufficient for a satisfactory analysis of their behavior, especially for testing the hypothesis regarding the inverse relationship between their rejection rates and 6. The results in Table 2 show that the highest number of rejections (14 out of 26) occurred for very small offers in the range 0-2 NIS, and under high 6 conditions (0.5 and 0.8). It is reasonable to assume that even 'weak' Recipients playing under these conditions were willing to pay the relatively low cost of one or two NIS in order to punish 'unfair' Allocators who offered them almost nothing. The second highest number of rejections occurred for offers in the range 9-11 NIS (see Table 2) but their small number and the corresponding pattern of rejection rates across the 6 conditions make it hard to use this data to explain the Recipients' behaviors. Taken together, it seems fair to conclude that the picture emerging from the Recipients' results remains largely unclear, and certainly insufficient for the understanding of Recipients' behaviors in ultimatum situations. An important question related to Allocators' behaviors in ultimatum and other resource allocation situations concerns the issue of fairness. A frequently voiced stand in this respect posits that what might look like a fairness-driven offer in ultimatum situations is not necessarily so. In support of this position, Harrison

19 R. Suleiman / Journal of Economic Psychology 17 (1996) and McCabe (1992) provide an interesting analysis of data from Carter and Irons (1991) study. This analysis suggests that rational and self interested Allocators may choose to make fair allocations not because of cooperative or altruistic motives, but out of pure egoistic ones. In the Carter and Irons study, subjects were requested to enter strategies for both an Allocator and a Recipient, and the designation of roles actually played was made after all strategies were submitted. The allocation was made by randomly pairing the subjects, and then letting the winner of a word-game be the Allocator. Based on these data, Harrison and McCabe computed the Allocators' expected payoffs from demanding 100%, 90%, 80%, 60%, or 50% of the 'cake'. Their results showed that an expected payoff maximizer should choose the 50% (equal) split. Another convincing evidence in this respect was given by Kravitz and Gunto (1992) who conducted two experiments designed to study the replies and expectations of Recipients in a one-shot standard Ultimatum game. Their study contained a pre-test question that elicited the minimum acceptable offer by each subject. The authors used the cumulative distribution of the minimum acceptable offers to calculate the expected value for the Allocator from each possible offer between $0.5 and $2.5. The resulting expected value function shows that the optimal offer guaranteeing a maximal EV to the Allocator is $2 (40% of the entire cake), a size that is not far from the equal split. Yet when the subjects were asked what offers they would make if they knew the other would accept anything greater than zero, only 11% said they would offer at least an even share. The modal response (42%) was 1 cent. The authors conclude by quoting from Walster et al. (1973) that "so long as individuals perceive that they can maximize their outcomes by behaving equitably, they will do so, should they perceive that they can maximize their outcomes by behaving inequitably, they will do so" (Walster et al., 1973, p. 153). Did Allocators in the present study try to maximize their expected payoff? And if so, can a maximization of expected payoff model account for even splits as well? To answer both questions, I first computed for each Allocator the prediction of a Subjective Expected Values (SEV) model. Each Allocator's estimates for the likelihood that the Recipient would accept each one of several hypothetical offers (see questions 2a-9a 1) was used to calculate his respective expected payoffs. The SEV model prediction was chosen as the offer that yields i In addition to the expected values for the offers NIS 2, 4, 6, 8, 10, 12, 15, and 20, the expected value for a zero offer was also calculated, under the reasonable assumption that such an offer would be rejected with certainty.

20 550 R. Suleiman / Journal g/" Economic Psychology 17 (1996) Table 4 Frequencies of correct predictions by the SEV and FS models for each 6 condition Model Condition ( 6 ) SEV 19 (15) 15 (13) 12 (9) 8 (5) - 63% 50c/~ 40% 27% FS 17 (15) 18 (18) 16 (16) 10 (10) 10 (9) 57% 60c~ 53% 33% 33% SEV and FS 12 (11) 12 (12) 4 (4) 0 (0) - 40% 40cA 13 % 0% Neither SEV nor FS 6 ( 11 ) 9 ( I 1 ) 6 (9) 12 (15) - 20% % 40% Total % 100'/, 100% 100% 100% the highest expected value. Table 4 summarizes the results of the SEV model predictions, and contrasts them with the predictions of a simple Fair-Share (FS) model. Each entry with no brackets indicates the number of Allocators for whom the prediction of the respective model(s) was accurate up to a NIS 2 deviation (5% of the entire 'cake') from the actual offer. The corresponding numbers within the brackets, when appearing, give the results of accurate point predictions. The first two rows give the results of correct predictions for the SEV model and the FS model respectively. The third row gives the numbers of Allocators for whom both models gave correct predictions, and the fourth row presents numbers of Allocators for whom neither model yielded correct predictions. An examination of Table 4 shows that both models perform fairly well for most 6 conditions. The percentages of correct prediction of the SEV model are 63%, 50%, 40%, and 27%, for conditions 6 = 0.0, 0.2, 0.5, and 0.8 respectively, while the predicted percentages for the Fair-Share model are 57%, 60%, 53%, 33%, and 33% for conditions 6 = 0.0, 0.2, 0.5, 0.8, and 1 respectively. More interesting are the results for joint correct predictions. These results show that for the standard Ultimatum game (6 = 0), 40% of the offers (12 out of 30) are correctly predicted by each of the two models. One way to interpret this result is that 71% (12 out of 17) of the split offers are also optimal in that they maximize the Allocator's SEV. A similar conclusion applies to the 'near Ultimatum' (8 = 0.2) condition (see Table 4). For the mid-range case of 6 = 0.5, only 13% (4 out of 30) of the offers are jointly predicted by the two models. These constitute only 25% of the splits. The cell corresponding

21 R. Suleiman / Journal of Economic Psychology 17 (1996) to joint prediction for the 'near Dictator' case (6 = 0.8) is empty. Nevertheless, under this condition a sizable minority of 33% (more than the number of SEV maximizers) offered a split. Not surprisingly, an identical proportion of Allocators offered the split under the Dictator condition. Based on the above analysis it seems reasonable to conclude, like Harrison and McCabe (1992), and Kravitz and Gunto (1992), that when playing with a 'strong' recipient (under small 6 condition), the likelihood that unfair offers will be rejected caused many allocators to offer the split, and that most of them did so not only because this was the fair thing to do, but also, and maybe primarily, because it paid to do so. On the other hand, the 'near Dictator' condition provided clear evidence that a sizable minority split the 'cake' fairly, even when as rational payoff maximizers they could do much better. Although nonequilibruim 'fair' offers can be explained as rational self-interested behaviors by Allocators who fear that Recipients might reject relatively small offers, Recipients' concerns for fairness may stem from completely different motives. Based on a series of ultimatum experiments, Murnighan and Pillutla (1995) concluded that the reasons for nonequilibrium replies are essentially not strategic, but rather psychological and moral. The results of the present study do not allow a deep analysis of Recipients' motives. They do, however, show (a) that Allocators expected to be treated more fairly (if they were to play as Recipients) than they actually treated their counterparts, and (b) that Recipients report that they would be 'generous' if they were to play as Allocators. Both of these results are consistent with Murnighan and Pillutla's conclusions. Notwithstanding the advantages of the 6-Ultimatum game alluded to before, the game suffers from at least one methodological disadvantage. As implemented in this study, both the efficacy of a Recipient (i.e. his 'power' to affect the Allocator's outcome if he chooses to reject the latter's offer) and his personal cost in doing so, are determined by the same parameter. Under the 6 conditions tested in this study, a Recipient could inflict a higher loss on the Allocator under ~ = 0 than under ~ = 0.2, but contingently, his personal loss would be higher under 6 = 0 than under 6 = 0.2. A rational Allocator might recognize this dependency and feel less threatened by his Recipient when playing under the 6 = 0 than under the condition. Although not significant, the mean offers for 6 = 0 and 6 = 0.2 (see Fig. 2) are consistent with such reasoning. An improved variant of the 6-Ultimatum game is easily obtained by ascribing different 6 values (61, 62) for the two players. Such improvement allows for separation of the Recipient's potential 'threat' to reject an offer from the personal cost that he incurs if he chooses to do so.

22 552 R. Suleiman / Journal of Economic Psychology 17 (1996) Acknowledgements This research was supported by research grant SES from NSF. I wish to thank Orly Kloner and Irk Bach for their assistance in data collection and Yuval Samid for his help in the data analysis. I also wish to thank David Boninger, David V. Budescu, Faith Gleicher, David Messick, Sam Rackover, Larry Samuelson and two anonymous reviewers for their helpful remarks. Appendix A. Instructions (A) The following are the instructions for the ~ = 0.5 condition. The instructions for the 6 = 0.0, 0.2, and 0.8 conditions are identical, except for the value of 8. You are about to participate in an economics experiment which involves only two persons. In addition to you, there are three other participants in the adjacent booths. You will be randomly paired to only one of them. The remaining two will participate in an experiment that will run parallel to the one that you will participate in. This arrangement was adopted so that no one of the four participants will be able to tell who his partner is. In other words, you will not be able to know who out of the three others is your partner for the experiment. Also your partner for the experiment will not be able to know who you are. The experiment will be conducted as follows: a sum of NIS 40 will be allocated to each pair, and one of the two participants will be requested to propose how to divide it between himself and the other participant. All that the Allocator has to do is to specify: (1) how much from the overall amount he/she wants to give to himself/herself, and (2) how much he/she wants to give to the other participant (this amount should equal NIS 40 minus the amount that the Allocator wanted for himself/herself). This is done by typing the two amounts on the computer keyboard. When the Allocator keys in his/her proposal, it will appear on the other participant's computer screen, and he/she will have to reply by stating whether he/she accepts it or rejects it. This is done by using one of two keys designated for this purpose. If the Recipient chooses to accept the proposal, then the total amount will be divided exactly as proposed by the Allocator. If the Recipient chooses to reject the proposal, then each one will get an amount that equals the amount proposed by the Allocator multiplied by a factor of 0.5.

23 R. Suleiman / Journal of Economic Psychology 17 (1996) For example, if the Allocator proposes to give himself/herself A (NIS), and the Recipient B (NIS) (A + B = 40), and the Recipient agrees, then the Allocator will be given A (NIS), and the Recipient B (NIS). But if the Recipient rejects the offer, then the Allocator will be given 0.5 * A (NIS), and the recipient 0.5 * B (NIS). In addition to the above, each participant will be requested to answer a short computerized questionnaire by keying in his/her answers on his/her terminal keyboard. The assignment of the role of Allocator to one participant and Recipient to another will be made before the experiment begins, by a random draw to be carried out by the computer. The results of the draw will be shown immediately on all the PC screens. When the experiment ends, each participant will be paid according to his/her gain. To prevent any contact between participants, each one will be dismissed alone. When you finish, please wait patiently for the experimenter to come in. (B) Instructions for the 6 = 1 (Dictator) condition. You are about to participate in an economics experiment which involves only two persons. In addition to you, there are three other participants in the adjacent booths. You will be randomly paired to only one of them. The remaining two will participate in an experiment that will run parallel to the one that you will participate in. This arrangement was adopted so that no one of the four participants will be able to tell who his partner is. In other words, you will not be able to know who out of the three others is your partner for the experiment. Also, your partner for the experiment will not be able to know who you are. The experiment will be conducted as follows: a sum of NIS 40 will be allocated to each pair, and one of the two participants will be requested to propose how to divide it between himself and the other participant. All that the Allocator has to do is to specify: (1) how much out of the overall amount he/she wants to give to himself/herself, and (2) how much he/she wants to give to the other participant (this amount should equal NIS 40 minus the amount that the Allocator wanted for himself/herself). This is done by typing the two amounts on the computer keyboard. When the Allocator keys in his proposal, it will appear on Recipient's computer screen. This proposal determines how much each participant will gain in the experiment. In addition to the above, each participant will be requested to answer a short computerized questionnaire by keying in his/her answers on his/her terminal keyboard.

Emanuela Carbonara. 31 January University of Bologna - Department of Economics

Emanuela Carbonara. 31 January University of Bologna - Department of Economics Game Theory, Behavior and The Law - I A brief introduction to game theory. Rules of the game and equilibrium concepts. Behavioral Games: Ultimatum and Dictator Games. Entitlement and Framing effects. Emanuela

More information

ULTIMATUM GAME. An Empirical Evidence. Presented By: SHAHID RAZZAQUE

ULTIMATUM GAME. An Empirical Evidence. Presented By: SHAHID RAZZAQUE 1 ULTIMATUM GAME An Empirical Evidence Presented By: SHAHID RAZZAQUE 2 Difference Between Self-Interest, Preference & Social Preference Preference refers to the choices people make & particularly to tradeoffs

More information

Today s lecture. A thought experiment. Topic 3: Social preferences and fairness. Overview readings: Fehr and Fischbacher (2002) Sobel (2005)

Today s lecture. A thought experiment. Topic 3: Social preferences and fairness. Overview readings: Fehr and Fischbacher (2002) Sobel (2005) Topic 3: Social preferences and fairness Are we perfectly selfish? If not, does it affect economic analysis? How to take it into account? Overview readings: Fehr and Fischbacher (2002) Sobel (2005) Today

More information

3. Bargaining experiments

3. Bargaining experiments 3. Bargaining experiments How do we implement bargaining in the lab? What are key results from these bargaining experiments? Do we see deviations from what is predicted by standard economics? Falk: Experimental

More information

Sequential Decision and Strategy Vector Methods in Ultimatum Bargaining: Evidence on the Strength of Other- Regarding Behavior

Sequential Decision and Strategy Vector Methods in Ultimatum Bargaining: Evidence on the Strength of Other- Regarding Behavior Department of Economics Discussion Paper 2004-04 Sequential Decision and Strategy Vector Methods in Ultimatum Bargaining: Evidence on the Strength of Other- Regarding Behavior Robert J. Oxoby University

More information

The Game Prisoners Really Play: Preference Elicitation and the Impact of Communication

The Game Prisoners Really Play: Preference Elicitation and the Impact of Communication The Game Prisoners Really Play: Preference Elicitation and the Impact of Communication Michael Kosfeld University of Zurich Ernst Fehr University of Zurich October 10, 2003 Unfinished version: Please do

More information

Lecture 3. QIAO Zhilin ( 乔志林 ) School of Economics & Finance Xi an Jiaotong University

Lecture 3. QIAO Zhilin ( 乔志林 )   School of Economics & Finance Xi an Jiaotong University Lecture 3 QIAO Zhilin ( 乔志林 ).co School of Economics & Finance Xi an Jiaotong University October, 2015 Introduction Ultimatum Game Traditional Economics Fairness is simply a rhetorical term Self-interest

More information

SUPPLEMENTARY INFORMATION

SUPPLEMENTARY INFORMATION Supplementary Statistics and Results This file contains supplementary statistical information and a discussion of the interpretation of the belief effect on the basis of additional data. We also present

More information

HYPOTHETICAL AND REAL INCENTIVES IN THE ULTIMATUM GAME AND ANDREONI S PUBLIC GOODS GAME: AN EXPERIMENTAL STUDY

HYPOTHETICAL AND REAL INCENTIVES IN THE ULTIMATUM GAME AND ANDREONI S PUBLIC GOODS GAME: AN EXPERIMENTAL STUDY HYPOTHETICAL AND REAL INCENTIVES IN THE ULTIMATUM GAME AND ANDREONI S PUBLIC GOODS GAME: INTRODUCTION AN EXPERIMENTAL STUDY Mark T. Gillis West Virginia University and Paul L. Hettler, Ph.D. California

More information

Topic 3: Social preferences and fairness

Topic 3: Social preferences and fairness Topic 3: Social preferences and fairness Are we perfectly selfish and self-centered? If not, does it affect economic analysis? How to take it into account? Focus: Descriptive analysis Examples Will monitoring

More information

Social Utility in Ultimatum Bargaining

Social Utility in Ultimatum Bargaining Social Justice Research, Vol. 16, No. 3, September 2003 ( C 2003) Social Utility in Ultimatum Bargaining Michel J. J. Handgraaf, 1,4 Eric Van Dijk, 2 and David De Cremer 3 In this article we will provide

More information

Self-Serving Assessments of Fairness and Pretrial Bargaining

Self-Serving Assessments of Fairness and Pretrial Bargaining Self-Serving Assessments of Fairness and Pretrial Bargaining George Loewenstein Samuel Issacharoff Colin Camerer and Linda Babcock Journal of Legal Studies 1993 報告人 : 高培儒 20091028 1 1. Introduction Why

More information

DIFFERENCES IN THE ECONOMIC DECISIONS OF MEN AND WOMEN: EXPERIMENTAL EVIDENCE*

DIFFERENCES IN THE ECONOMIC DECISIONS OF MEN AND WOMEN: EXPERIMENTAL EVIDENCE* DIFFERENCES IN THE ECONOMIC DECISIONS OF MEN AND WOMEN: EXPERIMENTAL EVIDENCE* Catherine C. Eckel Department of Economics Virginia Tech Blacksburg, VA 24061-0316 Philip J. Grossman Department of Economics

More information

The Effect of Stakes in Distribution Experiments. Jeffrey Carpenter Eric Verhoogen Stephen Burks. December 2003

The Effect of Stakes in Distribution Experiments. Jeffrey Carpenter Eric Verhoogen Stephen Burks. December 2003 The Effect of Stakes in Distribution Experiments by Jeffrey Carpenter Eric Verhoogen Stephen Burks December 2003 MIDDLEBURY COLLEGE ECONOMICS DISCUSSION PAPER NO. 03-28 DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS MIDDLEBURY

More information

WILL HOMO ECONOMICUS SURVIVE?

WILL HOMO ECONOMICUS SURVIVE? WILL HOMO ECONOMICUS SURVIVE? PHILIPP DOERRENBERG Erasmus Student In this essay, Philipp Doerrenberg highlights recent experimental work that has proven the shaky foundations of the concept of the rational,

More information

social preferences P000153

social preferences P000153 P000153 Behaviour in a variety of games is inconsistent with the traditional formulation of egoistic decision-makers; however, the observed differences are often systematic and robust. In many cases, people

More information

Koji Kotani International University of Japan. Abstract

Koji Kotani International University of Japan. Abstract Further investigations of framing effects on cooperative choices in a provision point mechanism Koji Kotani International University of Japan Shunsuke Managi Yokohama National University Kenta Tanaka Yokohama

More information

Jakub Steiner The University of Edinburgh. Abstract

Jakub Steiner The University of Edinburgh. Abstract A trace of anger is enough: on the enforcement of social norms Jakub Steiner The University of Edinburgh Abstract It is well documented that the possibility of punishing free-riders increases contributions

More information

Behavioral Game Theory

Behavioral Game Theory Outline (September 3, 2007) Outline (September 3, 2007) Introduction Outline (September 3, 2007) Introduction Examples of laboratory experiments Outline (September 3, 2007) Introduction Examples of laboratory

More information

3. Bargaining Behavior

3. Bargaining Behavior 3. Bargaining Behavior A sequential bargaining game Predictions and actual behavior Comparative statics of bargaining behavior Fairness and the role of stake size Best-shot versus ultimatum game Proposer

More information

Clicker quiz: Should the cocaine trade be legalized? (either answer will tell us if you are here or not) 1. yes 2. no

Clicker quiz: Should the cocaine trade be legalized? (either answer will tell us if you are here or not) 1. yes 2. no Clicker quiz: Should the cocaine trade be legalized? (either answer will tell us if you are here or not) 1. yes 2. no Economic Liberalism Summary: Assumptions: self-interest, rationality, individual freedom

More information

Explaining Bargaining Impasse: The Role of Self-Serving Biases

Explaining Bargaining Impasse: The Role of Self-Serving Biases Explaining Bargaining Impasse: The Role of Self-Serving Biases Linda Babcock and George Loewenstein Journal of Economic Perspectives, 1997 報告人 : 高培儒 20091028 1 1. Introduction Economists, and more specifically

More information

EXPERIMENTAL ECONOMICS INTRODUCTION. Ernesto Reuben

EXPERIMENTAL ECONOMICS INTRODUCTION. Ernesto Reuben EXPERIMENTAL ECONOMICS INTRODUCTION Ernesto Reuben WHAT IS EXPERIMENTAL ECONOMICS? 2 WHAT IS AN ECONOMICS EXPERIMENT? A method of collecting data in controlled environments with the purpose of furthering

More information

Positive reciprocity and intentions in trust games

Positive reciprocity and intentions in trust games Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization Vol. 52 (2003) 267 275 Positive reciprocity and intentions in trust games Kevin A. McCabe a, Mary L. Rigdon b,, Vernon L. Smith a a Interdisciplinary Center

More information

DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS AND FINANCE COLLEGE OF BUSINESS AND ECONOMICS UNIVERSITY OF CANTERBURY CHRISTCHURCH, NEW ZEALAND

DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS AND FINANCE COLLEGE OF BUSINESS AND ECONOMICS UNIVERSITY OF CANTERBURY CHRISTCHURCH, NEW ZEALAND DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS AND FINANCE COLLEGE OF BUSINESS AND ECONOMICS UNIVERSITY OF CANTERBURY CHRISTCHURCH, NEW ZEALAND Comment on Promises and Partnership Cary Deck, Maroš Servátka, and Steven Tucker

More information

Strong Reciprocity and Human Sociality

Strong Reciprocity and Human Sociality Notes on Behavioral Economics 1 Strong Reciprocity and Human Sociality Human groups are highly social despite a low level of relatedness. There is an empirically identifiable form of prosocial behavior

More information

Irrationality in Game Theory

Irrationality in Game Theory Irrationality in Game Theory Yamin Htun Dec 9, 2005 Abstract The concepts in game theory have been evolving in such a way that existing theories are recasted to apply to problems that previously appeared

More information

Effects of Sequential Context on Judgments and Decisions in the Prisoner s Dilemma Game

Effects of Sequential Context on Judgments and Decisions in the Prisoner s Dilemma Game Effects of Sequential Context on Judgments and Decisions in the Prisoner s Dilemma Game Ivaylo Vlaev (ivaylo.vlaev@psy.ox.ac.uk) Department of Experimental Psychology, University of Oxford, Oxford, OX1

More information

Homo economicus is dead! How do we know how the mind works? How the mind works

Homo economicus is dead! How do we know how the mind works? How the mind works Some facts about social preferences, or why we're sometimes nice and sometimes not Karthik Panchanathan buddha@ucla.edu Homo economicus is dead! It was a mistake to believe that individuals and institutions

More information

CeDEx Discussion Paper Series ISSN

CeDEx Discussion Paper Series ISSN Discussion Paper No. 2009 10 Klaus Abbink and Benedikt Herrmann June 2009 The Moral Costs of Nastiness CeDEx Discussion Paper Series ISSN 1749 3293 The Centre for Decision Research and Experimental Economics

More information

Lecture 2: Learning and Equilibrium Extensive-Form Games

Lecture 2: Learning and Equilibrium Extensive-Form Games Lecture 2: Learning and Equilibrium Extensive-Form Games III. Nash Equilibrium in Extensive Form Games IV. Self-Confirming Equilibrium and Passive Learning V. Learning Off-path Play D. Fudenberg Marshall

More information

Gaming Emotions. Teck-Hua Ho (UC Berkeley) Joint work with Eduardo Andrade

Gaming Emotions. Teck-Hua Ho (UC Berkeley) Joint work with Eduardo Andrade Gaming Emotions Teck-Hua Ho (UC Berkeley) Joint work with Eduardo Andrade Emotions on Behavior Emotions influence cognition and behavior Information Processing Memory, categorization, flexibility, etc.

More information

Social Norms and Reciprocity*

Social Norms and Reciprocity* Social Norms and Reciprocity* Andreas Diekmann Institut für Soziologie Universität Bern Thomas Voss Institut für Soziologie Universität Leipzig [ March 2003 ] Paper presented on the session Solidarity

More information

Veronika Grimm, Friederike Mengel. Let me sleep on it: Delay reduces rejection rates in Ultimatum Games RM/10/017

Veronika Grimm, Friederike Mengel. Let me sleep on it: Delay reduces rejection rates in Ultimatum Games RM/10/017 Veronika Grimm, Friederike Mengel Let me sleep on it: Delay reduces rejection rates in Ultimatum Games RM/10/017 Let me sleep on it: Delay reduces rejection rates in Ultimatum Games Veronika Grimm Friederike

More information

VOLKSWIRTSCHAFTLICHE ABTEILUNG. Reputations and Fairness in Bargaining Experimental Evidence from a Repeated Ultimatum Game with Fixed Opponents

VOLKSWIRTSCHAFTLICHE ABTEILUNG. Reputations and Fairness in Bargaining Experimental Evidence from a Repeated Ultimatum Game with Fixed Opponents VOLKSWIRTSCHAFTLICHE ABTEILUNG Reputations and Fairness in Bargaining Experimental Evidence from a Repeated Ultimatum Game with Fixed Opponents Tilman Slembeck March 999 Discussion paper no. 99 DEPARTMENT

More information

Chapter 11. Experimental Design: One-Way Independent Samples Design

Chapter 11. Experimental Design: One-Way Independent Samples Design 11-1 Chapter 11. Experimental Design: One-Way Independent Samples Design Advantages and Limitations Comparing Two Groups Comparing t Test to ANOVA Independent Samples t Test Independent Samples ANOVA Comparing

More information

Rationality and Emotions in Ultimatum Bargaining. Introduction

Rationality and Emotions in Ultimatum Bargaining. Introduction Conférence Des Annales (Lecture delivered in Paris, June 19, 00) Rationality and Emotions in Ultimatum Bargaining Shmuel Zamir 1 The Hebrew University and LEI/CREST Abstract The Ultimatum Bargaining paradigm

More information

Gender Effects in Private Value Auctions. John C. Ham Department of Economics, University of Southern California and IZA. and

Gender Effects in Private Value Auctions. John C. Ham Department of Economics, University of Southern California and IZA. and Gender Effects in Private Value Auctions 2/1/05 Revised 3/3/06 John C. Ham Department of Economics, University of Southern California and IZA and John H. Kagel** Department of Economics, The Ohio State

More information

By Olivia Smith and Steven van de Put Third Year, Second Prize

By Olivia Smith and Steven van de Put Third Year, Second Prize Are humans always the rational, self-interested agents that mainstream economics assumes them to be? Discuss, using ideas of reciprocity, altruism and fairness By Olivia Smith and Steven van de Put Third

More information

How to identify trust and reciprocity

How to identify trust and reciprocity Games and Economic Behavior 46 (2004) 260 281 www.elsevier.com/locate/geb How to identify trust and reciprocity JamesC.Cox Department of Economics, 401 McClelland Hall, University of Arizona, Tucson, AZ

More information

An Experimental Investigation of Self-Serving Biases in an Auditing Trust Game: The Effect of Group Affiliation: Discussion

An Experimental Investigation of Self-Serving Biases in an Auditing Trust Game: The Effect of Group Affiliation: Discussion 1 An Experimental Investigation of Self-Serving Biases in an Auditing Trust Game: The Effect of Group Affiliation: Discussion Shyam Sunder, Yale School of Management P rofessor King has written an interesting

More information

Cooperation in Prisoner s Dilemma Game: Influence of Social Relations

Cooperation in Prisoner s Dilemma Game: Influence of Social Relations Cooperation in Prisoner s Dilemma Game: Influence of Social Relations Maurice Grinberg (mgrinberg@nbu.bg) Evgenia Hristova (ehristova@cogs.nbu.bg) Milena Borisova (borisova_milena@abv.bg) Department of

More information

Cooperation in a Prisoners Dilemma with Losses. Results from an Experimental Study.

Cooperation in a Prisoners Dilemma with Losses. Results from an Experimental Study. Cooperation in a Prisoners Dilemma with Losses. Results from an Experimental Study. Roger Berger Institute for Sociology, University of Leipzig and SNF Venice International University 2006 Rational Choice

More information

Altruistic Behavior: Lessons from Neuroeconomics. Kei Yoshida Postdoctoral Research Fellow University of Tokyo Center for Philosophy (UTCP)

Altruistic Behavior: Lessons from Neuroeconomics. Kei Yoshida Postdoctoral Research Fellow University of Tokyo Center for Philosophy (UTCP) Altruistic Behavior: Lessons from Neuroeconomics Kei Yoshida Postdoctoral Research Fellow University of Tokyo Center for Philosophy (UTCP) Table of Contents 1. The Emergence of Neuroeconomics, or the Decline

More information

Asking and answering research questions. What s it about?

Asking and answering research questions. What s it about? 2 Asking and answering research questions What s it about? (Social Psychology pp. 24 54) Social psychologists strive to reach general conclusions by developing scientific theories about why people behave

More information

ULTIMATUM BARGAINING EXPERIMENTS: THE STATE OF THE ART

ULTIMATUM BARGAINING EXPERIMENTS: THE STATE OF THE ART ULTIMATUM BARGAINING EXPERIMENTS: THE STATE OF THE ART J. NEIL BEARDEN Abstract. In the basic ultimatum bargaining game two players, P 1 and P 2, must divide a pie (π). P 1 proposes a division in which

More information

Ultimatum decision-making: A test of reciprocal kindness. David L. Dickinson ABSTRACT

Ultimatum decision-making: A test of reciprocal kindness. David L. Dickinson ABSTRACT Ultimatum decision-making: A test of reciprocal kindness By David L. Dickinson ABSTRACT While fairness is often mentioned as a determinant of ultimatum bargaining behavior, few data sets are available

More information

ExpEc I. Preliminaries

ExpEc I. Preliminaries ExpEc I. Preliminaries Giovanni Ponti Università di Ferrara Facoltà di Giurisprudenza LUISS Guido Carli LAboratory for Theoretical and EXperimental Economics Universidad de Alicante Roma, 7/6/2010 h t

More information

Risk attitude in decision making: A clash of three approaches

Risk attitude in decision making: A clash of three approaches Risk attitude in decision making: A clash of three approaches Eldad Yechiam (yeldad@tx.technion.ac.il) Faculty of Industrial Engineering and Management, Technion Israel Institute of Technology Haifa, 32000

More information

Altruism. Why Are Organisms Ever Altruistic? Kin Selection. Reciprocal Altruism. Costly Signaling. Group Selection?

Altruism. Why Are Organisms Ever Altruistic? Kin Selection. Reciprocal Altruism. Costly Signaling. Group Selection? Altruism Nepotism Common-Pool Resource (CPR) Tragedy of the Commons Public Good Free-riders Competitive Altruism A 1987 Florida news story reported that 22 blood donors who had false positives on an HIV

More information

Author's personal copy

Author's personal copy Exp Econ DOI 10.1007/s10683-015-9466-8 ORIGINAL PAPER The effects of endowment size and strategy method on third party punishment Jillian Jordan 1 Katherine McAuliffe 1,2 David Rand 1,3,4 Received: 19

More information

DO WEALTH DIFFERENCES AFFECT FAIRNESS CONSIDERATIONS?

DO WEALTH DIFFERENCES AFFECT FAIRNESS CONSIDERATIONS? DO WEALTH DIFFERENCES AFFECT FAIRNESS CONSIDERATIONS? Olivier Armantier May 2003 Abstract The influence of relative wealth on fairness considerations is analyzed in a series of ultimatum game experiments

More information

Equilibrium Cooperation in Three-Person, Choice-of-Partner Games

Equilibrium Cooperation in Three-Person, Choice-of-Partner Games Equilibrium Cooperation in Three-Person, Choice-of-Partner Games Douglas D. Davis and Charles A. Holt * Abstract The experiment involves three-person games in which one player can choose which of two others

More information

Unlike standard economics, BE is (most of the time) not based on rst principles, but on observed behavior of real people.

Unlike standard economics, BE is (most of the time) not based on rst principles, but on observed behavior of real people. Behavioral Economics Lecture 1. Introduction and the Methodology of Experimental Economics 1. Introduction Characteristica of Behavioral Economics (BE) Unlike standard economics, BE is (most of the time)

More information

Handout on Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium

Handout on Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium Handout on Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium Fudong Zhang April 19, 2013 Understanding the concept Motivation In general, the Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium (PBE) is the concept we are using when solving dynamic

More information

Economic Computation and Economic Cybernetics Studies and Research, Issue 4/2015

Economic Computation and Economic Cybernetics Studies and Research, Issue 4/2015 Economic Computation and Economic Cybernetics Studies and Research, Issue 4/205 Assistant Professor Sigifredo LAENGLE, PhD Department of Management Control, Universidad de Chile E-mail: slaengle@fen.uchile.cl

More information

CHAPTER - 6 STATISTICAL ANALYSIS. This chapter discusses inferential statistics, which use sample data to

CHAPTER - 6 STATISTICAL ANALYSIS. This chapter discusses inferential statistics, which use sample data to CHAPTER - 6 STATISTICAL ANALYSIS 6.1 Introduction This chapter discusses inferential statistics, which use sample data to make decisions or inferences about population. Populations are group of interest

More information

In his essay The Truth in Psychological Egoism, Hugh Lafollette uses a modified version

In his essay The Truth in Psychological Egoism, Hugh Lafollette uses a modified version Ashton Payne 100832968 Moral Psychology: PHIL2550 July 25 th, 2014 Part I: In his essay The Truth in Psychological Egoism, Hugh Lafollette uses a modified version of psychological egoism (henceforth PE)

More information

Bargaining about Time: Evidence from Dictator and Ultimatum Games. Roger Berger & Sandra Prade

Bargaining about Time: Evidence from Dictator and Ultimatum Games. Roger Berger & Sandra Prade Bargaining about Time: Evidence from Dictator and Ultimatum Games Roger Berger & Sandra Prade Collaboration and funding: ETH Zurich, Dirk Helbing, Heiko Rauhut. Experimental work: LMU Munich (Chair Braun),

More information

Using Experimental Methods to Inform Public Policy Debates. Jim Murphy Presentation to ISER July 13, 2006

Using Experimental Methods to Inform Public Policy Debates. Jim Murphy Presentation to ISER July 13, 2006 Using Experimental Methods to Inform Public Policy Debates Jim Murphy Presentation to ISER July 13, 2006 Experiments are just one more tool for the applied economist Econometric analysis of nonexperimental

More information

Supporting Information

Supporting Information Supporting Information Burton-Chellew and West 10.1073/pnas.1210960110 SI Results Fig. S4 A and B shows the percentage of free riders and cooperators over time for each treatment. Although Fig. S4A shows

More information

WHEN CULTURE DOES NOT MATTER: EXPERIMENTAL EVIDENCE FROM COALITION FORMATION ULTIMATUM GAMES IN AUSTRIA AND JAPAN

WHEN CULTURE DOES NOT MATTER: EXPERIMENTAL EVIDENCE FROM COALITION FORMATION ULTIMATUM GAMES IN AUSTRIA AND JAPAN WHEN CULTURE DOES NOT MATTER: EXPERIMENTAL EVIDENCE FROM COALITION FORMATION ULTIMATUM GAMES IN AUSTRIA AND JAPAN Akira Okada and Arno Riedl First version: February, 1999 This version: March, 1999 Instructions

More information

A cash effect in ultimatum game experiments

A cash effect in ultimatum game experiments A cash effect in ultimatum game experiments JUNYI SHEN * Research Institute for Economics & Business Administration, Kobe University, Japan and HIROMASA TAKAHASHI Faculty of International Studies, Hiroshima

More information

Reciprocity, Cooperation, and Reputation

Reciprocity, Cooperation, and Reputation Reciprocity, Cooperation, and Reputation Reciprocal altruism Prisoner s dilemma: repeated play allows cooperation Generosity, punishment, spite (Ultimatum games) Reputation Collective action and punishment

More information

Tests of Difference Aversion to Explain Anomalies in Simple Bargaining Games 1. John H. Kagel Department of Economics Ohio State University.

Tests of Difference Aversion to Explain Anomalies in Simple Bargaining Games 1. John H. Kagel Department of Economics Ohio State University. Tests of Difference Aversion to Explain Anomalies in Simple Bargaining Games 1 John H. Kagel Department of Economics Ohio State University and Katherine Wolfe Department of Economics University of Pittsburgh

More information

The Bystander Effect in a Multi-Player Dictator Game. The Bystander Effect Latané and Nida, The Bystander Effect Kitty Genovese (03/13/64)

The Bystander Effect in a Multi-Player Dictator Game. The Bystander Effect Latané and Nida, The Bystander Effect Kitty Genovese (03/13/64) The Bystander Effect in a Multi-Player Dictator Game The Good Samaritan by He Qi Karthik Panchanathan Willem E. Frankenhuis Joan B. Silk Humans are a cooperative species Humans are vastly more cooperative

More information

Appendix: Instructions for Treatment Index B (Human Opponents, With Recommendations)

Appendix: Instructions for Treatment Index B (Human Opponents, With Recommendations) Appendix: Instructions for Treatment Index B (Human Opponents, With Recommendations) This is an experiment in the economics of strategic decision making. Various agencies have provided funds for this research.

More information

COOPERATION 1. How Economic Rewards Affect Cooperation Reconsidered. Dan R. Schley and John H. Kagel. The Ohio State University

COOPERATION 1. How Economic Rewards Affect Cooperation Reconsidered. Dan R. Schley and John H. Kagel. The Ohio State University COOPERATION 1 Running Head: COOPERATION How Economic Rewards Affect Cooperation Reconsidered Dan R. Schley and John H. Kagel The Ohio State University In Preparation Do Not Cite Address correspondence

More information

Giving Feedback to Clients

Giving Feedback to Clients Giving Feedback to Clients Teck-Hua Ho and Catherine Yeung 1 April 27, 2013 1 Authors are listed in alphabetical order. We thank the editor, the associate editor, and 3 anonymous reviewers for their helpful

More information

Further Properties of the Priority Rule

Further Properties of the Priority Rule Further Properties of the Priority Rule Michael Strevens Draft of July 2003 Abstract In Strevens (2003), I showed that science s priority system for distributing credit promotes an allocation of labor

More information

Sawtooth Software. The Number of Levels Effect in Conjoint: Where Does It Come From and Can It Be Eliminated? RESEARCH PAPER SERIES

Sawtooth Software. The Number of Levels Effect in Conjoint: Where Does It Come From and Can It Be Eliminated? RESEARCH PAPER SERIES Sawtooth Software RESEARCH PAPER SERIES The Number of Levels Effect in Conjoint: Where Does It Come From and Can It Be Eliminated? Dick Wittink, Yale University Joel Huber, Duke University Peter Zandan,

More information

Behavioral Game Theory

Behavioral Game Theory School of Computer Science, McGill University March 4, 2011 1 2 3 4 5 Outline Nash equilibria One-shot games 1 2 3 4 5 I Nash equilibria One-shot games Definition: A study of actual individual s behaviors

More information

HOT VS. COLD: SEQUENTIAL RESPONSES AND PREFERENCE STABILITY IN EXPERIMENTAL GAMES * August 1998

HOT VS. COLD: SEQUENTIAL RESPONSES AND PREFERENCE STABILITY IN EXPERIMENTAL GAMES * August 1998 HOT VS. COLD: SEQUENTIAL RESPONSES AND PREFERENCE STABILITY IN EXPERIMENTAL GAMES * August 1998 Jordi Brandts Instituto de Análisis Económico (CSIC) Barcelona and University of California Berkeley (jbrandts@econ.berkeley.edu)

More information

Fairness and Reciprocity in the Hawk-Dove game

Fairness and Reciprocity in the Hawk-Dove game Fairness and Reciprocity in the Hawk-Dove game Tibor Neugebauer*, Anders Poulsen**, and Arthur Schram*** Abstract We study fairness and reciprocity in a Hawk-Dove game. This allows us to test various models

More information

Gender and Culture: International Experimental Evidence from Trust Games

Gender and Culture: International Experimental Evidence from Trust Games Gender and Culture: International Experimental Evidence from Trust Games By RACHEL CROSON AND NANCY BUCHAN* Gender is rarely included as a factor in economics models. However, recent work in experimental

More information

UC Merced Proceedings of the Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society

UC Merced Proceedings of the Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society UC Merced Proceedings of the Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society Title Fairness overrides reputation: The importance of fairness considerations in altruistic cooperation Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/8wp9d7v0

More information

Running head: EMOTIONAL AGENCY: WHY SUGARCOATING PAYS? 1. Emotional Agency: Why Sugarcoating Pays? Teck-Hua Ho

Running head: EMOTIONAL AGENCY: WHY SUGARCOATING PAYS? 1. Emotional Agency: Why Sugarcoating Pays? Teck-Hua Ho Running head: EMOTIONAL AGENCY: WHY SUGARCOATING PAYS? 1 Emotional Agency: Why Sugarcoating Pays? Teck-Hua Ho University of California, Berkeley and National University of Singapore Catherine Yeung National

More information

Games With Incomplete Information: Bayesian Nash Equilibrium

Games With Incomplete Information: Bayesian Nash Equilibrium Games With Incomplete Information: Bayesian Nash Equilibrium Carlos Hurtado Department of Economics University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign hrtdmrt2@illinois.edu June 29th, 2016 C. Hurtado (UIUC - Economics)

More information

Examining differences between two sets of scores

Examining differences between two sets of scores 6 Examining differences between two sets of scores In this chapter you will learn about tests which tell us if there is a statistically significant difference between two sets of scores. In so doing you

More information

A Note On the Design of Experiments Involving Public Goods

A Note On the Design of Experiments Involving Public Goods University of Colorado From the SelectedWorks of PHILIP E GRAVES 2009 A Note On the Design of Experiments Involving Public Goods PHILIP E GRAVES, University of Colorado at Boulder Available at: https://works.bepress.com/philip_graves/40/

More information

Reinforcement Learning : Theory and Practice - Programming Assignment 1

Reinforcement Learning : Theory and Practice - Programming Assignment 1 Reinforcement Learning : Theory and Practice - Programming Assignment 1 August 2016 Background It is well known in Game Theory that the game of Rock, Paper, Scissors has one and only one Nash Equilibrium.

More information

European Society for Organ Transplantation Council

European Society for Organ Transplantation Council This response was submitted to the consultation held by the Nuffield Council on Bioethics on Give and take? Human bodies in medicine and research between April 2010 and July 2010. The views expressed are

More information

Institutions and Cooperative Behavior

Institutions and Cooperative Behavior Institutions and Cooperative Behavior by Arild Vatn Department of International Environmental and Development Studies Norwegian University of Life Sciences Complexity Economics for Sustainability Seminar

More information

Fairness behavior in an economic crisis environment: a Romanian experimental perspective

Fairness behavior in an economic crisis environment: a Romanian experimental perspective Available online at www.sciencedirect.com Procedia - Social and Behavioral Sciences 33 (2012) 503 507 PSIWORLD 2011 Fairness behavior in an economic crisis environment: a Romanian experimental perspective

More information

Guilt and Pro-Social Behavior amongst Workers in an Online Labor Market

Guilt and Pro-Social Behavior amongst Workers in an Online Labor Market Guilt and Pro-Social Behavior amongst Workers in an Online Labor Market Dr. Moran Blueshtein Naveen Jindal School of Management University of Texas at Dallas USA Abstract Do workers in online labor markets

More information

CHAPTER 3 METHOD AND PROCEDURE

CHAPTER 3 METHOD AND PROCEDURE CHAPTER 3 METHOD AND PROCEDURE Previous chapter namely Review of the Literature was concerned with the review of the research studies conducted in the field of teacher education, with special reference

More information

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. Two-Level Ultimatum Bargaining with Incomplete Information: an Experimental Study Author(s): Werner Güth, Steffen Huck, Peter Ockenfels Source: The Economic Journal, Vol. 106, No. 436 (May, 1996), pp.

More information

Color Cues and Viscosity in. Iterated Prisoner s Dilemma

Color Cues and Viscosity in. Iterated Prisoner s Dilemma Color Cues and Viscosity in Iterated Prisoner s Dilemma Michael Joya University of British Columbia Abstract The presence of color tag cues and a viscous environment have each been shown to foster conditional

More information

Introduction to Behavioral Economics Like the subject matter of behavioral economics, this course is divided into two parts:

Introduction to Behavioral Economics Like the subject matter of behavioral economics, this course is divided into two parts: Economics 142: Behavioral Economics Spring 2008 Vincent Crawford (with very large debts to Colin Camerer of Caltech, David Laibson of Harvard, and especially Botond Koszegi and Matthew Rabin of UC Berkeley)

More information

Reciprocity, Cooperation, and Reputation

Reciprocity, Cooperation, and Reputation Reciprocity, Cooperation, and Reputation Reciprocal altruism Prisoner s dilemma: repeated play allows cooperation Generosity, punishment, spite (Ultimatum games) Reputation Before next lecture, see intentionality

More information

THE IMPACT OF GROUP THERAPY ON SOCIAL BEHAVIOUR IN BORDERLINE PERSONALITY DISORDER. Ben Griffin (medical student) & Dr.

THE IMPACT OF GROUP THERAPY ON SOCIAL BEHAVIOUR IN BORDERLINE PERSONALITY DISORDER. Ben Griffin (medical student) & Dr. THE IMPACT OF GROUP THERAPY ON SOCIAL BEHAVIOUR IN BORDERLINE PERSONALITY DISORDER Ben Griffin (medical student) & Dr. Kate Saunders 1 Content Of Talk Introduction This study and previous research in this

More information

Subjects are motivated not only by their own payoffs but also by those of others and the relationship between the payoffs of the players of the game

Subjects are motivated not only by their own payoffs but also by those of others and the relationship between the payoffs of the players of the game Subjects are motivated not only by their own payoffs but also by those of others and the relationship between the payoffs of the players of the game ultimatum games resistance to unfairness dictator games

More information

A static and dynamic experimental analysis

A static and dynamic experimental analysis A static and dynamic experimental analysis Max-Planck-Institute of Economics, Jena in collaboration with Heiko Rauhut & Dirk Helbing December 1, 29 Overview The classical perspective Social norms generate

More information

Introduction to Game Theory Autonomous Agents and MultiAgent Systems 2015/2016

Introduction to Game Theory Autonomous Agents and MultiAgent Systems 2015/2016 Introduction to Game Theory Autonomous Agents and MultiAgent Systems 2015/2016 Ana Paiva * These slides are based on the book by Prof. M. Woodridge An Introduction to Multiagent Systems and the online

More information

Lies, Probabilities, and Threats in Ultimatum Games

Lies, Probabilities, and Threats in Ultimatum Games Connecticut College Digital Commons @ Connecticut College Economics Honors Papers Economics Department 2015 Lies, Probabilities, and Threats in Ultimatum Games Mark Ferreira Connecticut College, mark.r.ferreira@gmail.com

More information

Contributions and Beliefs in Liner Public Goods Experiment: Difference between Partners and Strangers Design

Contributions and Beliefs in Liner Public Goods Experiment: Difference between Partners and Strangers Design Working Paper Contributions and Beliefs in Liner Public Goods Experiment: Difference between Partners and Strangers Design Tsuyoshi Nihonsugi 1, 2 1 Research Fellow of the Japan Society for the Promotion

More information

Does observation of others a ect learning in strategic environments? An experimental study*

Does observation of others a ect learning in strategic environments? An experimental study* Int J Game Theory (1999) 28:131±152 999 Does observation of others a ect learning in strategic environments? An experimental study* John Du y1, Nick Feltovich2 1 Department of Economics, University of

More information

Team Reasoning and a Rank-Based Function of Team s Interests

Team Reasoning and a Rank-Based Function of Team s Interests Team Reasoning and a Rank-Based Function of Team s Interests Jurgis Karpus Mantas Radzvilas April 2015 Abstract Orthodox game theory is sometimes criticized for its failure to single out intuitively compelling

More information

Why do Psychologists Perform Research?

Why do Psychologists Perform Research? PSY 102 1 PSY 102 Understanding and Thinking Critically About Psychological Research Thinking critically about research means knowing the right questions to ask to assess the validity or accuracy of a

More information

Equilibrium Selection In Coordination Games

Equilibrium Selection In Coordination Games Equilibrium Selection In Coordination Games Presenter: Yijia Zhao (yz4k@virginia.edu) September 7, 2005 Overview of Coordination Games A class of symmetric, simultaneous move, complete information games

More information