Causality and Statistical Learning 1. Andrew Gelman Feb 2010

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Causality and Statistical Learning 1. Andrew Gelman Feb 2010"

Transcription

1 Causality and Statistical Learning 1 Andrew Gelman 2 24 Feb 2010 In social science we are sometimes in the position of studying descriptive questions (for example: In what places do working-class whites vote for Republicans? In what eras has social mobility been higher in the United States than in Europe? In what social settings are different sorts of people more likely to act strategically?). Answering descriptive questions is not easy and involves issues of data collection, data analysis, and measurement (how should one define concepts such as working class whites, social mobility, and strategic ), but is uncontroversial from a statistical standpoint. All becomes more difficult when we shift our focus from What to What-if and Why. Thinking about causal inference Consider two broad classes of inferential questions: 1. Forward causal inference. What might happen if we do X? What are the effects of smoking on health, the effects of schooling on knowledge, the effect of campaigns on election outcomes, and so forth? 2. Reverse causal inference. What causes Y? Why do more attractive people earn more money, why do many poor people vote for Republicans and rich people vote for Democrats, why did the economy collapse? In forward reasoning, the potential treatments under study are chosen ahead of time, whereas, in reverse reasoning, the research goal is to find and assess the importance of the causes. The distinction between forward and reverse reasoning (also called the effects of causes and the causes of effects ) was made by Mill (1843). Forward causation is a pretty clearly-defined problem, and there is a consensus that it can be modeled using the counterfactual or potentialoutcome notation associated with Neyman (1923) and Rubin (1974) and expressed using graphical models by Pearl (2009): the causal effect of a treatment T on an outcome Y for an individual person (say), is a comparison between the value of Y that would ve been observed had the person followed the treatment, versus the value that would ve been observed under the control; in many contexts, the treatment effect for person i is defined as the difference, Y i (T=1) - 1 Review for American Journal of Sociology of Counterfactuals and Causal Inference, by Stephen Morgan and Christopher Winship, Causality: Models, Reasoning, and Inference, second edition, by Judea Pearl, and Caual Models: How People Think About the World and Its Alternatives, by Steven Sloman. 2 Department of Statistics and Department of Political Science, Columbia University, New York, gelman@stat.columbia.edu, We thank Kevin Quinn, Jasjeet Sekhon, Judea Pearl, Rajeev Dehejia, Michael Sobel, Jennifer Hill, Paul Rosenbaum, Sander Greenland, Guido Imbens, Donald Rubin, Steven Sloman, Peter Hoff, Thomas Richardson, Niall Bolger, and Christopher Winship for helpful comments and the Institute for Educational Sciences for partial support of this work.

2 Y i (T=0). Many common techniques, such as differences in differences, linear regression, and instrumental variables, can be viewed as estimated average causal effects under this definition. In the social sciences, where it is generally not possible to try more than one treatment on the same unit (and, even when this is possible, there is the possibility of contamination from past exposure and changes in the unit or the treatment over time), questions of forward causation are most directly studied using randomization or so-called natural experiments (see Angrist and Pischke, 2008, for discussion and many examples). In some settings, crossover designs can be used to estimate individual causal effects, if one accepts certain assumptions about treatment effects being bounded in time. Heckman (2006), pointing to the difficulty of generalizing from experimental to real-world settings, argues that randomization is not any sort of gold standard of causal inference, but this is a minority position: I believe that most social scientists and policy analysts would be thrilled to have randomized experiments for their forward-causal questions, even while recognizing that subject-matter models are needed to make useful inferences from any experimental or observational study. Reverse causal inference is another story. As has long been realized, the effects of action X flow naturally forward in time, while the causes of outcome Y cannot be so clearly traced backward. Did the North Vietnamese win the American War because of the Tet Offensive, or because of American public opinion, or because of the skills of General Giap, or because of the political skills of Ho Chi Minh, or because of the conflicted motivations of Henry Kissinger, or because of Vietnam s rough terrain, or...? To ask such a question is to reveal the impossibility of answering it. On the other hand, questions such as Why do whites do better than blacks in school?, while difficult, do not seem inherently unanswerable or meaningless. We can have an idea of going backward in the causal chain, accounting for more and more factors until the difference under study disappears that is, is explained by the causal predictors. Such an activity can be tricky hence the motivation for statistical procedures for studying causal paths and ultimately is often formulated in terms of forward causal questions: causal effects that add up to explaining the Why question that was ultimately asked. Reverse causal questions are often more interesting and motivate much, perhaps most, social science research; forward causal research is more limited and less generalizable but is more doable. So we all end up going back and forth on this. We see three difficult problems in causal inference: - Studying problems of forward causation with observational data or experiments with missing data (the traditional focus of causal inference in the statistics and biostatistics literature); recall that missingness is inherent in the counterfactual definition of causal effects. - Generalizing from experiments or quasi-expeirments to realistic settings. This is the problem of external validity (Campbell and Stanley, 1966), which Heckman (2006) has emphasized. The difficulty is that experiments are often a poor method for understanding how effects may vary across contexts, including from the lab to the real world, and across populations when treatment effects vary.

3 - Studying reverse causation (learning about Why questions) from observational data using multivariate analysis. Here the many threats to a model's validity may be so great as to make confidence in any estimates unattainable.. Along with any of these analyses comes the problem of assessing the plausibility of whatever assumptions are being used to identify causal effects in the particular problem at hand, and the assessment of the sensitivity of causal inferences to these assumptions. It was with this in mind that I read the three books under review, each of which is well-written, thought-provoking, and advances the science of causal reasoning. Morgan and Winship focus on the second item above (their running examples include the effects of family background on educational attainment, the effects of education on earnings, and the effects of voting technology on voting), and Sloman also talks a bit about the third item: learning about causal relationships from multivariate observational data. Fernbach, Darlow, and Sloman (2010) discuss the role of forward and reverse causal reasoning in everyday judgment. Pearl presents a framework in which the potential-outcome model for forward causation can be used to study reverse causation as well. (The three books pretty much ignore the first item in my list above, perhaps under the assumption that, once the basic causal questions are identified, it shouldn t be too hard to fit a model and use it to generalize to other populations.) In this review, I address some of the central debates in causal inference but I do not attempt anything like a serious literature review. I encourage readers to follow the trails of references in the cited here to get a fuller sense of the development of causal inference ideas in the social and cognitive sciences. The statistical literature on causal inference (which has been influenced by work in economics, epidemiology, psychology, philosophy, and computer science) has featured contentious debate, and some of that debate has found its way into the books under review here. I recommend starting with Morgan and Winship s Counterfactuals and Causal Inference, which is written by two sociologists and provides an agnostic overview of the field. They discuss regression estimates of causal effects and the assumptions needed for these estimates to make sense. Along with this, I recommend the discussion of Sobel (2008), who discusses the assumptions required to make inference for mediation that is, quantitative estimates of the decomposition of a causal effect across different paths and Rosenbaum s (2010) book on the design of studies for causal inference. In social science, it can be important not just to have one substantive theory, but to have two theories which the study will contrast, and to have a design that can evaluate them. Pearl s book is the second edition of his influential work that presents causal reasoning as mathematical operations on a system of non-parametric equations, often encoded in directed graphical models. Pearl s formulation is, at the very minimum, a helpful way to understand structural equations and identifiability (as explained by Morgan and Winship in language that may be more comfortable to a statistically-trained social scientist), and this is important. Without a good formal structure, we are all at risk of getting confused over causal inference; for instance, Rubin, 2005, relates an example where the legendary R. A. Fisher made the basic (but apparently not trivial) mistake of adjusting for an intermediate outcome when estimating a

4 treatment effect. Even if we are alert to this particular mistake, if we work without a formal structure we are still at risk of making others, for example when deciding whether to adjust for particular pre-treatment variables in the presence of unobserved confounders. The third book under review is different from the others. Steven Sloman is a cognitive scientist and is just as interested in how people do think as in how they should think. And people think about causality all the time. Just as Karl Popper (1959) and others have told us, scientific facts are difficult to interpret or even collect except in light of a theory. In his research, Sloman has studied the ways that people use causal models to understand correlations. For example: A fact increases belief in another fact if the two share an explanation. For example, telling people that boxers are not eligible for most health insurance plans increased their judgment of the probability that asbestos removers are not eligible either. The common explanation depends on the causal relations. (Increased health risk Cost to health insurers Denial of coverage) However, telling people that boxers are more likely than average to develop a neurological disorder actually decreased their average probability that asbestos removers are more likely than average to develop a neurological disorder. This sort of finding demonstrates the importance of explanation in our understanding of the world. Although it does not itself represent statistical learning, the evident importance of causal thinking in everyday (not just scientific or statistical) contexts makes cognitive and information scientists receptive to Pearl s view that causal structure can, under certain conditions, be perceived from correlational data. Attitudes toward causal inference We can identify a (very rough) ordering of views based on the sorts of assumptions used in causal reasoning. At one extreme is a view expressed by the economists James Heckman (2006), who trusts causal inferences only when they are based on a substantively-motivated model (although this stance can be more permissive to the extent that one is willing to accept such substantive models); see also Deaton (2009). Slightly less conservative is the mainstream view in statistics and labor economics (see Angrist and Pischke, 2008) in which causal inference is allowed from randomized experiments and in certain quasi-random or natural experimental settings under strong assumptions about data collection (such as associated with regression discontinuity designs or instrumental variables). In that way, the statisticians and econometricians, even when they use Bayesian inference, are working with the classical statistical paradigm in which identification is driven by randomization (or, more generally, conditional independence) in data collection. Compared to other social scientists, economists tend to focus more on the effects of possible interventions. Moving in the more permissive direction, we find many epidemiologists (for example, Greenland and Robins, 1986, 2009) who, having long experience with procedures such as attributable risk analysis, are more comfortable with causal inference from observational data, feeling that the assumptions required to move from association to causation are reasonable in some scientific settings. Even more permissive

5 (in this admittedly oversimplified ordering) are social psychologists and others who have been using path analysis and structural equation models for many years to identify the strengths of posited causal relationships from observed covariance matrices (see Duncan, 1966, and Kenny, 1979) although in recent years there has been a move toward a hybrid approach in which mediation analysis is applied to experimental data to study the effects of intervening variables (Baron and Kenny, 1986). Finally, the extreme position is taken, I believe, by those who believe that a computer should be able to discern causal relationships from observational data, based on the reasonable argument that we, as humans, can do this ourselves in our everyday life with little recourse to experiment. The books under review stand somewhat outside this spectrum. Morgan and Winship only commit to the conservative statistical view causal inference from experiments and quasiexperiments but they present the logic behind the more permissive stances. Pearl, as befits his computer-science background, supports a permissive view, but only in theory; he accepts that any practical causal inference will be only as good as the substantive models that underlie it and he is explicit about the additional assumptions required to translate associations into causal inference. In some ways he is close to the statisticians and econometricians who emphasize that randomization allows more robust inferences for causal inference about population averages, although he is also interested in causal inference when randomization or its equivalents are not available. (Pearl does discuss methods for learning causal structural from observational data alone, but such inference is done under an assumption called faithfulness or stability, which corresponds to a model of conditional independence, which I do not think makes sense in social science settings except when such independence arises by design; see the discussion of no true zeroes below.) I myself hold conflicting views, in a manner similar to that expressed by Sobel (2008). On one hand, I do not see how one can get scientifically-strong causal inferences from observational data alone without strong theory; it seems to me a hopeless task to throw a data matrix at a computer program and hope to learn about causal structure. (More on this below.) On the other hand, I recognize that much of our everyday causal intuition, while not having the full quality of scientific reasoning, is still useful, and it seems a bit of a gap to simply use the label descriptive for all inference that is not supported by experiment or very strong theory. Thus, I am sympathetic to theories such as Pearl s that bridge different notions of causal inference and I applaud research such as Sobel s that, by clarifying implicit assumptions, bridges the gap between the experimental and structural-modeling perspectives, even as I have difficulty seeing exactly how to apply them in my own research. For example, income, religion, and religious attendance predict vote choice in different ways in different parts of the country, and we have also found variation in attitudes on economic and social issues (Gelman et al., 2009). But I don t know exactly what would be learned by throwing all these variables into a multivariate model. Throwing a data matrix into causal multivariate analysis software (such as that developed from the ideas of Spirtes, Glymour, and Scheines, 2001) is, if nothing else, a form of data summary, and I can well believe that it might be useful to those trained to interpret that data reduction, even if the estimated graphical model and estimated coefficients can't be interpreted directly in the way that the designers of these programs might

6 think. I am open to the possibility that such an analysis could be useful, but we don t appear to be there yet, and the outputs of structural modeling programs can easily be misinterpreted. There are (almost) no true zeroes: difficulties with the research program of learning causal structure We can distinguish between learning within a causal model (that is, inference about parameters characterizing a specified directed graph) and learning causal structure itself (that is, inference about the graph itself). In social science research, I am extremely skeptical of this second goal. The difficulty is that, in social science, there are no true zeroes. For example, religious attendance is associated with attitudes on economic as well as social issues, and both these correlations vary by state. And it does not interest me, for example, to test a model in which social class affects vote choice through party identification but not along a direct path. More generally, anything that plausibly could have an effect will not have an effect that is exactly zero. I can respect that some social scientists find it useful to frame their research in terms of conditional independence and the testing of null effects, but I don t generally find this approach helpful and I certainly don t believe that it is necessary to think in terms of conditional independence in order to study causality. Without structural zeroes, it is impossible to identify graphical structural equation models. The most common exceptions to this rule, as I see it, are independences from design (as in a designed or natural experiment) or effects that are zero based on a plausible scientific hypothesis (as might arise, for example, in genetics (where genes on different chromosomes might have essentially independent effects, or in a study of ESP). In such settings I can see the value of testing a null hypothesis of zero effect, either for its own sake or to rule out the possibility of a conditional correlation that is supposed not to be there. Another sort of exception to the no zeroes rule comes from information restriction: a person s decision should not be affected by knowledge that he or she doesn t have. For example, a consumer interested in buying apples cares about the total price he pays, not about how much of that goes to the seller and how much goes to the government in the form of taxes. So the restriction is that the utility depends on prices, not on the share of that going to taxes. That is the type of restriction that can help identify demand functions in economics. I realize, however, that my perspective that there are no zeroes (information restrictions aside) is a minority view among social scientists and perhaps among people in general, on the evidence of psychologist Sloman s book. For example, from chapter 2: A good politician will know who is motivated by greed and who is motivated by larger principles in order to discern how to solicit each one s vote when it is needed. I can well believe that people think in this way but I don t buy it! Just about everyone is motivated by greed and by larger principles! This sort of discrete thinking doesn t seem to me to be at all realistic about how people behave although it might very well be a good model about how people characterize others! In the next chapter, Sloman writes, No matter how many times A and B occur together, mere co-occurrence cannot reveal whether A causes B, or B causes A, or something else causes both.

7 [italics added] Again, I am bothered by this sort of discrete thinking. I will return in a moment with an example, but just to speak generally, if A could cause B, and B could cause A, then I would think that, yes, they could cause each other. And if something else could cause them both, I imagine that could be happening along with the causation of A on B and of B on A. Here we re getting into some of the differences between a normative view of science, a descriptive view of science, and a descriptive view of how people perceive the world. Just as there are limits to what folk physics can tell us about the motion of particles, similarly I think we have to be careful about too closely identifying folk causal inference from the stuff done by the best social scientists. To continue the analogy: it is interesting to study how we develop physical intuitions using commonsense notions of force, energy, momentum, and so on but it s also important to see where these intuitions fail. Similarly, ideas of causality are fundamental but that doesn t stop ordinary people and even experts from making basic mistakes. Now I would like to return to the graphical model approach described by Sloman. In chapter 5, he discusses an example with three variables: If two of the variables are dependent, say, intelligence and socioeconomic status, but conditionally independent given the third variable [beer consumption], then either they are related by one of two chains: (Intelligence Amount of beer consumed Socioeconomic status) (Socio-economic status Amount of beer consumed Intelligence) or by a fork: (Amount of beer consumed Socioeconomic status) Intelligence) and then we must use some other means [other than observational data] to decide between these three possibilities. In some cases, common sense may be sufficient, but we can also, if necessary, run an experiment. If we intervene and vary the amount of beer consumed and see that we affect intelligence, that implies that the second or third model is possible; the first one is not. Of course, all this assumes that there aren t other variables mediating between the ones shown that provide alternative explanations of the dependencies. This makes no sense to me. I don t see why only one of the three models can be true. This is a mathematical possibility, but it seems highly implausible to me. And, in particular, running an experiment that reveals one of these causal effects does not rule out the other possible paths. For example, suppose that Sloman were to perform the above experiment (finding that beer consumption affects intelligence) and then another experiment, this time varying intelligence (in some way; the method of doing this can very well determine the causal effect) and finding that it affects the amount of beer consumed. Beyond this fundamental problem, I have a statistical critique, which is that in social science you won t have these sorts of conditional independencies, except from design or as artifacts of small sample sizes that do not allow us to distinguish small dependencies from zero. I think I see where Sloman is coming from, from a psychological perspective: you see these variables that are related to each other, and you want to know which is the cause and which is the

8 effect. But I don t think this is a useful way of understanding the world, just as I don t think it s useful to categorize political players as being motivated either by greed or by larger principles, but not both. Exclusive-or might feel right to us internally, but I don t think it works as science. One important place where I agree with Sloman (and thus with Pearl and Sprites et al.) is in the emphasis that causal structure cannot in general be learned from observational data alone; they hold the very reasonable position that we can use observational data to rule out possibilities and formulate hypotheses, and then use some sort of intervention or experiment (whether actual or hypothetical) to move further. In this way they connect the observational/experimental division to the hypothesis/deduction formulation that is familiar to us from the work of Popper, Kuhn, and other modern philosophers of science. The place where I think Sloman is misguided is in his formulation of scientific models in an either/or way, as if, in truth, social variables are linked in simple causal paths, with a scientific goal of figuring out if A causes B or the reverse. I don t know much about intelligence, beer consumption, and socioeconomic status, but I certainly don t see any simple relationships between income, religious attendance, party identification, and voting and I don t see how a search for such a pattern will advance our understanding, at least given current techniques. I d rather start with description and then go toward causality following the approach of economists and statisticians by thinking about potential interventions one at a time. I d love to see Sloman s and Pearl s ideas of the interplay between observational and experimental data developed in a framework that is less strongly tied to the notion of choice among simple causal structures. Causality as intervention and causality as system modeling The present discussion has highlighted some different ways of thinking about causality. In the world of Pearl, causation is defined in terms of interventions (the do operator), and causality is restricted to be unidirectional, forward in time hence the directed graphs. Rubin adds another restriction, that of associating any causal effect with to a particular intervention, an idea that Sekhon (2009), via Cochran (1965), traces to the following question of Dorn (1956): How would the study be conducted if it were possible to do it by controlled experimentation? For example, statistical writing on causality has sometimes been misunderstood to imply that you can t ever estimate the effects of sex and ethnicity, because it is (nearly) impossible to manipulate these on an individual person. The real point, though, is not that such effect can t be studied but rather that there are many versions of such effects. One sort of effect of sex and ethnicity on hiring has been studied using experiments in which interviewers have been asked to evaluate files with and without details on the job candidates. In this case, the effects are identified with this one particular sort of intervention; other, biological, effects of sex and ethnicity could be studied in other ways. Perhaps because of my own statistical training, I am most comfortable with this view, in which causal inferences are tied to specific (real or hypothesized) treatment. Thus, for example, one might consider the effect of a law requiring adolescents to stay in school another year, or the effect of a financial incentive to stay in school, rather than the more generic effect of schooling.

9 I find it helpful to focus ideas by thinking of specific treatments, but one could certainly argue the opposite and hold the position that the graphical modeling approach (with its do operator that can be applied to any variable in a system) is a more realistic way to understand the world as it is. Different from both the above approaches is the world of many structural equation models used in social science, where causation is defined in terms of variables in a system (for example, inflation can affect unemployment, unemployment can affect inflation, and both can both affect and be affected by government policy). The system-variable approach can be incorporated into the do-calculus or intervention framework by adding time into the system (inflation at time 1 affects unemployment at time 2, and so forth), but this is not always so easy to do with observational data, and in many ways the goals are different: unidirectional causation in one case and equilibrium modeling in the other. Sloman s book is interesting partly because it points up the tension between these two views, both of which are present in our casual reasoning about causality. If we take three variables (beer consumption, intelligence, and social status) that are defined in no particular logical or time order, then any causal patterns are possible and they can all hold. From the causality-asintervention perspective, it makes sense to study the effects of each of these three variables considered as a treatment, and this will likely require three different experiments or observational studies. It would rely on unrealistic assumptions to think that one observational analysis could get at all three treatment effects. From the system-variable perspective, we can consider the effects of these variables on each other without imagining that one configuration of the arrows is correct and the others wrong. Similarly, in economics and sociology, researchers have studied the returns to education and the factors that influence students to stay in school. I find it more helpful to understand the causality here in terms of two different sorts of interventions rather than as a single set of simultaneous equations. Conclusions Casual inference will always be a challenge, partly because our psychological intuitions do not always match how the world works. We like to think of simple causal stories, but in the social world, causes and effects are complex. We the scientific community still have not formed a consensus about how best to form consensus on causal questions: there is a general acceptance that experimentation is a gold standard, but it is not at clear how much experimentation should be done, to what extent we can trust inference from observational data, and to what extent experimentation should be more fully incorporated into daily practice (as suggested by some in the evidence-based medicine movement). The most compelling causal studies have (i) a simple structure that you can see through to the data and the phenomenon under study, (ii) no obvious plausible source of major bias, (iii) serious efforts to detect plausible biases, efforts that have come to naught, and (iv) insensitivity to small and moderate biases (see, for example, Greenland, 2005). Two large open questions are, first, how to best achieve these four steps in practice and, second, what sorts of causal claims to make

10 in settings where we are not able to satisfy these conditions. Right now I think the best approach is a combination of the economists focus on clever designs and identification strategies and the statisticians ability to build more complicated models to assess what might happen if the strict assumptions fall apart. The three books under review convey much of the state of the art in causal reasoning. My own view is that for the foreseeable future, those of us who do causal reasoning in the social sciences will have to continue to think hard about identification strategies (as discussed, for example, by Campbell and Stanley, 1966, and Angrist and Pischke, 2008) and to recognize that multiple analyses may be needed to explore complex causal paths. Ideas of discovering an underlying causal structure do not match to how I understand social science. But there is a diversity of perspectives, both in theory and in practice, on how to move from description to causal inference, and I recommend that social scientists try different approaches as befit their applications. The research contributions of Pearl, and the exposition of Morgan and Winship, should give readers the tools to state the assumptions underlying whatever causal models they choose to use, and the research of Sloman and other cognitive scientists should help us in better understanding how people draw causal conclusions in general, and in the relations between observational and experimental inference inside and outside of science. References Angrist, J. D., and Pischke, J. S. (2008). Mostly Harmless Economics: An Empiricist s Companion. Princeton University Press. Baron, R. M., and Kenny, D. A. (1986). The moderator-mediator variable distinction in social psychological research: conceptual, strategic, and statistical considerations. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 51, Campbell, D. T., and Stanley, J. C. (1966). Experimental and Quasi-Experimental Designs for Research. Chicago: Rand-McNally. Cochran, W. G. (1965). The planning of observational studies of human populations (with discussion). Journal of the Royal Statistical Society A 128, Deaton, A. (2010). Instruments of development: randomization in the tropics, and the search for the elusive keys to economic development. Journal of Economic Literature, to appear. Dorn, H. F. (1953). Philosophy of inference from retrospective studies. American Journal of Public Health 43, Duncan, O. D. (1966). Path analysis: sociological examples. American Journal of Sociology 72, 1-16.

11 Fernbach, P. M., Darlow, A., and Sloman, S. A. (2010). Neglect of alternative causes in predictive but not diagnostic reasoning. Psychological Science. Gelman, A., Park, D., Shor, B., and Cortina, J. (2009). Red State, Blue State, Rich State, Poor State: Why Americans Vote the Way They Do, second edition. Princeton University Press. Greenland, S. (2005). Multiple-bias modeling for analysis of observational data (with discussion). Journal of the Royal Statistical Society A 168, Greenland, S., and Robins, J. M. (1986). Identifiability, exchangeability, and epidemiological confounding. International Journal of Epidemiology 15, Greenland, S., and Robins, J. M. (1989). Identifiability, exchangeability, and confounding revisited. Epidemiologic Perspectives and Innovations 6. Heckman, J. J. (2006). Rejoinder: response to Sobel. Sociological Methodology 35, Imbens, G. W. (2010). Better LATE than nothing: some comments on Deaton (2010) and Heckman and Urzua (2009). Journal of Economic Literature, to appear. Kenny, D. A. (1979). Correlation and Causality. New York: Wiley. Mill, J. S. (1843). A System of Logic. Morgan, S., and Winship, C. (2007). Counterfactuals and Causal Inference: Methods and Principles for Social Research. Cambridge University Press. Neyman, J. (1923). On the application of probability theory to agricultural experiments. Essay on principles. Section 9. Translated and edited by D. M. Dabrowska and T. P. Speed. Statistical Science 5, (1990). Pearl, J. (2009). Causality: Models, Reasoning, and Inference, second edition. Cambridge University Press. Popper, K. R. (1959). The Logic of Scientific Discovery. New York: Basic Books. Rosenbaum, P. R. (2010). Design of Observational Studies. New York: Springer-Verlag. Rubin, D. B. (1974). Estimating causal effects of treatments in randomized and nonrandomized studies. Journal of Educational Psychology 66, Rubin, D. B. (2005). Causal inference using potential outcomes: design, modeling, decisions. Journal of the American Statistical Association 100, Sekhon, J. (2009). Opiates for the matches: matching methods for causal inference. Annual Review of Political Science 12,

12 Sloman, S. (2005). Causal Models: How People Think About the World and Its Alternatives. Oxford University Press. Sobel, M. E. (2008). Identification of causal parameters in randomized studies with mediating variables. Journal of Educational and Behavioral Statistics 33, Spirtes, P., Glymour, C., and Scheines, R. (2001). Causation, Prediction, and Search, second edition. New York: Springer-Verlag.

Causality and Statistical Learning

Causality and Statistical Learning Department of Statistics and Department of Political Science, Columbia University 27 Mar 2013 1. Different questions, different approaches Forward causal inference: What might happen if we do X? Effects

More information

Causality and Statistical Learning

Causality and Statistical Learning Department of Statistics and Department of Political Science, Columbia University 29 Sept 2012 1. Different questions, different approaches Forward causal inference: What might happen if we do X? Effects

More information

Propensity Score Analysis Shenyang Guo, Ph.D.

Propensity Score Analysis Shenyang Guo, Ph.D. Propensity Score Analysis Shenyang Guo, Ph.D. Upcoming Seminar: April 7-8, 2017, Philadelphia, Pennsylvania Propensity Score Analysis 1. Overview 1.1 Observational studies and challenges 1.2 Why and when

More information

The Logic of Causal Inference

The Logic of Causal Inference The Logic of Causal Inference Judea Pearl University of California, Los Angeles Computer Science Department Los Angeles, CA, 90095-1596, USA judea@cs.ucla.edu September 13, 2010 1 Introduction The role

More information

The Regression-Discontinuity Design

The Regression-Discontinuity Design Page 1 of 10 Home» Design» Quasi-Experimental Design» The Regression-Discontinuity Design The regression-discontinuity design. What a terrible name! In everyday language both parts of the term have connotations

More information

Causal Inference Course Syllabus

Causal Inference Course Syllabus ICPSR Summer Program Causal Inference Course Syllabus Instructors: Dominik Hangartner Marco R. Steenbergen Summer 2011 Contact Information: Marco Steenbergen, Department of Social Sciences, University

More information

ICPSR Causal Inference in the Social Sciences. Course Syllabus

ICPSR Causal Inference in the Social Sciences. Course Syllabus ICPSR 2012 Causal Inference in the Social Sciences Course Syllabus Instructors: Dominik Hangartner London School of Economics Marco Steenbergen University of Zurich Teaching Fellow: Ben Wilson London School

More information

You must answer question 1.

You must answer question 1. Research Methods and Statistics Specialty Area Exam October 28, 2015 Part I: Statistics Committee: Richard Williams (Chair), Elizabeth McClintock, Sarah Mustillo You must answer question 1. 1. Suppose

More information

Book review of Herbert I. Weisberg: Bias and Causation, Models and Judgment for Valid Comparisons Reviewed by Judea Pearl

Book review of Herbert I. Weisberg: Bias and Causation, Models and Judgment for Valid Comparisons Reviewed by Judea Pearl Book review of Herbert I. Weisberg: Bias and Causation, Models and Judgment for Valid Comparisons Reviewed by Judea Pearl Judea Pearl University of California, Los Angeles Computer Science Department Los

More information

Temporalization In Causal Modeling. Jonathan Livengood & Karen Zwier TaCitS 06/07/2017

Temporalization In Causal Modeling. Jonathan Livengood & Karen Zwier TaCitS 06/07/2017 Temporalization In Causal Modeling Jonathan Livengood & Karen Zwier TaCitS 06/07/2017 Temporalization In Causal Modeling Jonathan Livengood & Karen Zwier TaCitS 06/07/2017 Introduction Causal influence,

More information

Why do Psychologists Perform Research?

Why do Psychologists Perform Research? PSY 102 1 PSY 102 Understanding and Thinking Critically About Psychological Research Thinking critically about research means knowing the right questions to ask to assess the validity or accuracy of a

More information

Audio: In this lecture we are going to address psychology as a science. Slide #2

Audio: In this lecture we are going to address psychology as a science. Slide #2 Psychology 312: Lecture 2 Psychology as a Science Slide #1 Psychology As A Science In this lecture we are going to address psychology as a science. Slide #2 Outline Psychology is an empirical science.

More information

Jake Bowers Wednesdays, 2-4pm 6648 Haven Hall ( ) CPS Phone is

Jake Bowers Wednesdays, 2-4pm 6648 Haven Hall ( ) CPS Phone is Political Science 688 Applied Bayesian and Robust Statistical Methods in Political Research Winter 2005 http://www.umich.edu/ jwbowers/ps688.html Class in 7603 Haven Hall 10-12 Friday Instructor: Office

More information

Supplement 2. Use of Directed Acyclic Graphs (DAGs)

Supplement 2. Use of Directed Acyclic Graphs (DAGs) Supplement 2. Use of Directed Acyclic Graphs (DAGs) Abstract This supplement describes how counterfactual theory is used to define causal effects and the conditions in which observed data can be used to

More information

PARTIAL IDENTIFICATION OF PROBABILITY DISTRIBUTIONS. Charles F. Manski. Springer-Verlag, 2003

PARTIAL IDENTIFICATION OF PROBABILITY DISTRIBUTIONS. Charles F. Manski. Springer-Verlag, 2003 PARTIAL IDENTIFICATION OF PROBABILITY DISTRIBUTIONS Charles F. Manski Springer-Verlag, 2003 Contents Preface vii Introduction: Partial Identification and Credible Inference 1 1 Missing Outcomes 6 1.1.

More information

Introduction to Applied Research in Economics

Introduction to Applied Research in Economics Introduction to Applied Research in Economics Dr. Kamiljon T. Akramov IFPRI, Washington, DC, USA Regional Training Course on Applied Econometric Analysis June 12-23, 2017, WIUT, Tashkent, Uzbekistan Why

More information

Chapter 11 Nonexperimental Quantitative Research Steps in Nonexperimental Research

Chapter 11 Nonexperimental Quantitative Research Steps in Nonexperimental Research Chapter 11 Nonexperimental Quantitative Research (Reminder: Don t forget to utilize the concept maps and study questions as you study this and the other chapters.) Nonexperimental research is needed because

More information

Assignment 4: True or Quasi-Experiment

Assignment 4: True or Quasi-Experiment Assignment 4: True or Quasi-Experiment Objectives: After completing this assignment, you will be able to Evaluate when you must use an experiment to answer a research question Develop statistical hypotheses

More information

August 29, Introduction and Overview

August 29, Introduction and Overview August 29, 2018 Introduction and Overview Why are we here? Haavelmo(1944): to become master of the happenings of real life. Theoretical models are necessary tools in our attempts to understand and explain

More information

Why randomize? Rohini Pande Harvard University and J-PAL.

Why randomize? Rohini Pande Harvard University and J-PAL. Why randomize? Rohini Pande Harvard University and J-PAL www.povertyactionlab.org Agenda I. Background on Program Evaluation II. What is a randomized experiment? III. Advantages and Limitations of Experiments

More information

Durkheim. Durkheim s fundamental task in Rules of the Sociological Method is to lay out

Durkheim. Durkheim s fundamental task in Rules of the Sociological Method is to lay out Michelle Lynn Tey Meadow Jane Jones Deirdre O Sullivan Durkheim Durkheim s fundamental task in Rules of the Sociological Method is to lay out the basic disciplinary structure of sociology. He begins by

More information

Introduction to Observational Studies. Jane Pinelis

Introduction to Observational Studies. Jane Pinelis Introduction to Observational Studies Jane Pinelis 22 March 2018 Outline Motivating example Observational studies vs. randomized experiments Observational studies: basics Some adjustment strategies Matching

More information

Introduction to Applied Research in Economics Kamiljon T. Akramov, Ph.D. IFPRI, Washington, DC, USA

Introduction to Applied Research in Economics Kamiljon T. Akramov, Ph.D. IFPRI, Washington, DC, USA Introduction to Applied Research in Economics Kamiljon T. Akramov, Ph.D. IFPRI, Washington, DC, USA Training Course on Applied Econometric Analysis June 1, 2015, WIUT, Tashkent, Uzbekistan Why do we need

More information

Chapter Eight: Multivariate Analysis

Chapter Eight: Multivariate Analysis Chapter Eight: Multivariate Analysis Up until now, we have covered univariate ( one variable ) analysis and bivariate ( two variables ) analysis. We can also measure the simultaneous effects of two or

More information

Rejoinder to discussion of Philosophy and the practice of Bayesian statistics

Rejoinder to discussion of Philosophy and the practice of Bayesian statistics 76 British Journal of Mathematical and Statistical Psychology (2013), 66, 76 80 2012 The British Psychological Society www.wileyonlinelibrary.com Author response Rejoinder to discussion of Philosophy and

More information

Chapter Eight: Multivariate Analysis

Chapter Eight: Multivariate Analysis Chapter Eight: Multivariate Analysis Up until now, we have covered univariate ( one variable ) analysis and bivariate ( two variables ) analysis. We can also measure the simultaneous effects of two or

More information

Political Science 15, Winter 2014 Final Review

Political Science 15, Winter 2014 Final Review Political Science 15, Winter 2014 Final Review The major topics covered in class are listed below. You should also take a look at the readings listed on the class website. Studying Politics Scientifically

More information

An Experimental Investigation of Self-Serving Biases in an Auditing Trust Game: The Effect of Group Affiliation: Discussion

An Experimental Investigation of Self-Serving Biases in an Auditing Trust Game: The Effect of Group Affiliation: Discussion 1 An Experimental Investigation of Self-Serving Biases in an Auditing Trust Game: The Effect of Group Affiliation: Discussion Shyam Sunder, Yale School of Management P rofessor King has written an interesting

More information

On the diversity principle and local falsifiability

On the diversity principle and local falsifiability On the diversity principle and local falsifiability Uriel Feige October 22, 2012 1 Introduction This manuscript concerns the methodology of evaluating one particular aspect of TCS (theoretical computer

More information

Endogeneity is a fancy word for a simple problem. So fancy, in fact, that the Microsoft Word spell-checker does not recognize it.

Endogeneity is a fancy word for a simple problem. So fancy, in fact, that the Microsoft Word spell-checker does not recognize it. Jesper B Sørensen August 2012 Endogeneity is a fancy word for a simple problem. So fancy, in fact, that the Microsoft Word spell-checker does not recognize it. Technically, in a statistical model you have

More information

PSYCHOLOGISM VS. CONVENTIONAL VALUES by L.A. Boland

PSYCHOLOGISM VS. CONVENTIONAL VALUES by L.A. Boland PSYCHOLOGISM VS. CONVENTIONAL VALUES by L.A. Boland 1. Introduction 1.1 The purpose of this short paper is to present the view that Social Science today may be methodologically incapable of explaining

More information

Response to the ASA s statement on p-values: context, process, and purpose

Response to the ASA s statement on p-values: context, process, and purpose Response to the ASA s statement on p-values: context, process, purpose Edward L. Ionides Alexer Giessing Yaacov Ritov Scott E. Page Departments of Complex Systems, Political Science Economics, University

More information

Overview of Perspectives on Causal Inference: Campbell and Rubin. Stephen G. West Arizona State University Freie Universität Berlin, Germany

Overview of Perspectives on Causal Inference: Campbell and Rubin. Stephen G. West Arizona State University Freie Universität Berlin, Germany Overview of Perspectives on Causal Inference: Campbell and Rubin Stephen G. West Arizona State University Freie Universität Berlin, Germany 1 Randomized Experiment (RE) Sir Ronald Fisher E(X Treatment

More information

Bayesian and Frequentist Approaches

Bayesian and Frequentist Approaches Bayesian and Frequentist Approaches G. Jogesh Babu Penn State University http://sites.stat.psu.edu/ babu http://astrostatistics.psu.edu All models are wrong But some are useful George E. P. Box (son-in-law

More information

Rational Choice Theory I: The Foundations of the Theory

Rational Choice Theory I: The Foundations of the Theory Rational Choice Theory I: The Foundations of the Theory Benjamin Ferguson Administrative Keep in mind that your second papers are due this coming Friday at midnight. They should be emailed to me, roughly

More information

(CORRELATIONAL DESIGN AND COMPARATIVE DESIGN)

(CORRELATIONAL DESIGN AND COMPARATIVE DESIGN) UNIT 4 OTHER DESIGNS (CORRELATIONAL DESIGN AND COMPARATIVE DESIGN) Quasi Experimental Design Structure 4.0 Introduction 4.1 Objectives 4.2 Definition of Correlational Research Design 4.3 Types of Correlational

More information

Causality and counterfactual analysis

Causality and counterfactual analysis Chapter 6.4 Causality and counterfactual analysis Daniel M. Hausman In chapter 6.2 of this book, Sander Greenland provides an introduction to contemporary views of causal inference (see also Pearl 2000)

More information

Prediction, Causation, and Interpretation in Social Science. Duncan Watts Microsoft Research

Prediction, Causation, and Interpretation in Social Science. Duncan Watts Microsoft Research Prediction, Causation, and Interpretation in Social Science Duncan Watts Microsoft Research Explanation in Social Science: Causation or Interpretation? When social scientists talk about explanation they

More information

The Logic of Data Analysis Using Statistical Techniques M. E. Swisher, 2016

The Logic of Data Analysis Using Statistical Techniques M. E. Swisher, 2016 The Logic of Data Analysis Using Statistical Techniques M. E. Swisher, 2016 This course does not cover how to perform statistical tests on SPSS or any other computer program. There are several courses

More information

9 research designs likely for PSYC 2100

9 research designs likely for PSYC 2100 9 research designs likely for PSYC 2100 1) 1 factor, 2 levels, 1 group (one group gets both treatment levels) related samples t-test (compare means of 2 levels only) 2) 1 factor, 2 levels, 2 groups (one

More information

Behaviorism: An essential survival tool for practitioners in autism

Behaviorism: An essential survival tool for practitioners in autism Behaviorism: An essential survival tool for practitioners in autism What we re going to do today 1. Review the role of radical behaviorism (RB) James M. Johnston, Ph.D., BCBA-D National Autism Conference

More information

Explaining an Explanatory Gap Gilbert Harman Princeton University

Explaining an Explanatory Gap Gilbert Harman Princeton University Explaining an Explanatory Gap Gilbert Harman Princeton University Discussions of the mind-body problem often refer to an explanatory gap (Levine 1983) between some aspect of our conscious mental life and

More information

How is ethics like logistic regression? Ethics decisions, like statistical inferences, are informative only if they re not too easy or too hard 1

How is ethics like logistic regression? Ethics decisions, like statistical inferences, are informative only if they re not too easy or too hard 1 How is ethics like logistic regression? Ethics decisions, like statistical inferences, are informative only if they re not too easy or too hard 1 Andrew Gelman and David Madigan 2 16 Jan 2015 Consider

More information

Quasi-experimental analysis Notes for "Structural modelling".

Quasi-experimental analysis Notes for Structural modelling. Quasi-experimental analysis Notes for "Structural modelling". Martin Browning Department of Economics, University of Oxford Revised, February 3 2012 1 Quasi-experimental analysis. 1.1 Modelling using quasi-experiments.

More information

Causality and Treatment Effects

Causality and Treatment Effects Causality and Treatment Effects Prof. Jacob M. Montgomery Quantitative Political Methodology (L32 363) October 24, 2016 Lecture 13 (QPM 2016) Causality and Treatment Effects October 24, 2016 1 / 32 Causal

More information

Regression Discontinuity Analysis

Regression Discontinuity Analysis Regression Discontinuity Analysis A researcher wants to determine whether tutoring underachieving middle school students improves their math grades. Another wonders whether providing financial aid to low-income

More information

Introduction to Program Evaluation

Introduction to Program Evaluation Introduction to Program Evaluation Nirav Mehta Assistant Professor Economics Department University of Western Ontario January 22, 2014 Mehta (UWO) Program Evaluation January 22, 2014 1 / 28 What is Program

More information

Step 2 Challenging negative thoughts "Weeding"

Step 2 Challenging negative thoughts Weeding Managing Automatic Negative Thoughts (ANTs) Step 1 Identifying negative thoughts "ANTs" Step 2 Challenging negative thoughts "Weeding" Step 3 Planting positive thoughts 'Potting" Step1 Identifying Your

More information

Chapter 1 Social Science and Its Methods

Chapter 1 Social Science and Its Methods Chapter 1 Social Science and Its Methods MULTIPLE CHOICE 1) Scientific knowledge is knowledge that has been: A) systematically gathered, classified, related, and interpreted. B) rediscovered and cherished

More information

PharmaSUG Paper HA-04 Two Roads Diverged in a Narrow Dataset...When Coarsened Exact Matching is More Appropriate than Propensity Score Matching

PharmaSUG Paper HA-04 Two Roads Diverged in a Narrow Dataset...When Coarsened Exact Matching is More Appropriate than Propensity Score Matching PharmaSUG 207 - Paper HA-04 Two Roads Diverged in a Narrow Dataset...When Coarsened Exact Matching is More Appropriate than Propensity Score Matching Aran Canes, Cigna Corporation ABSTRACT Coarsened Exact

More information

Lecture 9 Internal Validity

Lecture 9 Internal Validity Lecture 9 Internal Validity Objectives Internal Validity Threats to Internal Validity Causality Bayesian Networks Internal validity The extent to which the hypothesized relationship between 2 or more variables

More information

Introduction to Research Methods

Introduction to Research Methods Introduction to Research Methods Updated August 08, 2016 1 The Three Types of Psychology Research Psychology research can usually be classified as one of three major types: 1. Causal Research When most

More information

ISC- GRADE XI HUMANITIES ( ) PSYCHOLOGY. Chapter 2- Methods of Psychology

ISC- GRADE XI HUMANITIES ( ) PSYCHOLOGY. Chapter 2- Methods of Psychology ISC- GRADE XI HUMANITIES (2018-19) PSYCHOLOGY Chapter 2- Methods of Psychology OUTLINE OF THE CHAPTER (i) Scientific Methods in Psychology -observation, case study, surveys, psychological tests, experimentation

More information

What is: regression discontinuity design?

What is: regression discontinuity design? What is: regression discontinuity design? Mike Brewer University of Essex and Institute for Fiscal Studies Part of Programme Evaluation for Policy Analysis (PEPA), a Node of the NCRM Regression discontinuity

More information

A Brief Introduction to Bayesian Statistics

A Brief Introduction to Bayesian Statistics A Brief Introduction to Statistics David Kaplan Department of Educational Psychology Methods for Social Policy Research and, Washington, DC 2017 1 / 37 The Reverend Thomas Bayes, 1701 1761 2 / 37 Pierre-Simon

More information

Review of Animals and the Economy. Steven McMullen Palgrave, pp., ebook and hardcover. Bob Fischer Texas State University

Review of Animals and the Economy. Steven McMullen Palgrave, pp., ebook and hardcover. Bob Fischer Texas State University 153 Between the Species Review of Animals and the Economy Steven McMullen Palgrave, 2016 216 pp., ebook and hardcover Bob Fischer Texas State University fischer@txstate.edu Volume 20, Issue 1 Summer, 2017

More information

Lecture (chapter 1): Introduction

Lecture (chapter 1): Introduction Lecture (chapter 1): Introduction Ernesto F. L. Amaral January 17, 2018 Advanced Methods of Social Research (SOCI 420) Source: Healey, Joseph F. 2015. Statistics: A Tool for Social Research. Stamford:

More information

CSC2130: Empirical Research Methods for Software Engineering

CSC2130: Empirical Research Methods for Software Engineering CSC2130: Empirical Research Methods for Software Engineering Steve Easterbrook sme@cs.toronto.edu www.cs.toronto.edu/~sme/csc2130/ 2004-5 Steve Easterbrook. This presentation is available free for non-commercial

More information

PLS 506 Mark T. Imperial, Ph.D. Lecture Notes: Reliability & Validity

PLS 506 Mark T. Imperial, Ph.D. Lecture Notes: Reliability & Validity PLS 506 Mark T. Imperial, Ph.D. Lecture Notes: Reliability & Validity Measurement & Variables - Initial step is to conceptualize and clarify the concepts embedded in a hypothesis or research question with

More information

Doing High Quality Field Research. Kim Elsbach University of California, Davis

Doing High Quality Field Research. Kim Elsbach University of California, Davis Doing High Quality Field Research Kim Elsbach University of California, Davis 1 1. What Does it Mean to do High Quality (Qualitative) Field Research? a) It plays to the strengths of the method for theory

More information

The scope of perceptual content, II: properties

The scope of perceptual content, II: properties The scope of perceptual content, II: properties Jeff Speaks November 16, 2009 1 What are the candidates?............................ 1 2 Arguments for inclusion............................. 2 2.1 From

More information

Functionalist theories of content

Functionalist theories of content Functionalist theories of content PHIL 93507 April 22, 2012 Let s assume that there is a certain stable dependence relation between the physical internal states of subjects and the phenomenal characters

More information

INTERVIEWS II: THEORIES AND TECHNIQUES 5. CLINICAL APPROACH TO INTERVIEWING PART 1

INTERVIEWS II: THEORIES AND TECHNIQUES 5. CLINICAL APPROACH TO INTERVIEWING PART 1 INTERVIEWS II: THEORIES AND TECHNIQUES 5. CLINICAL APPROACH TO INTERVIEWING PART 1 5.1 Clinical Interviews: Background Information The clinical interview is a technique pioneered by Jean Piaget, in 1975,

More information

Soci Social Stratification

Soci Social Stratification University of North Carolina Chapel Hill Soci850-001 Social Stratification Spring 2010 Professor François Nielsen Module 7 Socioeconomic Attainment & Comparative Social Mobility Discussion Questions Introduction

More information

The Logic of Causal Order Richard Williams, University of Notre Dame, https://www3.nd.edu/~rwilliam/ Last revised February 15, 2015

The Logic of Causal Order Richard Williams, University of Notre Dame, https://www3.nd.edu/~rwilliam/ Last revised February 15, 2015 The Logic of Causal Order Richard Williams, University of Notre Dame, https://www3.nd.edu/~rwilliam/ Last revised February 15, 2015 [NOTE: Toolbook files will be used when presenting this material] First,

More information

Modelling Experimental Interventions: Results and Challenges

Modelling Experimental Interventions: Results and Challenges Concrete Causation Munich 2010 Modelling Experimental Interventions: Results and Challenges Jan-Willem Romeijn Faculty of Philosophy University of Groningen Contents 1 Overview 3 2 Interventions and confirmation

More information

The Limits of Inference Without Theory

The Limits of Inference Without Theory The Limits of Inference Without Theory Kenneth I. Wolpin University of Pennsylvania Koopmans Memorial Lecture (2) Cowles Foundation Yale University November 3, 2010 Introduction Fuller utilization of the

More information

Measuring Impact. Conceptual Issues in Program and Policy Evaluation. Daniel L. Millimet. Southern Methodist University.

Measuring Impact. Conceptual Issues in Program and Policy Evaluation. Daniel L. Millimet. Southern Methodist University. Measuring mpact Conceptual ssues in Program and Policy Evaluation Daniel L. Millimet Southern Methodist University 23 May 2013 DL Millimet (SMU) Measuring mpact May 2013 1 / 25 ntroduction Primary concern

More information

Bradford Hill Criteria for Causal Inference Based on a presentation at the 2015 ANZEA Conference

Bradford Hill Criteria for Causal Inference Based on a presentation at the 2015 ANZEA Conference Bradford Hill Criteria for Causal Inference Based on a presentation at the 2015 ANZEA Conference Julian King Director, Julian King & Associates a member of the Kinnect Group www.julianking.co.nz www.kinnect.co.nz

More information

What is analytical sociology? And is it the future of sociology?

What is analytical sociology? And is it the future of sociology? What is analytical sociology? And is it the future of sociology? Twan Huijsmans Sociology Abstract During the last few decades a new approach in sociology has been developed, analytical sociology (AS).

More information

Pros. University of Chicago and NORC at the University of Chicago, USA, and IZA, Germany

Pros. University of Chicago and NORC at the University of Chicago, USA, and IZA, Germany Dan A. Black University of Chicago and NORC at the University of Chicago, USA, and IZA, Germany Matching as a regression estimator Matching avoids making assumptions about the functional form of the regression

More information

Answers to end of chapter questions

Answers to end of chapter questions Answers to end of chapter questions Chapter 1 What are the three most important characteristics of QCA as a method of data analysis? QCA is (1) systematic, (2) flexible, and (3) it reduces data. What are

More information

Chapter 1: Explaining Behavior

Chapter 1: Explaining Behavior Chapter 1: Explaining Behavior GOAL OF SCIENCE is to generate explanations for various puzzling natural phenomenon. - Generate general laws of behavior (psychology) RESEARCH: principle method for acquiring

More information

The Economics of tobacco and other addictive goods Hurley, pp

The Economics of tobacco and other addictive goods Hurley, pp s of The s of tobacco and other Hurley, pp150 153. Chris Auld s 318 March 27, 2013 s of reduction in 1994. An interesting observation from Tables 1 and 3 is that the provinces of Newfoundland and British

More information

UNIT 5 - Association Causation, Effect Modification and Validity

UNIT 5 - Association Causation, Effect Modification and Validity 5 UNIT 5 - Association Causation, Effect Modification and Validity Introduction In Unit 1 we introduced the concept of causality in epidemiology and presented different ways in which causes can be understood

More information

- Triangulation - Member checks - Peer review - Researcher identity statement

- Triangulation - Member checks - Peer review - Researcher identity statement Module 3 Dr. Maxwell Reema Alsweel EDRS 797 November 13, 2009 Matrix Potential validity threat Looking for answers Leading Overlooking important data that does not seem to fit Asking the right questions

More information

Speaker Notes: Qualitative Comparative Analysis (QCA) in Implementation Studies

Speaker Notes: Qualitative Comparative Analysis (QCA) in Implementation Studies Speaker Notes: Qualitative Comparative Analysis (QCA) in Implementation Studies PART 1: OVERVIEW Slide 1: Overview Welcome to Qualitative Comparative Analysis in Implementation Studies. This narrated powerpoint

More information

the examples she used with her arguments were good ones because they lead the reader to the answer concerning the thesis statement.

the examples she used with her arguments were good ones because they lead the reader to the answer concerning the thesis statement. SAMPLE PAPER 2 Using our PW and CT models, I concluded that Meg Greenfield's essay "In Defense of the Animals" is better than Ron Kline's " A Scientist: I am the enemy". Although both the essays had the

More information

Data and Statistics 101: Key Concepts in the Collection, Analysis, and Application of Child Welfare Data

Data and Statistics 101: Key Concepts in the Collection, Analysis, and Application of Child Welfare Data TECHNICAL REPORT Data and Statistics 101: Key Concepts in the Collection, Analysis, and Application of Child Welfare Data CONTENTS Executive Summary...1 Introduction...2 Overview of Data Analysis Concepts...2

More information

15.301/310, Managerial Psychology Prof. Dan Ariely Recitation 8: T test and ANOVA

15.301/310, Managerial Psychology Prof. Dan Ariely Recitation 8: T test and ANOVA 15.301/310, Managerial Psychology Prof. Dan Ariely Recitation 8: T test and ANOVA Statistics does all kinds of stuff to describe data Talk about baseball, other useful stuff We can calculate the probability.

More information

You can use this app to build a causal Bayesian network and experiment with inferences. We hope you ll find it interesting and helpful.

You can use this app to build a causal Bayesian network and experiment with inferences. We hope you ll find it interesting and helpful. icausalbayes USER MANUAL INTRODUCTION You can use this app to build a causal Bayesian network and experiment with inferences. We hope you ll find it interesting and helpful. We expect most of our users

More information

Chapter 11. Experimental Design: One-Way Independent Samples Design

Chapter 11. Experimental Design: One-Way Independent Samples Design 11-1 Chapter 11. Experimental Design: One-Way Independent Samples Design Advantages and Limitations Comparing Two Groups Comparing t Test to ANOVA Independent Samples t Test Independent Samples ANOVA Comparing

More information

POLI 343 Introduction to Political Research

POLI 343 Introduction to Political Research POLI 343 Introduction to Political Research Session 5: Theory in the Research Process, Concepts, Laws and Paradigms Lecturer: Prof. A. Essuman-Johnson, Dept. of Political Science Contact Information: aessuman-johnson@ug.edu.gh

More information

Conflict Management & Problem Solving

Conflict Management & Problem Solving Conflict Management & Problem Solving Ground Rules S L O W down the conversation Put your thinking on the table, not your finished thought Stay open to influence be willing to move your stake Listen in

More information

A Brief Guide to Writing

A Brief Guide to Writing Writing Workshop WRITING WORKSHOP BRIEF GUIDE SERIES A Brief Guide to Writing Psychology Papers and Writing Psychology Papers Analyzing Psychology Studies Psychology papers can be tricky to write, simply

More information

Representational Content and Phenomenal Character

Representational Content and Phenomenal Character By David Hilbert, Unversity of Illinois at Chicago, Forthcoming in Sage Encyclopedia of Perception QUALIA Perception and thought are often, although not exclusively, concerned with information about the

More information

In 1980, a new term entered our vocabulary: Attention deficit disorder. It

In 1980, a new term entered our vocabulary: Attention deficit disorder. It In This Chapter Chapter 1 AD/HD Basics Recognizing symptoms of attention deficit/hyperactivity disorder Understanding the origins of AD/HD Viewing AD/HD diagnosis and treatment Coping with AD/HD in your

More information

Further Properties of the Priority Rule

Further Properties of the Priority Rule Further Properties of the Priority Rule Michael Strevens Draft of July 2003 Abstract In Strevens (2003), I showed that science s priority system for distributing credit promotes an allocation of labor

More information

Public Opinion Survey on Tobacco Use in Outdoor Dining Areas Survey Specifications and Training Guide

Public Opinion Survey on Tobacco Use in Outdoor Dining Areas Survey Specifications and Training Guide Public Opinion Survey on Tobacco Use in Outdoor Dining Areas Survey Specifications and Training Guide PURPOSE OF SPECIFICATIONS AND TRAINING GUIDE This guide explains how to use the public opinion survey

More information

Checking the counterarguments confirms that publication bias contaminated studies relating social class and unethical behavior

Checking the counterarguments confirms that publication bias contaminated studies relating social class and unethical behavior 1 Checking the counterarguments confirms that publication bias contaminated studies relating social class and unethical behavior Gregory Francis Department of Psychological Sciences Purdue University gfrancis@purdue.edu

More information

Causal Thinking in the Twilight Zone

Causal Thinking in the Twilight Zone Observational Studies 1 (2015) 200-204 Submitted 7/15; Published 8/15 TECHNICAL REPORT R-456 August 2015 Causal Thinking in the Twilight Zone Judea Pearl Computer Science Department University of California,

More information

Reduce Tension by Making the Desired Choice Easier

Reduce Tension by Making the Desired Choice Easier Daniel Kahneman Talk at Social and Behavioral Sciences Meeting at OEOB Reduce Tension by Making the Desired Choice Easier Here is one of the best theoretical ideas that psychology has to offer developed

More information

1 The conceptual underpinnings of statistical power

1 The conceptual underpinnings of statistical power 1 The conceptual underpinnings of statistical power The importance of statistical power As currently practiced in the social and health sciences, inferential statistics rest solidly upon two pillars: statistical

More information

Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-Share Alike License

Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-Share Alike License Author: Brenda Gunderson, Ph.D., 2015 License: Unless otherwise noted, this material is made available under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution- NonCommercial-Share Alike 3.0 Unported License:

More information

PSY 328 Module 1 Lecture Notes

PSY 328 Module 1 Lecture Notes PSY 328 Module 1 Lecture Notes In the perspective portion of this module, you were introduced to just one aspect of social psychology, impression formation. In Module 1, we will define social psychology,

More information

Doing After Seeing. Seeing vs. Doing in Causal Bayes Nets

Doing After Seeing. Seeing vs. Doing in Causal Bayes Nets Doing After Seeing Björn Meder (bmeder@uni-goettingen.de) York Hagmayer (york.hagmayer@bio.uni-goettingen.de) Michael R. Waldmann (michael.waldmann@bio.uni-goettingen.de) Department of Psychology, University

More information

t-test for r Copyright 2000 Tom Malloy. All rights reserved

t-test for r Copyright 2000 Tom Malloy. All rights reserved t-test for r Copyright 2000 Tom Malloy. All rights reserved This is the text of the in-class lecture which accompanied the Authorware visual graphics on this topic. You may print this text out and use

More information

Lecture II: Difference in Difference and Regression Discontinuity

Lecture II: Difference in Difference and Regression Discontinuity Review Lecture II: Difference in Difference and Regression Discontinuity it From Lecture I Causality is difficult to Show from cross sectional observational studies What caused what? X caused Y, Y caused

More information

Clicker quiz: Should the cocaine trade be legalized? (either answer will tell us if you are here or not) 1. yes 2. no

Clicker quiz: Should the cocaine trade be legalized? (either answer will tell us if you are here or not) 1. yes 2. no Clicker quiz: Should the cocaine trade be legalized? (either answer will tell us if you are here or not) 1. yes 2. no Economic Liberalism Summary: Assumptions: self-interest, rationality, individual freedom

More information