The role of linguistic interpretation in human failures of reasoning

Similar documents
Reasoning with Uncertainty. Reasoning with Uncertainty. Bayes Rule. Often, we want to reason from observable information to unobservable information

Representativeness Heuristic and Conjunction Errors. Risk Attitude and Framing Effects

Heuristics & Biases:

Perception Search Evaluation Choice

Standard Logic and Probability Theory as Criteria for True Logical Propositions. Bayesian Logic

On the Conjunction Fallacy in Probability Judgment: New Experimental Evidence

Testing boundary conditions for the conjunction fallacy: Effects of response mode, conceptual focus, and problem type

An Understanding of Role of Heuristic on Investment Decisions

THE CONJUNCTION EFFECT AND CLINICAL JUDGMENT

Experimental Economics Lecture 3: Bayesian updating and cognitive heuristics

Decision-making II judging the likelihood of events

Answer the questions on the handout labeled: Four Famous Reasoning Problems. Try not to remember what you may have read about these problems!

4/26/2017. Things to Consider. Making Decisions and Reasoning. How Did I Choose to Get Out of Bed...and Other Hard Choices

Recognizing Ambiguity

References. Christos A. Ioannou 2/37

8/23/2017. ECON4260 Behavioral Economics. 1 st lecture Introduction, Markets and Uncertainty. Practical matters. Three main topics

ROLE OF HEURISTICS IN RISK MANAGEMENT

Slide 1. Slide 2. Slide 3. Is implies ought: Are there ethical cognitive biases? What are cognitive biases? categories

CS 5306 INFO 5306: Crowdsourcing and. Human Computation. Lecture 10. 9/26/17 Haym Hirsh

First Problem Set: Answers, Discussion and Background

On the Conjunction Fallacy in Probability Judgment: New Experimental Evidence Regarding Linda

Is implies ought: Are there ethical cognitive biases?

On Narrow Norms and Vague Heuristics: A Reply to Kahneman and Tversky (1996)

A Text Corpus Analysis Approach to the Conjunction Fallacy

Probability judgement from samples: accurate estimates and the conjunction fallacy

Are Humans Rational? SymSys 100 April 14, 2011

In press, Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes. Frequency Illusions and Other Fallacies. Steven A. Sloman.

Lecture 10: Psychology of probability: predictable irrationality.

Vagueness, Context Dependence and Interest Relativity

Single-case probabilities and content-neutral norms: a reply to Gigerenzer

The Psychology of Inductive Inference

Lecture 10: Psychology of probability: predictable irrationality.

Cognition 122 (2012) Contents lists available at SciVerse ScienceDirect. Cognition. journal homepage:

What can statistical theory tell us about human cognition? Dan Navarro University of Adelaide

Updating: Learning versus supposing

Probabilistic judgment

The Case Against Deliberative Decision Making

Are We Rational? Lecture 23

7/23/2018. TOWARD BETTER DECISIONS: Behavioral Economics and Palliative Care. How many of you consider yourselves to be rational people?

COGNITIVE BIAS IN PROFESSIONAL JUDGMENT

From Prototypes to Exemplars: Representational Shifts in a Probability Judgment Task

Psychological. Influences on Personal Probability. Chapter 17. Copyright 2005 Brooks/Cole, a division of Thomson Learning, Inc.

COGNITIVE ILLUSIONS RECONSIDERED

We will do a quick review before we get into the content of this week s lecture.

The Frequency Hypothesis and Evolutionary Arguments

The Role of Causal Models in Reasoning Under Uncertainty

Behavioural Issues: Heuristics & Biases; Level-k Reasoning

Oct. 21. Rank the following causes of death in the US from most common to least common:

Bayesian Analysis by Simulation

The Role of Causal Models in Statistical Reasoning

Doing High Quality Field Research. Kim Elsbach University of California, Davis

In what follows, we will assume the existence of a context without stating it.

Argument Analysis Using Bayesian Networks

Inside View Versus Outside View Irregularity Hypothesis Attribute Substitution

Semantic Coherence and Fallacies in Estimating Joint Probabilities

A Description Logic of Typicality for Conceptual Combination

Biases and [Ir]rationality Informatics 1 CG: Lecture 18

Psychological Perspectives on Visualizing Uncertainty. Barbara Tversky Stanford University

Wendy J. Reece (INEEL) Leroy J. Matthews (ISU) Linda K. Burggraff (ISU)

Kahneman, Daniel. Thinking Fast and Slow. New York: Farrar, Straus & Giroux, 2011.

Strategic Decision Making. Steven R. Van Hook, PhD

D F 3 7. beer coke Cognition and Perception. The Wason Selection Task. If P, then Q. If P, then Q

Assignment 4: True or Quasi-Experiment

This article appeared in a journal published by Elsevier. The attached copy is furnished to the author for internal non-commercial research and

Behind Behavioral Economic Man: The Methods and Conflicts Between Two Perspectives

Naturalizing the Mind, by Fred Dretske. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, Pp. 208.

Coherence Theory of Truth as Base for Knowledge Based Systems

On the Evaluation of If p then q Conditionals

The Conjunction and Disjunction Fallacies: Explanations of the Linda Problem by the Equate-to-Differentiate Model

Dilution Effects in Perceptual Information Integration

Commentary on The Erotetic Theory of Attention by Philipp Koralus. Sebastian Watzl

Pragmatics = meaning in context We ll be looking at: Grice s 4 conversational maxims Presupposition

Does providing a subtle reasoning hint remedy the conjunction fallacy?

My Notebook. A space for your private thoughts.

Functionalist theories of content

Do Causal Beliefs Influence the Hot-Hand and the Gambler s Fallacy?

Embedded Implicatures

Tamina Stephenson Class paper for , Topics in the Philosophy of Language (Vagueness, Rayo) Fall 2005 [Revised January 2006]

Narrow Norms of Predication?

Updating: Learning versus supposing

Leader decision making

Reasoning Deduction. Dual-Process Theories of Deductive Reasoning

Our previous accounts of perceptual experience accepted the phenomenal principle:

Behavioral Game Theory

Chapter 11 Decision Making. Syllogism. The Logic

UNIVERSITY OF DUBLIN TRINITY COLLEGE. Faculty of Arts Humanities and Social Sciences. School of Business

The Sounding Board-June 2012

HEURISTICS AND BIASES

An Investigation of Factors Influencing Causal Attributions in Managerial Decision Making

On the provenance of judgments of conditional probability

When Intuition. Differs from Relative Frequency. Chapter 18. Copyright 2005 Brooks/Cole, a division of Thomson Learning, Inc.

Knowledge is rarely absolutely certain. In expert systems we need a way to say that something is probably but not necessarily true.

Cognitive cherry picking: the patchwork process of examining A level essays

Reflexivity vs Transparency in the Study of Consciousness. David Chalmers

Sleeping Beauty goes to the lab: The psychology of self-locating evidence

Percep&on of Risk. Content of the Lectures. Topic 2. Peter Wiedemann

In Search of Prototypes and Feminist Bank-Tellers: Exploring the Representativeness Heuristic

Probability: Psychological Influences and Flawed Intuitive Judgments

Representational Content and Phenomenal Character

TEACHING YOUNG GROWNUPS HOW TO USE BAYESIAN NETWORKS.

Transcription:

The role of linguistic interpretation in human failures of reasoning Salvador Mascarenhas The University of Oxford Ecole Normale Supérieure ESSLLI 2016, week 2, lecture #4 1 The conjunction fallacy Scandinavian peninsula [Slide 4] The Scandinavian peninsula is the European area with the greatest percentage of people with blond hair and blue eyes. This is the case even though (as in Italy) every possible combination of hair and eye color occurs. Suppose we choose at random an individual from the Scandinavian population. Which is more probable? 1. The individual has blond hair. 2. The individual has blond hair and blue eyes. Linda [Slide 5] Linda is 31 years old, single, outspoken, and very bright. She majored in philosophy. As a student, she was deeply concerned with issues of discrimination and social justice, and also participated in anti-nuclear demonstrations. Which is more probable? 1. Linda is a bank teller. 2. Linda is a bank teller and is active in the feminist movement. Conjunction fallacy [Slide 6] About 85% of subjects rank 2. higher than 1. According to probability theory, and taking the strings in 1. and 2. to be interpreted in the most obvious (and naive) way, this is a fallacy. For recall that P(ϕ ψ) P(ϕ) and P(ϕ ψ) P(ψ). Enormous amounts of ink have been spilled on this fallacy. It is certainly Tversky and Kahneman s most famous result, and it has puzzled psychologists, economists, and statisticians for decades. It is also an exception to the trend in psychology I ve been criticizing: this fallacy has actually been investigated somewhat systematically from an interpretation-based perspective 1

The conjunction fallacy in the heuristics and biases tradition [Slide 7] Three classes of experiments by Tversky and Kahneman (1983): 1. Direct transparent: as above, direct comparison between A and A B 2. Direct subtle: A, A B, and a number of (alleged) fillers 3. Indirect: one group sees A B together with (alleged) fillers, another group sees A, B, and (alleged) fillers (Which type of CF effect is most puzzling to you?) T&K s account: 1. Substitution of representativeness question for probability question (caveat: this is not an interpretation-based account) 2. Conjunctive option ranks higher on representativeness than the relevant conjunct Representativeness heuristic [Slide 8] It is [... ] natural and economical for the probability of an event to be evaluated by the degree to which that event is representative of an appropriate mental model [in the sense of prototype]. (Tversky & Kahneman, 1983) Representativeness An assessment of the degree of correspondence between a sample and a population, an instance and a category, an act and an actor. (T&K, 1974) When the token and type can be described in the same terms, representativeness reduces to similarity or prototypicality. The notion can be made precise in terms of prototype theory (Kahneman and Frederick, 2002) and exemplar theory (Nilson, Juslin, and Olsson, 2008). 2 Alternative approaches Probabilities vs. frequencies [Slide 10] There is evidence that the interpretation of what is more probable? is not the expected probabilitytheoretical one. Gigerenzer (1991) shows that, when the problem is stated in terms of explicit frequencies rather than probabilities, conjunction effects all but disappear. Linda is 31 years old, single, outspoken, and very bright. She majored in philosophy. As a student, she was deeply concerned with issues of discrimination and social justice, and also participated in anti-nuclear demonstrations. Which is more probable? 1. Bank tellers: out of 100 2. Bank tellers who are active in the feminist movement: out of 100 2

A simple secondary implicature? [Slide 11] T&K (1983) consider the possibility that bank teller is in fact interpreted as bank teller who is not active in the feminist movement. This would be (to some extent) an absolving interpretation (NB: would still require something like base-rate neglect) They controlled for this by using the variants below 1. Linda is a bank teller whether or not she is active in the feminist movement. 2. Linda is a bank teller and is active in the feminist movement. A simple secondary implicature? [Slide 12] 1. Linda is a bank teller whether or not she is active in the feminist movement. 2. Linda is a bank teller and is active in the feminist movement. Since (1) literally expresses ignorance about whether Linda is a feminist, it is implausible that it be strengthened to not a feminist Conjunction fallacy effects were still found, though the rates decreased: 57% (Asking subjects to bet on the original Linda problem has a comparable mitigating effect: 56% commit the conjunction fallacy) T&K on whether or not [Slide 13] the extension of Linda is a bank teller whether or not she is active in the feminist movement clearly includes the extension of Linda is a bank teller and is active in the feminist movement (Tversky & Kahneman, 1983, p. 299) Does that sound right to you???? Linda is a bankteller and is active in the feminist movement, whether or not she is active in the feminist movement. A primary implicature? [Slide 14] Recall: primary implicatures are of the form it is not the case that the speaker believes that ϕ. They are very difficult to cancel, unlike secondary implicatures So we expect the non-conjunctive option to be interpreted along the lines below, even when we control for the secondary implicature 1. Linda is a bank teller and I have no way of deciding whether she is active in the feminist movement or not. 2. Linda is a bank teller and is active in the feminist movement. Question Is it conjunction-fallacyish to resist a statement of ignorance about something one actually doesn t feel ignorant about? Is it irrational? (See Dulany & Hilton, 1991; Mascarenhas, 2014) 3

An interpretation-based hypothesis for the conjunction fallacy [Slide 15] For a transparent Linda-type problem whose options are A and A B 1. reasoners calculate primary (ignorance) implicatures for the A option, committing one to ignorance about B, 2. reasoners consider that P(B) >.5 (base-rate neglect), 3. option A pays a hefty price in the currency of probabilities because it asserts ignorance about a proposition that reasoners do not believe one is ignorant about. 3 The CF as hypothesis testing The CF within Bayesian confirmation theory [Slide 17] T&K imagine that the primary (hard) task subjects are considering is comparing the probabilities that A and that A B, conditioned on the description of Linda But maybe they are instead asking themselves which hypothesis about Linda (A or A B) best explains the description of Linda. Crupi et al. (2008) prove that a number of different strategies for measuring increase in firmness from the literature derive the observed responses to conjunction fallacy setups as a kind of hypothesis testing. Likelihoods [Slide 18] A very pedestrian form of hypothesis testing turns out to be enough to illustrate the spirit of the account: just look at likelihoods rather than posteriors In this view, subjects conclude reasonably that the hypothesis that Linda is a bankteller and a feminist increases the probability of the given description more than the hypothesis that she is a bankteller. P(B d) P(B F d), but P(d B) < P(d B F) But why should subjects ask themselves a question about confirmation as opposed to a simple question about posteriors? Interpretation to the rescue [Slide 19] The task of conditionalizing on the description of Linda renders the description irrelevant! Any account of pragmatics predicts that hearers will try their best to interpret all of the information they are given in a relevant way So The target task is one that violates a principle of pragmatics. It is therefore expected (and in fact reasonable) for subjects to come up with a related task that maximizes the relevance of the information given in the setup. Testing hypotheses (NB an erotetic process) is an excellent and immediate candidate. 4

4 Representativeness revisited Representativeness revisited [Slide 21] T&K tell us that subjects substitute a question about representativeness for a question about probabilities But these two functions are fundamentally different. Probability is a function from propositions to the real line Representativeness is a function from a pair of an individual and a property to (say, for simplicity s sake) the real line 1. How likely is it that Linda is a bank teller? P(B(l)) 2. How typical an example of a bank teller is Linda? R(B,l) The problem [Slide 22] For the examples studied by T&K, representativeness works more or less straightforwardly because a topical individual is always available and yields a coherent question about representativeness In their examples, the conjunctive option always contains two propositions about the same individual (1) Linda is a bank teller and Clinton will win the presidential election. How likely is (1)? How typical an example of (1) is Linda? OK PROBLEM With respect to what can we ask a representativeness question about (2)? (2) a. It is raining. b. The Goldbach conjecture is true. Properties and individuals or propositions? [Slide 23] Representativeness accounts in the market either predict there should be no conjunction effects for such cases or they cannot evaluate such cases. (This is not to say that representativeness cannot in principle be rescued: define a notion of naive probability inductively (structure-sensitively) that reduces to representativity of the subject with respect to the VP in the base case.) In a pilot study, I tested four scenarios with the following properties. 1. A description of a topical individual t, 2. an unlikely (and unrepresentative) statement about t, 3. a likely statement about something else, 4. the conjunction of these two statements. 5

An example [Slide 24] The Scandinavian peninsula, including Sweden, Norway, and Finland, has a high percentage of people with blond hair and blue eyes. This is the case even though (as in the US) every possible combination of hair and eye color occurs. Suppose we choose at random an individual from the Scandinavian peninsula. Questions (two conditions) To what degree does the individual represent a typical example of the following statement? How likely do you think the following statement is? 1. The individual has dark hair. 2. Norway has universal healthcare. 3. The individual has dark hair, and Norway has universal healthcare. Design [Slide 25] Each subject was assigned either to the representativeness condition or the probability condition Each subject sees four different stories, and rates only one sentence for each story. They were allowed to refuse to answer by saying the question was ill-formed A third group compared the conjunctive option with its unrepresentative/unlikely conjunct Results [Slide 26] 1. The individual has dark hair. 2. Norway has universal healthcare. 3. The individual has dark hair, and Norway has universal healthcare. A between-subjects analysis showed that Representativeness and likelihood did not differ significantly for (1), but differed greatly for (2): likelihood was much greater. Representativeness and likelihood differed significantly for (3). The likelihood judgments displayed a significant conjunction error ((3) > (1)), but representativeness judgments did not. 6

Results [Slide 27] Ratings by target (all stories) 0 1 2 3 4 5 Likelihood Represent.ness A B C Target Just a pilot... [Slide 28] The design needs serious improvement: the question about representativeness was (to my sensibilities) ill formed Though perhaps strangely only a negligible portion of subjects choose the response Cannot answer. But at the very least: we ve shown that conjunction errors exist for sentences where the predictions from representativeness are dubious References Crupi, Vincenzo, Branden Fitelson and Katya Tentori (2008). Probability, confirmation, and the conjunction fallacy. Thinking & Reasoning, 14(2):182 199. Dulany, Don E. and Denis J. Hilton (1991). Conversational implicature, conscious representation, and the conjunction fallacy. Social Cognition, 9(1):85 110. Gigerenzer, Gerd (1991). How to make cognitive illusions disappear: Beyond heuristics and biases. In W. Stroebe and M. Hewstone, editors, European Review of Social Psychology. Chichester, England: Wiley. Kahneman, Daniel and Shane Frederick (2002). Representativeness revisited: attribute substitution in intuitive judgment. In Thomas Gilovich, Dale Griffin and Daniel Kahneman, editors, Heuristics and Biases: The Psychology of Intuitive Judgment, pages 49 81. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Mascarenhas, Salvador (2014). Formal Semantics and the Psychology of Reasoning: Building new bridges and investigating interactions. Ph.D. thesis, New York University. Nilson, Hakan, Peter Juslin and Henrik Olsson (2008). Exemplars in the mist: the cognitive substrate of the representativeness heuristic. Scandinavian Journal of Psychology, 49:201 212. Tentori, Katya, Nicolao Bonini and Daniel Osherson (2004). The conjunction fallacy: a misunderstanding about conjunction? Cognitive Science, 28:467 477. 7

Tversky, Amos and Daniel Kahneman (1974). Judgment under uncertainty: heuristics and biases. Science, 185:1124 1131. Tversky, Amos and Daniel Kahneman (1983). Extensional versus intuitive reasoning: the conjunction fallacy in probability judgment. Psychological Review, 90:293 315. 8