Mental Imagery: philosophical foundations

Similar documents
A Direct Object of Perception

Mental Imagery. What is Imagery? What We Can Imagine 3/3/10. What is nature of the images? What is the nature of imagery for the other senses?

Perceptual Imagination and Perceptual Memory

Ian Rory Owen. Psychotherapy and Phenomenology: On Freud, Husserl and Heidegger. Lincoln, NE: iuniverse, Inc., 2006.

Representational Content and Phenomenal Character

Chapter 8: Visual Imagery & Spatial Cognition

Lecture 9: Lab in Human Cognition. Todd M. Gureckis Department of Psychology New York University

Effective Intentions: The Power of Conscious Will

Consciousness (Response to the Hard Problem)

PSYCHOLOGICAL CONSCIOUSNESS AND PHENOMENAL CONSCIOUSNESS. Overview

Identity theory and eliminative materialism. a) First trend: U. T. Place and Herbert Feigl- mental processes or events such as

Phil 490: Consciousness and the Self Handout [16] Jesse Prinz: Mental Pointing Phenomenal Knowledge Without Concepts

Eliminative materialism

Chapter 7. Mental Representation

Study of Imagery. Banned by behaviorists

Comments on David Rosenthal s Consciousness, Content, and Metacognitive Judgments

Is it ever possible, in being aware of an attribute of one s own body from the inside, to

The scope of perceptual content, II: properties

Am I free? Free will vs. neuroscience

Psychology, Neuroscience, and the Consciousness Dilemma. Katalin Balog

The Developing Viewpoints

Our previous accounts of perceptual experience accepted the phenomenal principle:

Philosophical Review.

24.500/Phil253 topics in philosophy of mind/perceptual experience

Intro to Perception. Dr. Jonathan Pillow Sensation & Perception (PSY 345 / NEU 325) Spring 2017, Princeton University

Explaining an Explanatory Gap Gilbert Harman Princeton University

AP PSYCHOLOGY SUMMER ASSIGNMENT-2017

Intentional Horizons

Is Cognitive Science Special? In what way is it special? Cognitive science is a delicate mixture of the obvious and the incredible

PHILOSOPHY OF MIND AND COGNITIVE SCIENCE PHIL 30400, FALL 2018

Consciousness and Intrinsic Higher- Order Content

The Varieties of Self- Awareness. David Chalmers

Arguments for intentionalism

Perception LECTURE FOUR MICHAELMAS Dr Maarten Steenhagen

Chapter Six Functionalism: Antecedent Influences. The Functionalist Protest. Forerunners of Functionalism

The Standard Theory of Conscious Perception

H.O.T. Theory, Concepts, and Synesthesia: A Reply to Adams and Shreve

The Nature of Consciousness Handout [6] William Lycan: Consciousness as Internal Monitoring

Computation and Consciousness

Philosophy of Animal Minds

1 MENTAL IMAGERY. 1.1 What Mental Imagery Is

Empty Thoughts: An Explanatory Problem for Higher-Order Theories of Consciousness

Skepticism about perceptual content

HIGHER-ORDER THEORIES OF CONSCIOUSNESS

History and Approaches

Materialism and the Mind and Body Problem:

Chapter Six Functionalism: Antecedent Influences. The Functionalist Protest. Forerunners of Functionalism

Appearance properties

How do Categories Work?

PSYCHOLOGY. Prof. Riyadh Al_Azzawi F.R.C.Psych

Psych 401: Exam 1 Review. Be familiar with the role of philosophy and physiology in the development of psychology

Color Science and Spectrum Inversion: A Reply to Nida-Rümelin

Naturalizing the Mind, by Fred Dretske. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, Pp. 208.

Autonomy as a Positive Value Some Conceptual Prerequisites Niklas Juth Dept. of Philosophy, Göteborg University

P H E N O M E N O L O G Y

Comments on Cohen, Mizrahi, Maund, and Levine * Alex Byrne, MIT

There are two types of presuppositions that are significant in NLP: linguistic presuppositions and epistemological presuppositions.

U. T. Place, Is consciousness a brain process?

SLIDE 2: PSYCHOLOGY. By: Sondos Al-Najjar

Mental imagery scale: an application in the field of art didactics

Introducing Psychology $

Philosophical and Theoretical Roots of Therapeutic Psychology. Theoretical Foundations of Psychology (M0542)

NOË, A. Out of our heads: why you are not your brain, and other lessons from the biology of consciousness. Nova York: Hill and Wang, 2010, 232 p.

From where does the content of a certain geo-communication come? semiotics in web-based geo-communication Brodersen, Lars

Part I History & Conceptualizations

The Vote! Winners. $100 Question from Ch 10 11/16/11

Introduction to NLP. Dr Alan Jones PhD. Inspire NLP 2016

Dikran J. Martin Psychology 111

Ross Jeffries Speed Seduction

Oman College of Management & Technology

An Alternative Explanation for Premack & Premack

Physiological Function, Health and Medical Theory

Review of Tim Bayne s The Unity of Consciousness

Psychology, Fifth Edition, James S. Nairne Chapter 1. Chapter 1 An Introduction to Psychology

Lecturer: Rob van der Willigen 11/9/08

AI and Philosophy. Gilbert Harman. Tuesday, December 4, Early Work in Computational Linguistics (including MT Lab at MIT)

COMP329 Robotics and Autonomous Systems Lecture 15: Agents and Intentions. Dr Terry R. Payne Department of Computer Science

Lecturer: Rob van der Willigen 11/9/08

Consciousness and Theory of Mind: a Common Theory?

Psychology of visual perception C O M M U N I C A T I O N D E S I G N, A N I M A T E D I M A G E 2014/2015

Over the years, philosophers, psychoanalysts, psychologists, psychiatrists,

Metaphysics and consciousness. Mary ET Boyle, Ph. D. Department of Cognitive Science UCSD

CR 1: History & Approaches. This Curricular Requirement can be found in Chapter 1 of Myers Psychology for AP.

AFFECTS, MOODS, EMOTIONS, AND BELONGING

Psychology, Neuroscience, and the Consciousness Dilemma. Katalin Balog. Draft (comments welcome)

MIND BODY Problem. distinction: body soul. Mind-Body Problem 1. Psychology of Religous. Beliefs

Papineau on the Actualist HOT Theory of Consciousness

PHIL 512: Seminar in Philosophy of Mind

An overview of the verbatim argument in Husserl s Fifth Cartesian Meditation

Phenomenal content. PHIL April 15, 2012

PSY111 Notes. For Session 3, Carrington Melbourne. C. Melbourne PSY111 Session 3,

The Physiological Mechanism Underlying the Glo to Sleep Effect Technical Report No.GTS

RapidRapport. Action Journal. with Michael Bernoff

Managing Behaviors: Start with Yourself!

REVIEW OF ATTENTION, NOT SELF BY JONARDON GANERI

On A Distinction Between Access and Phenomenal Consciousness

Behaviorism: An essential survival tool for practitioners in autism

Neurological Basis for Placbeo effect*

Study Guide for Why We Overeat and How to Stop Copyright 2017, Elizabeth Babcock, LCSW

Transcription:

Mental Imagery: philosophical foundations Peter Ekberg, PhD student in Theoretical Philosophy Department of Philosophy, Göteborg University 1. The History of Imagery in Philosophy Questions of how human thought is construed and executed are as ancient as philosophy itself. Aristotle, for instance, believed that every thought carries an image and that consequently thought without images is impossible (Leahy 2000). In On Memory and Recollection Aristotle describes imagery as the persistence of a percept after the object originally causing it has gone. This position is not to be confused with the notion that the persistence of the percept comes in the form of a mental image, in the sense of a picture in the brain or mind. Aristotle s position is not philosophically problematic in this sense; he simply states the existence of the phenomenon in a pre-theorizing manner. The shift towards more problematic philosophical waters would emerge later with the mental images notion. The resemblance theory, for instance, is one such problematic notion. The idea is that imagery of an object is (1) an inner mental image of the object and also (2) that the mental image represents 1 the object through resemblance, i.e. that the images of the mind resemble the objects they stand for and they stand for those objects because they resemble them. Clearly, thus, we distinguish imagery and imagination in the pre-theorizing context from the more philosophically burdened term mental images. Though the representational explanations vary it 1 Present in most imagery debates is the above mentioned term representation. Since we do not carry the world in our heads some form of representing seems necessary. It is tempting to conclude that when I think of my childhood home I really think of my representation of my childhood home. As we will see in the last section the debate concerning representational issues is very much alive. 1

is safe to say that imagery is a bearer of intentionality; the mental imagery is always imagery of something. The imagery phenomenon has only been partially analyzed throughout the history of philosophy, e.g. the Stoics, Augustine, Descartes, Leibniz, Locke, Hume, Kant, Brentano, Husserl, Wittgenstein, Sartre and Collingwood. Contemporary philosopher Colin McGinn (2004), states the following in regard to the state of imagery in philosophy: Seldom is the topic handled in a comprehensive an impartial manner simply as a subject of intrinsic interest, with many aspects and varieties. It is a phenomenon of the human mind that needs to be analyzed and understood in its own right. It is also elusive, tantalizing, and fascinating. Thinking about it calls for rigor and speculation, clarity and tolerance of obscurity. It positively attracts error and confusion. Despite the familiarity and everydayness of imagery the topic turns out to be extremely elusive. David Hume, for instance, claimed that the difference between perception and images was merely a matter of clarity or vivacity, i.e. degree: Images, according to Hume were the faint ideas left behind after the more forceful impressions (sensory experience) had made their mark upon the mind. Thomas Hobbes poses a similar idea in Leviathan: after the object is removed or the eye shut, we still retain an image of the thing seen, though more obscure than when we see it. Ludwig Wittgenstein thought differently. In Zettel sec. 621, we are provided with a list of differences between images and percepts (or sensations) and here he points out that their difference is not one of vivacity as Hume and Hobbes suggested. Instead he puts forward (among other postulates) two proposals of special interest to this thesis: (1) that Images tell us nothing, either right or wrong, about the external world and (2) he puts into focus the fact that imagery is subject to the will, something that percepts are not. We cannot choose to see the philosophy department in Göteborg when we open our eyes (without going there), 2

but we can choose to think, or form an image, of the philosophy department regardless of our whereabouts. However, it should be noted that since imagery is subject to the will we may choose to let imagery act as stand in percepts if we decide to divert our attention during dynamic world interaction or are diverted for any other reason. Of course the transfer from percept to dynamic image is often done unconsciously and apparently beyond the range of the will, but at least it can be done willingly, which is the point. Furthermore the stand in percepts acts as if they could tell us something true about the external world, and they most often do. They mimic the dynamics of the world in a way that allows us to navigate flawlessly for limited periods of time relying solely on the dynamic imagery. 2. Modern Empirical Research The problematics of imagery is not solely left up to philosophers. For instance, imagery played a vital part in classical experimental psychology. Following the empiricist philosophical tradition these researchers referred to the imagery phenomenon as ideas. Wilhelm Wundt (1912) took a Humean position when he stated that there is no fundamental difference between the ideas provided by perception and the ideas provided by memory images. It is well worth noting that imagery during this period carried the same representational (intentional) role as it had done earlier in philosophy. William James (1890), contemporary to Wundt considered the idea that thoughts might not consist of visual components as much as the verbal images of inner speech. A version of this idea would surface again during the cognitive revolution of the 1960 s and 1970 s under the name dual coding theory. The idea is that the mind uses two separate classes of mental representation, namely verbal representations and the infamous mental images. Associative processes were deemed to be at work, thus according to the dual coding theory a word gives 3

rise to an image of the object the word represents. Again it is in one sense unproblematic that hearing or reading the words childhood home most often evokes visual memory responses, it is quite another thing to claim that the visual memory responses comes in the form of an image. More recently an interest for the subject matter has arisen in the cognitive sciences, in neuropsychology, and in the philosophy of cognition (Pylyshyn, Kosslyn, Grueter, etc.). For instance there is the Mental Rotation experiment. This is Shepard and Metzlers (1971) blocks rotation example. The experiment was (deemed) demonstrational of the thesis that the greater the angle by which an object had to be rotated with the inner eye, the longer it took to rotate it. The conclusion was made that the objects (the blocks) were represented as three dimensional images in the brain. Another example is the Mental Scanning experiment. This is Kosslyn et al s Island experiment where it was argued that the time to travel in thought between objects on an imagined map correlates to the distances of the real map (the real image). According to Kosslyn who is the best-known representative of the pictorialist approach, this experiment speaks in favour of the Image as Picture notion. Kosslyn model of picture-like mental imagery includes neurological evidence such as PET results (PET stands for Positron Emission Tomography. The PET-technique gives us strong indications of the activity of specific brain regions by the study of increase in blood flow to these localizations) and studies of brain lesioned patients. According to Kosslyn s results mental images and perceptual images are mostly processed in the same regions of the brain. In the so called visual buffer (a name coined by Kosslyn) in the visual cortex a graphical image of the imagined object is made. The current debate is by no means closed. For instance Zenon Pylyshyn (2003) provides strong arguments against the picture theory, strongly influenced by the verbal representation theory mentioned above. 4

3. The Contemporary Philosophical/Scientific Debate Above we have gained some acquaintance with the scientific field of imagery. What do philosophers have to say on the matter? In typical philosophical fashion it is more or less generally stated that the images of the mind appear to be unlike images in several ways. According to Tye (1999) three basic objections have been raised by philosophers against the pictorial attitude. (1) Objections to the sense of the view, (2) Objections of indeterminacy, (3) Objections to the evidential underpinnings of the view. Below I present an account of the objections in a modified version with several examples. The first objection states that there is the old homunculus misleading notion to account for. If imagery is like images that we perceive with our eyes, then who perceives the mental images, a little man in our minds? The answer is definitely negative; there is no man and no third eye in the brain to behold the imagery, and there are no images either for that matter. Indeed the questions of how the conglomerates of nerve cells in the brain represent the world is a lively part of contemporary philosophical and neurological research, The second objection puts into focus that details of the imagery tend to be indistinct as the indeterminacy example of the tiger s stripes show. In a real picture (a photograph or painting) of a tiger the number of stripes is easily determined. Our imaginary tiger has an indeterminable number of stripes. Of course we may decide that our imaginary tiger has exactly three stripes, but this only proves the point: we can not decide for the picture of a tiger to have the number of stripes we desire. If we imagine a wall filled with red dots the same problem arise; we can not determine the exact number of dots, something that is easily done if we deal with a real picture. The third objection is mainly that traditionally in philosophy imagery has been examined through introspection. Introspection is in itself a very problematic 5

notion in many ways, but the main point in regard to imagery is that introspection does not show us any mental pictures but only tells us that the imagery experience is phenomenologically similar to the experience of perception. References: Aristotle On memory and reminiscience, translated by J.I: Beare, Internet resource: http://psychclassics.yorku.ca/aristotle/memory.htm. Originally published in Ross, W. D. (Ed.) (1930). The works of Aristotle (vol. 3). Oxford: Clarendon Press. Ekberg P. (2005) The Spatial abilities of Humans and other Beasts, Master of Arts essay, Department of philosophy, Göteborg University. Grueter T (2006), Picture This, How does the brain create images in our minds?, Scientific American Mind, vol 17, Number 1, Feb/March. Hobbes T (1651) Leviathan ebook, Internet resource: http://www.4literature.net/thomas_hobbes/leviathan/2.html Hume D (1739) A Treatise of Human Nature, Being an attempt to introduce the experimental method of reasoning into moral subjects. Book One: Of the understanding, Part 1. Internet resource: ebook, www.class.uidaho.edu/mickelsen/toc/hume%20treatise%20toc.htm#** James W. (1890) The Principles of Psychology. New York: Holt. Internet resource: http://psychclassics.yorku.ca/james/principles/index.htm Kosslyn S.M, (1994) Image and Brain, MIT Press Kosslyn (1978) Visual images preserve mewtric spatial information: Evidence from studies of image scanning. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and performance, 4, 47-60. Leahy TM (2000) A history of psychology, Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall. Malmgren H, (2005) Presentations, re-presentations and learning. Festskrift Filosofiska Institutionen vid Göteborgs Universitet, 2005 Marks D.F, (1999). Consciousness, Mental Imagery and Action. British Journal of Psychology (90) 567-585. McGinn C. (2004) Mindsight, Image, Dream, Meaning, Harvard University Press 6

Pylyshyn Z, (2003) Return of the mental image: are there really pictures in the brain? Trends of cognitive science, 7, (2003) 113-118 Shepard & Metzler (1971) Mental Rotation of Three-Dimensional Objects, Science v171 n3972 p701-703 Tye M (1999) Image indeterminacy: The picture theory of images and the bifurcation of what and where information in higher-level vision. Spatial Representation, problems in Philosophy and Psychology, Ed: Eilan et al. Oxford University Press. Wittgenstein (1967, 1995), Zettel, sec. 621, Bokförlaget Thales, Stockholm Wundt W (1912) Elemente der Völkerpsychologie (Elements of Folk Psychology) Internet resource: http://psychclassics.yorku.ca/wundt/folk/preface.htm 7