Active and Passive Euthanasia

Similar documents
Constraints on Harming and Health Care I: The Doctrine of Doing and Allowing

Research Ethics: a Philosophical Perspective. Dr. Alexandra Couto Lecturer in Philosophy University of Kent

Human Experimentation

Ethics, Euthanasia, and Education. B Robert September 30, 2015

Bonnie Steinbock, PhD University at Albany (emerita) Distinguished Visiting Professor, CUHK Centre for Bioethics Dying Well Workshop 2 2 nd December,

Bill C-407: An Act to Amend the Criminal Code (Right to Die with Dignity)

SHOULD DOCTORS BE ALLOWED TO ASSIST SERIOUSLY ILL PATIENTS WITH SUICIDE?

Prof Kamm s discussion

In Support of a No-exceptions Truth-telling Policy in Medicine

Autonomy as a Positive Value Some Conceptual Prerequisites Niklas Juth Dept. of Philosophy, Göteborg University

Euthanasia Philosophy of Medical Ethics series

I. Preliminaries II. Important Distinctions III. The Combinations

Global Perspectives on Organ Donation

How to stop Someone who is ADDICTED ENABLING

Chapter 1. Dysfunctional Behavioral Cycles

Dementia: involves a progressive loss of cerebral functions. The most common form of dementia is Alzheimer s.

Taking Control of Anger. About Anger

Sooner really isn t better TEENS AND DRINKING:

AFSP SURVIVOR OUTREACH PROGRAM VOLUNTEER TRAINING HANDOUT

Difficult Conversations

Step One for Gamblers

624 N. Broadway, 3rd Floor, Johns Hopkins University, Baltimore, MD 21205, USA THE EMBRYO RESCUE CASE

alone seen a corpse. The case of Monica was very different. For the first time, I became

Why Is It That Men Can t Say What They Mean, Or Do What They Say? - An In Depth Explanation

Subliminal Messages: How Do They Work?

section 6: transitioning away from mental illness

To Live While Squarely Facing Death

We admitted that we were powerless over alcohol that our lives had become unmanageable.

We admitted that we were powerless over alcohol that our lives had become unmanageable. Alcoholics Anonymous (AA) (2001, p. 59)

in March, The Oregon Death With Dignity Act passed a referendum in November,

Living and Dying The State s Way

David Campbell, PhD Ethicist KHSC Palliative Care Rounds April 20, 2018

Focus Words prevention critical pursue alter approach

Physician Aid in Dying: Continuing the Discussion

Half Off, Human Organs for Sale. Human organ selling creates a sense of discomfort in society because it questions the

Ones Way of Thinking. Every day, people make decisions that determine where the next step we take in life will

Moral Permissibility of Active Euthanasia

Seana Shiffrin, Wrongful Life, Procreative Responsibility, and the Significance of Harm

POWERFUL DEPTHS OF THE UNKNOWN

Eliminative materialism

Stress is different for everyone While what happens in the brain and the body is the same for all of us, the precipitating factors are very

Suicide.. Bad Boy Turned Good

Patient Autonomy in Health Care Ethics-A Concept Analysis

15 Common Cognitive Distortions

Audio: In this lecture we are going to address psychology as a science. Slide #2

How to not blow it at On Campus Mock Trial Competition. with Tyler

The Good, the Bad and the Blameworthy: Understanding the Role of Evaluative Reasoning in Folk Psychology. Princeton University

Psychopathy. Phil408P

Why Is Mommy Like She Is?

Depression: More than just the blues

A lmost 30 years ago, James Rachels (writing in what

Euthanasia. Types of Euthanasia. Types of Euthanasia. Current doctrine (law, AMA) Types of Euthanasia

Human Ethics: The Morals behind the Death with Dignity Act: Research Proposal

Transition and Maintenance

STAGES OF ADDICTION. Materials Needed: Stages of Addiction cards, Stages of Addiction handout.

Barriers to concussion reporting. Qualitative Study of Barriers to Concussive Symptom Reporting in High School Athletics

The Zika Virus. What Is Our Catholic Response?

Mastering Emotions. 1. Physiology

The Psychology of Street Photography

Family Connections Validation Skills

Just use the link above to register. Then start with the next slide.

USE THE RATING SCALE BELOW: 0 = NEVER 1 = SELDOM

Suicide Awareness and Prevention

Bellwork. Define patient self-determination Understand legal and ethical issues 1

Of Mice and Men. Euthanasia Synthesis

Psychiatrists Views on Assisted Dying and Psychiatric Patients: a Qualitative Study

FOREVER FREE STOP SMOKING FOR GOOD B O O K L E T. StopSmoking. For Good. What If You Have A Cigarette?

EUTHANASIA, ASSISTED SUICIDE AND THE PROFESSIONAL OBLIGATIONS OF PHYSICIANS

Guiding Questions for Kindred

Physician Assisted Death and Voluntary Active Euthanasia

Reframing Perspectives

What to Do When a Loved One Is Severely Depressed

INTERPERSONAL EFFECTIVENESS

Reduce Tension by Making the Desired Choice Easier

Question: I m worried my child is using illegal drugs, what should I do about it?

RapidRapport. Action Journal. with Michael Bernoff

How to Motivate Clients to Push Through Self-Imposed Boundaries

THE VIRTUE OF JUSTICE

Problem Situation Form for Parents

Medical Aid-in-Dying 4348 Waialae Avenue #927 Honolulu, HI phone CompassionAndChoices.org

Depression. Northumberland, Tyne and Wear NHS Trust (Revised Jan 2002) An Information Leaflet

Euthanasia: Some Critical Remarks

Instructions for Printing Outbreak Scenario Cards:

Understanding Medical Aid in Dying

Depression: what you should know

The science of the mind: investigating mental health Treating addiction

two ways in which things can be colloquially called the same : being that very thing, and not another being like and undistinguishable

PSY 4960/5960 Science vs. Pseudoscience

D.A.R.E Presentation

EXERCISES, QUESTIONS, AND ACTIVITIES My Answers

This is an edited transcript of a telephone interview recorded in March 2010.

Death and Dying. Thanatology

Would genome editing harm or benefit the person born as a result? Prof. Rob Sparrow Philosophy, Monash University.

End-of-Life Care. Might There be a Duty to Die? End of Life Care, Euthanasia, and the Incompetent. Medical Ethics 1

End-of-life decisions

Sexual Feelings. Having sexual feelings is not a choice, but what you do with your feelings is a choice. Let s take a look at this poster.

Why we get hungry: Module 1, Part 1: Full report

suicide Part of the Plainer Language Series

Terms and mindsets: emotional meaning.

Transcription:

Active and Passive Euthanasia 1. Active vs. Passive Euthanasia: Imagine two cases: Withdrawn Treatment Jack is suffering from a terminal disease. He has two weeks to live, and is in extreme, incurable pain. He spends his days in agony, unable to sleep, and asking for death. Seeing that death could be hastened if Jack s I.V. is removed, with Jack s consent the doctor does so. Jack dies a week sooner than expected. Lethal Injection Jill is suffering from a terminal disease. She has two weeks to live, and is in extreme, incurable pain. She spends her days in agony, unable to sleep, and asking for death. One week before her death, the doctor gives Jill a lethal injection with her consent, and her suffering ends. Both of these stories are instances of euthanasia. Euthanasia: Literally, in ancient Greek, good death. The act of bringing about someone s death (directly or indirectly) for their own good. The first is a case of PASSIVE euthanasia, and the second a case of ACTIVE euthanasia. Passive Euthanasia: Indirectly bringing about someone s death (e.g., by withholding or withdrawing treatment) for their own good. Active Euthanasia: Directly bringing about someone s death for their own good. Most people think it would be PERMISSIBLE to withdraw treatment in the first case, but WRONG to administer lethal injection in the second case. Our laws reflect this. At least some form of passive euthanasia is currently legal everywhere in the world, while active euthanasia is illegal in all but six countries (as of 2018, they are: Netherlands, Belgium, Luxembourg, India, Canada, Columbia). 1 Both ordinary ethical intuition as well as the law sees a difference between active and passive euthanasia. But, is there really a moral difference between them? 2. Doing vs. Allowing Harm; or, Killing vs. Letting Die: Most people think it is much worse, morally, to DO harm (or KILL) than to merely ALLOW harm (or LET DIE). When the physician administers a lethal injection, she is KILLING the patient. On the other hand, when the physician withdraws treatment, she is merely LETTING the patient die (and the former is MUCH worse, morally, than the latter). Why would we think this? 1 Also, in the U.S., physician-assisted suicide is legal in 6 states: CA, OR, WA, CO, VT, and HI, as of 2018. 1

In passive euthanasia, the disease is the cause of the death of the patient (we might say that passive euthanasia is merely letting nature run its course ). But, in active euthanasia, the physician causes the death; s/he is directly responsible for the death of a human being. Furthermore, there are cases which seem to clearly demonstrate that doing harm is much worse morally than allowing harm; for instance: Crowded Cliff: You are standing at the edge of a cliff with a crowd of people. The crowd surges, and someone next to you begins to slip over the edge. At the last second, you shove someone else off the edge in order to make room for the slipping person, thus saving their life. Is shoving someone off of the cliff to make room for someone else who is about to fall morally permissible? Most of us would agree, that, CLEARLY it is wrong to kill the one stranger, even if it saves the other s life. This may be an indication that our duty to not DO harm to others is much stronger than our duty to not ALLOW harm to others. 3. Rachels Objection: James Rachels disagrees. He believes that there is no morally relevant difference between doing harm and allowing it. In order to defend this stance, he asks us to consider the following two cases: Bathtub (Smith) Smith stands to gain a large inheritance if anything should happen to his six-year-old cousin. One evening while the child is taking a bath, Smith sneaks into the bathroom and drowns the child. Bathtub (Jones) Jones also stands to gain if anything should happen to his sixyear-old cousin. One evening while the child is taking a bath, Jones sneaks into the bathroom to drown the child. However, just as he enters, the child slips and hits his head, falling face down in the water. Jones is delighted. He stands by, ready to push the child s head back under if necessary, but it is not necessary. The child drowns. Smith is doing harm, or killing the child. Meanwhile, Jones is merely allowing harm, or letting the child die. If there were a morally relevant distinction here, we ought to think that what Smith does is far worse, morally, than what Jones does. But, we do not. What Smith and Jones do seem to be equally morally wrong. (Do you agree?) Therefore, Rachels argues, the do-allow distinction is not a morally relevant one. 2

Rachels argument might be stated as follows: 1. If killing were morally much worse than letting die, then what Smith does to the child would be morally much worse than what Jones does to the child. 2. What Smith does is NOT morally much worse than what Jones does. 3. Therefore, killing is not morally much worse than letting die. Since the killing-letting die distinction was the entire basis for the euthanasia distinction, Rachels concludes that active euthanasia is NOT much worse, morally, than passive euthanasia. Furthermore, if the killing-letting die distinction is really grounded in the distinction between doing and allowing harm, it would not apply to euthanasia: While killing USUALLY harms the victim (by making her worse off). But, euthanasia actually BENEFITS the victim (it actually makes them BETTER off by putting them out of their misery). This is, for instance, why we think it is permissible or even obligatory to put down an animal that is suffering, to put it out of its misery (e.g., putting your dog to sleep at the vet). The intent is to relieve suffering. It is a good deed. Only a monster would allow a dying dog who is in extreme pain, and no longer able move or eat or drink, to lie there for days suffering and dying of hunger, dehydration, and illness. Similarly, if all the human patient has to look forward to is suffering, it would actually be beneficial to them to end their life sooner. 4. Objection to Rachels: Judith Thomson thinks this sort of argument is a bad one. She says it is no better than the following one that proves that cutting off someone s head is no worse than punching someone. Consider two cases: Decapitation Alfrieda knows that if she cuts off Alfred s head he will die, and, wanting him to die, cuts it off. Nose Punch Bertha knows that if she punches Bert in the nose he will die Bert has a peculiar physical condition and, wanting him to die, punches him in the nose. What Alfrieda does is just as wrong as what Bertha does. So, have we proved that there is no moral difference between cutting off someone s head and punching someone in the nose? Not at all, Thomson says. At best, all we have shown is that decapitating someone CAN BE as bad as punching someone in the nose. Obviously, in many (nearly all?) cases, the former is still worse than the latter. Similarly, though Rachels Smith & Jones cases show that allowing harm is SOMETIMES just as wrong as doing harm, this does not entail that they are ALWAYS equivalent. Perhaps doing harm is still USUALLY much worse, morally, than allowing harm. (Recall Crowded Cliff!) 3

5. Against The Legalization of Active Euthanasia: Regardless of how the debate above turns out, let us pretend for a moment that Rachels is correct, and that active euthanasia IS morally permissible. Some argue that, even if that were true, it doesn t matter for, ultimately, active euthanasia should remain illegal because its legalization would lead to BAD CONSEQUENCES. For instance: (1) Erosion of Doctor-Patient Trust: Patients need to be able to visit their doctors knowing that the doctor will not kill them. If patients know that euthanasia is legal, they may fear being put down against their will. This erosion of trust would be disastrous. (Think of those who opposed putting organ donor on your driver s license, for fear that doctors would intentionally allow patients with donor cards to die in order to obtain their organs.) (2) Demand to Justify Continuation of Life: Right now, continuing to live is the default position. If someone wants to seek treatment for their condition, or does not want to be removed from life support, no one questions this choice. Death is not a legally sanctioned option. But, if death is an option, patients may feel some pressure to have to justify their continued existence. This pressure may lead to many patients feeling guilty or incapable of explaining their continued will to live, and therefore be indirectly coerced into euthanasia. (3) The Slippery Slope: Even if we restrict euthanasia to clear-cut cases, such as the patient with the terminal disease who is suffering from agonizing, unrelievable pain, there is a slippery slope. What begins as voluntary active euthanasia in extreme cases may slide easily into voluntary active euthanasia in less extreme cases, and then into non-voluntary (patient in a coma and cannot consent) active euthanasia, and ultimately into INvoluntarily (patient is conscious but has not consented) active euthanasia. Involuntary euthanasia may BEGIN with the APPEARANCE of consent grandparents in a nursing home, or a currently healthy patient diagnosed with cancer subtly pressured into euthanasia because their continued care or treatment is too expensive, etc. (We can imagine, Grandma, at this rate, in a couple of months you ll have no inheritance to leave for your children. Then we ll be footing the bill. I guess they said euthanasia was an option, but don t worry. We ll figure out how to pay for all of this. Euthanasia is not an option as far as we re concerned. But, grandma may feel pressured into concluding that it IS an option maybe THE only option.) But, even worse, we may even someday euthanize the elderly or the sick completely against their will (as in the movie Logan s Run. Check it out if you like old, cheesy sci-fi.) Are these legitimate worries? Why or why not? 4

Finally, here are two more worries about the permissibility of active euthanasia: (4) Valid Consent: Presumably, even if killing a patient is morally permissible, it is only permissible if the patient gives their informed CONSENT. But: Is it even POSSIBLE for someone who is suffering with a terminal illness to give valid consent to being killed? Such a patient may not be able to think clearly, or fully realize the repercussions of what they are asking for. Furthermore, when the alternative to dying is excruciating pain, there do not seem to be any reasonable alternatives to death as such, their request for death may in some sense be COERCED or FORCED upon them by their desire to make the pain stop. (5) Inalienable Rights: Many thing that we have a right to life, and that this life is INALIENABLE. That is, even if we WANT to forfeit that right, ANY attempt to do so is automatically invalid. Consider the right to liberty, for instance. If someone wants to forfeit this right by selling herself into slavery, may she do so? Some say no, claiming that the right to liberty is simply not one that any individual is capable of forfeiting. Is the right to life also like that? 5