REVIEW. P.M. Churchland, Matter Bnd Consciousness. Revised Edition, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1988.

Similar documents
Identity theory and eliminative materialism. a) First trend: U. T. Place and Herbert Feigl- mental processes or events such as

PHENOMENAL CONSCIUOSNESS: QUALIA & QUINNING QUALIA. Prof. Rajakishore Nath, Department of Humanities & Social Science, IIT Bombay

Empty Thoughts: An Explanatory Problem for Higher-Order Theories of Consciousness

Functionalism. (1) Machine Functionalism

Eliminative materialism

PSYCHOLOGICAL CONSCIOUSNESS AND PHENOMENAL CONSCIOUSNESS. Overview

Perception LECTURE FOUR MICHAELMAS Dr Maarten Steenhagen

Our previous accounts of perceptual experience accepted the phenomenal principle:

Explaining an Explanatory Gap Gilbert Harman Princeton University

Intentional Horizons

A Direct Object of Perception

Key words: Qualia, First Person Perspective, The Hard Problem of Consciousness, and Subjectivity

Comments on David Rosenthal s Consciousness, Content, and Metacognitive Judgments

Naturalizing the Mind, by Fred Dretske. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, Pp. 208.

Effective Intentions: The Power of Conscious Will

U. T. Place, Is consciousness a brain process?

Representational Content and Phenomenal Character

The Conscious Mind. - What is Mind? -No matter. -What is Matter? -Never mind. -Homer Simpson. Misha Sokolov B.A., M.Cog.Sci.

Comments on Cohen, Mizrahi, Maund, and Levine * Alex Byrne, MIT

David Chalmers, The hard problem of consciousness

Can Conscious Experience Affect Brain Activity?

CHAPTER TWO. The Philosophical Approach: Enduring Questions

Stances on the Relations of Psychology to the Brain

Lecture 14. Functionalism

Consciousness and Theory of Mind: a Common Theory?

Computation and Consciousness

What is the relationship between the mind and the brain?

Studying Mind from the Inside

Concerns with Identity Theory. Eliminative Materialism. Eliminative Materialism. Eliminative Materialism Argument

The Nature of Consciousness Handout [6] William Lycan: Consciousness as Internal Monitoring

Robyn Repko Waller, Philosophy of Psychology I Syllabus,

Varieties of Materialism. Behaviourism, Identity theory, and Functionalism

Let s Dance! The Equivocation in Chalmers Dancing Qualia Argument

EMPIRICAL AND EPISTEMOLOGICAL IMPLICATIONS OF AN ENACTIVE SENSORIMOTOR CONTINGENCY THEORY. Celine Geday

A conversation with Professor David Chalmers, May 20, 2016 Participants

Consciousness and Intrinsic Higher- Order Content

Review of Tim Bayne s The Unity of Consciousness

Stances on the Relation of Psychological States to the Brain

24.500/Phil253 topics in philosophy of mind/perceptual experience

Materialism and the Mind and Body Problem:

V71LAR: Locke, Appearance and Reality. TOPIC 2: WHAT IS IT TO PERCEIVE AN OBJECT? Continued...

Consciousness II. Mechanical Consciousness. Carlotta Pavese

Minds or Machines. John Beloff (1988) Intro to Philosophy Professor Douglas Olena

The scope of perceptual content, II: properties

CONSCIOUSNESS. Phil/Psych 256. Chris Eliasmith

On A Distinction Between Access and Phenomenal Consciousness

We Are Not Alone: Perception and the Others

The Varieties of Self- Awareness. David Chalmers

Computational Perception and Cognition

Critical review (Newsletter for Center for Qualitative Methodology) concerning:

Introduction to Philosophy

Behaviorism: Laws of the Observable

Research Ethics and Philosophies

Papineau on the Actualist HOT Theory of Consciousness

Book Review: HUTTO, Daniel and MYIN, Erik, Evolving Enactivism Basic minds meet content (2017, MIT Press, xxvi p.)

The Standard Theory of Conscious Perception

Jerry R. Hobbs. SRI International. Menlo Park, California. rules operating at a symbolic level intermediate between neurophysiology

PHILOSOPHY OF MIND AND COGNITIVE SCIENCE PHIL 30400, FALL 2018

A Difference that Makes a Difference: Welfare and the Equality of Consideration

Social-semiotic externalism in Can robot understand values?

Spectrum inversion and intentionalism

Skepticism about perceptual content

Class #22 - Functionalism Fodor, The Mind-Body Problem

Ch 16. The Problem of Consciousness

Self-Consciousness, Self-Ascription, and the Mental Self

Consciousness : An Integrative Systems Modelling Approach

Critical Thinking Assessment at MCC. How are we doing?

Brainy Brownson & the Body of Brown: The Reduction of Psychological Identity to

CONSCIOUSNESS : AWARENESS, INTENTIONALITY AND PHENOMENALITY

This article, the last in a 4-part series on philosophical problems

REVIEW OF ATTENTION, NOT SELF BY JONARDON GANERI

Neither Brain nor Ghost: A Non-Dualist Alternative to the Mind-Brain Identity Theory. by Teed Rockwell Forthcoming on Bradford Books, MIT press

14 The Nature of Reality

Is integrated information theory viable as a theory of consciousness? George Deane

Lectures I & II : Stimuli and Responses, Environment and Behavior: Where is the Mind? Overview of the Development of Mind and Consciousness.

Is it possible to give a philosophical definition of sexual desire?

AI and Philosophy. Gilbert Harman. Tuesday, December 4, Early Work in Computational Linguistics (including MT Lab at MIT)

Journal of Philosophy and Ethics in Health Care and Medicine, No.6, pp.62-78, August 2012 Scientific Contribution On the Possibility of Explanatory Pl

L6: Overview. with side orders of lecture revision, pokemon, and silly experiments. Dani Navarro

Ontology of Observing: The Biological Foundations of Self-Consciousness and of The Physical Domain of Existence

On Our Experience of Ceasing to Exist

5.8 Departure from cognitivism: dynamical systems

Identity theory and nomological danglers. Day 4 Nature of Mind

Learning Objectives. Learning Objectives 17/03/2016. Chapter 4 Perspectives on Consumer Behavior

The Mental Lives of Zombies

SEARLE AND FUNCTIONALISM. Is the mind software?

ELEMENTS OF PSYCHOPHYSICS Sections VII and XVI. Gustav Theodor Fechner (1860/1912)

Realism and Qualitative Research. Joseph A. Maxwell George Mason University

Psy2005: Applied Research Methods & Ethics in Psychology. Week 14: An Introduction to Qualitative Research

Mind & Body Behaviourism

II. The Behavioral Approach to Understanding Cognition

COHERENCE: THE PRICE IS RIGHT

Jackson and Churchland: Notes on mind and body Philosophy 1 Spring 2006

Functionalist theories of content

CHAPTERS CONSCIOUSNESS, SUBJECTIVITY AND QUALIA

Brain Mechanisms Explain Emotion and Consciousness. Paul Thagard University of Waterloo

Psychology, Neuroscience, and the Consciousness Dilemma. Katalin Balog

Consciousness (Response to the Hard Problem)

Conceptual Change in the Brain Revolution. Paul Thagard University of Waterloo

H.O.T. Theory, Concepts, and Synesthesia: A Reply to Adams and Shreve

Transcription:

REVIEW P.M. Churchland, Matter Bnd Consciousness. Revised Edition, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1988. Philosophy of mind is a lively issue these days. The abandonment of behaviorism, together with the use of computational models in psychology and linguistics and the growth of and philosophical interest in neuroscience has given rise to new approaches to old philosophical problems. In 'Matter and Consciousness~, one of the leading figures in the debate, Paul M. Churchland sketches the state of the art. In this book he does not only overview both the scientific developments and the main philosophical theories often inspired by them, but he also outlines his own position on the substantial issues. The interplay between philosophy of mind and science is reflected throughout the book. Though it can be said to consist of two parts (chapters 1-4 versus chapters 5-7 or 8), the first part philosophical and the second part, scientific, in fact the first part is filled with scientific evidence to decide philosophical problems. Likewise, in the second part scientific theories are confronted with philosophical questions. After an introductory chapter (ch. 2, 'The Ontological Problem'), the problem of the meaning(s) of the terms of our common sense psychological vocabulary (ch. 3, 'The Semantical Problem'), and the related problems of our knowledge of other minds and of our own minds (Ch. 4, 'The Epistemological Problem') are treated. Next, both artificial intelligence (ch. 6) and neuroscience (ch. 7) are overvie'\o.red. The last chapter ('Expanding our Perspective') is announced as 'overtly speculative' (p. 9). It concerns the distribution of intelligence in the universe and the ways in ""hich advances in neuroscience might have an impact on introspection. In the spirit of Quine's plea for a naturalized epistemology, it is one of Churchland's most central convictions that philosophical theories should be judged by the same standards as scientific theories. The main criteria Churchland appeals to, are: (1) coherence (of the philosophical doctrine) with well established scientific theories (2) explanatory and predictive value (3) generality Involving ontological issues, Churchland rejects dualism by invoking criteria (1) and (2). Dualism can't satisfy the first criterion because it is not coherent with evolutionary biology, and it fails by the second criterion because it cannot explain

116 REVIEW how physical causes (drugs, lesia) can affect mental processes. This leads Churchland to materialism. Yet he rejects the once popular 'identity theory', because it lacks generality (criterion 3). By identifying mental states one-to-one with brain states, it overlooks the possibility that non-human or non-organic entities could exhibit mentality. This is of course the classical functionalist argument against the identity theory. Functionalism itself acquires the right sort of generality by type-identifying mental states not physically but functionally. This means that a mental state is seen as belonging to a certain type of mental states because of its functional role, i.e. its relations to environmental stimuli, other mental states and overt behavior. No specification of the nature of the matter in which the state is 'realized' is needed. Thus far, Churchland agrees. He does not, however, fully embrace functionalism. Strange enough, Churchland thinks functionalism is necessarily committed to realism with respect to propositional attitudes and the other posits of folk psychology. Because Churchland expects that it is very unlikely that the categories and laws of folk psychology will match those of a future neuroscientific psychology, folk psychology and also functionalism, fail by the first criterion. So Churchland shows himself an adept of 'eliminative materialism', the theory that says that folk psychology will disappear in the course of the development of neuroscience. It must be remarked that Churchland has a rather narrow view of functionalism, by seeing it tied up so closely with folk psychology. There are philosophers, like D.C. Dennett, who are very sceptical about the fate of folk psychology, but nevertheless defend functionalism. Churchland indeed does the same, and his 'eliminative materialism' could as well have been named 'eliminative functionalism'. This is seen very clearly in his treatment of the semantics of mental (folk psychological) terms. According to Churchland, what is essential to the meaning of mental concepts, is their functional role, i.e. the relations they entertain with terms referring to environment and behavior, and with other mental terms. Churchland argues that the meanings of our ordinary mental concepts are fixed by the laws of folk psychology, which stipulate such causal/functional relations. He thinks this theory of meaning holds both for intentional concepts (concepts referring to states or processes that have a propositional content, e.g. belief states) and for qualitative states (without' propositional content, e.g. pain states). Thus pain, for example, is the state that is caused by bodily damage, that is hated by people, that causes distress, wincing, moaning, and avoidance behavior (p.

REVIEW 117 59). Churchland argues that this semantical theory is supported by the fact that it enables us to explain (remember criterion (1») how mental concepts have the same meaning for different people. Moreover, he claims that it can be used to solve an old epistemological puzzle, the famous 'other minds problem'. It explains how people attach the same meaning to mental terms because it says that knowing the meaning of a mental term involves nothing more than the mastery of a theory. This theory, folk psychology, can be understcx:>d by different people because it is partly grounded in observable phenomena. Terms referring to mental states and processes play the role of theoretical terms. They are not observational terms, yet they are linked to environmental stimuli and overt behavior by the laws of folk psychology that implicitly define them. Thus the seman tical theory is, according to Churchland, superior to theories that tell that the meanings of mental terms consist in the private sensations or feelings they allegedly refer to. Since one can never know whether one's private sensation of pain is the same as another one's, this theory (which Churchland calls 'inner ostentionism') leaves unexplained how people can engage in mutually intelligible conversation about their mental lives. Churchland claims that his semantical theory can also solve the other minds problem. We know that our fellow people are conscious, have beliefs and pains, because the laws of folk psychology truthfully describe, explain and predict their behavior. No further probing into their private experiences is needed, for instantiating a functional theory of pain (for example) is by definition to be - or to be able to be - in pain. Sceptics about other minds surely won't be satisfied "'lith the use Churchland makes of his functionalist semantics to 'solve' their problem. Churchland's neglect of the experiential, qualitative and private aspect8 of mental states or processes, and his stress on causal/functional role will surely be interpreted as begging the question. For they will protest that the other minds pr.0blem does not concern the functional organization of candidate other minds, but precisely their qualia. What is at issue, they will say, is not whether we have evidence that in other people pain plays the same causal/functional role, but whether we have any evidence that whatever plays the role of pain in them feels the same way to them as it feels to us. In some passages of the bcx:>k, Churchland comes quite close to what might be seen as a meeting of the sceptic's objection, by identifying qualia with the material medium "'Therein the functional organization is instantiated. So, on page 40, he proposes to

118 REVIEW identify qualia in humans with spiking frequencies in neural pathways, while in an electromechanical robot qualia might turn out to be identical with spikes in copper pathways. Whatever one might think of this example, I believe it may point a way out of the problem of evidence for analogous qualia in other minds. For indeed, for a materialist (like Churchland), qualia must be properties of brains. Since it is known that people have more or less similarly structured brains, this might be evidence enough that they have similarly feeling qualia. This move, however, has to abandon the functionalist's favourite theme of non-chauvinism, by restricting full mentality to human beings. Another way to reply to the sceptic is to argue that having qualia is a necessary by-product of instantiating a functional organization as complex as that of human beings. Churchland goes some way along this line when he writes: "our functional states (or rather their physical realization) do indeed have an intrinsic nature on which an introspective identification of these states depends" (p.39), and "such intrinsic qualia merely serve as salient features that permit the quick introspective identification of sensations" (p.40) and "sensory qualia are therefore an inevitable concomitant of any system with the kind of functional organization at issue (one that is isomorphic with us -E.M.)" (p.41). It is obvious, however, that the last claim is in no way implied by the former two. Functional states need not to have a qualitative nature in order to be identified (in functional systems). Discriminability seems to be guaranteed by any (physical) difference that the system will react differently to; there is no need for qualia. Thus, this proposal of Churchland is bound not to satisfy the sceptic. In some sense, one can reproach Churchland's theory, and functionalism in general, that it fails by criterion (2): it does not explain why some mental states have qualitative aspects, and how it comes that, in the course of evolution, they have appeared - for functionalism is compatible with the absence of qualia. Churchland's description of qualia as 'salient features that permit the quick introspective identification of sensations', fits in with his general view of self-consciousness and introspection as 'a continuous apprehension of an inner reality, the reality of one's mental states and activity' (p. 73). Thus, he thinks that introspection is very similar to ordinary perception. The only difference lies in the object: whereas outer perception is concerned with external objects, introspective consciousness is concerned with one's brain states. By adopting this point of view, Churchland comes to reject the thesis that introspective judgments are incorrigible. Instead, he argues, they are theory-

REVIEW 119 laden, and the replacement of folk psychology by neuroscience might lead to a refinement of our introspective skills. I think Churchland's theories of introspective consciousness are vulnerable to Rylean objections invoking infinite regresses. For qualia are normally considered to be the inner asp~cts of ordinary outer perception, and so it seems fruitless to use the model of outer perception to describe qualia themselves. As said, besides this mainly philosophical bulk, the book contains introductory chapters on both artificial intelligence and neuroscience. They are preceded by a chapter on 'The Methodological Problem' wherein different methodological choices these sciences make are discussed (it also contains a short discussion of phenomenology and,methodological behaviorism). Chapter 6 (on artificial intelligence) and chapter 7 (on neuroscience) serve their purposes as short introductions. They surely suggest the flavour of both areas and stimulate further reading. The picture that emerges, is that A.I. sees the mind more or less as a patchwork of independent modules, while neuroscience has a more unified view of the mind. This issues from neuroscience's unified account of what representations are, namely vector codings in multidimensional spaces. As has been remarked earlier, Churchland always tries to point out the philosophical implications of the scientific theories he treats. So, the section on cognitive neurobiology contains a sketch of how color-qualia might be stored as vectors in a 'color quality space', for which evidence exists that it is physically realized in the brain (p.148). An important feature of this storing is that our subjective closeness relations between colors (e.g. that orange is between red and yellow) are mirrored in this physical realization. As Churchland notes, this can be interpreted 8S evidence for a non-eliminativist reductionist ontological theory. The last chapter 'Expanding our Perspective' contains, besides a discussion on the probability of extra-terrestrial intelligence, a stimulating comparison of the concepts of life and of intelligence. Whether or not she or he will be convinced by all of Churchland's arguments, any reader of this revised edition of 'MaUer and Consciousness' will have to admit that the bcxjk is a highly informed and very well written introduction both to contemporary philosophy of mind and to Churchland's own contribution to it. Erik Myin Research Assistant NFSR (Belgium) Vrije Universiteit Brussel