Supplementary Material for Malle, Knobe, and Nelson (2007). Actor-observer asymmetries in explanations of behavior: New answers to an old question.

Similar documents
Intentional Action and Side Effects in Ordinary Language. The chairman of the board of a company has decided to implement

Actor Observer Asymmetries in Explanations of Behavior: New Answers to an Old Question

The Practice of Statistics 1 Week 2: Relationships and Data Collection

Whose psychological concepts?

Eliminative materialism

04/12/2014. Research Methods in Psychology. Chapter 6: Independent Groups Designs. What is your ideas? Testing

FUNCTIONAL CONSISTENCY IN THE FACE OF TOPOGRAPHICAL CHANGE IN ARTICULATED THOUGHTS Kennon Kashima

Why do Psychologists Perform Research?

Understanding Your Coding Feedback

The Good, the Bad and the Blameworthy: Understanding the Role of Evaluative Reasoning in Folk Psychology. Princeton University

Self and Other in the Explanation of Behavior: 30 Years Later

Asking & Answering Sociological Questions

33 Multiple choice questions

Self-Consciousness and its Effects on Dissonance-Evoking Behavior

Spontaneous Trait Inferences Are Bound to Actors Faces: Evidence From a False Recognition Paradigm

Chapter 11 Nonexperimental Quantitative Research Steps in Nonexperimental Research

State of Connecticut Department of Education Division of Teaching and Learning Programs and Services Bureau of Special Education

Implicit Information in Directionality of Verbal Probability Expressions

Research Methods in Human Computer Interaction by J. Lazar, J.H. Feng and H. Hochheiser (2010)

THE FORMATION OF FALSE MEMORIES LOFTUS AND PECKRILL (1995)

2 Critical thinking guidelines

Attributions as Behaviour Explanations: Towards a New Theory

The Role of Modeling and Feedback in. Task Performance and the Development of Self-Efficacy. Skidmore College

Hearing Voices Network Mini Facilitation Training

Testing the Persuasiveness of the Oklahoma Academy of Science Statement on Science, Religion, and Teaching Evolution

PSYCHOLOGICAL CONSCIOUSNESS AND PHENOMENAL CONSCIOUSNESS. Overview

Research Process. the Research Loop. Now might be a good time to review the decisions made when conducting any research project.

The good ship Theseus: The effect of valence on object identity judgments

the examples she used with her arguments were good ones because they lead the reader to the answer concerning the thesis statement.

It is often implied, and sometimes explicitly asserted, that folk psychology is best

Lecture 3. Previous lecture. Learning outcomes of lecture 3. Today. Trustworthiness in Fixed Design Research. Class question - Causality

Supplementary experiment: neutral faces. This supplementary experiment had originally served as a pilot test of whether participants

Attention to Behavioral Events During Interaction: Two Actor Observer Gaps and Three Attempts to Close Them

Do misery and happiness both love company? The emotional consequences of listening to experiences shared by others.

Underlying Theory & Basic Issues

Expert Strategies for Working with Anxiety

Chapter 11. Experimental Design: One-Way Independent Samples Design

Organizing Scientific Thinking Using the QuALMRI Framework

In this chapter we discuss validity issues for quantitative research and for qualitative research.

Emotions as Evaluative Feelings. Bennett Helm (2009) Slides by Jeremiah Tillman

When Your Partner s Actions Seem Selfish, Inconsiderate, Immature, Inappropriate, or Bad in Some Other Way

CHAPTER 3 METHOD AND PROCEDURE

VERDIN MANUSCRIPT REVIEW HISTORY REVISION NOTES FROM AUTHORS (ROUND 2)

Audio: In this lecture we are going to address psychology as a science. Slide #2

EVALUATING GATEKEEPER TRAINING EFFECTIVENESS: Use of Case Vignettes

Meeting someone with disabilities etiquette

Mindful Beings: Visitors Descriptions of Emotions, Intelligence, Consciousness, Creativity, and Mind. Joyce Ma. January 2002

Apes submentalise. Cecilia Heyes. All Souls College and Department of Experimental Psychology. University of Oxford. Oxford OX1 4AL.

Teresa Anderson-Harper

Chapter 1 Chapter 1. Chapter 1 Chapter 1. Chapter 1 Chapter 1. Chapter 1 Chapter 1. Chapter 1 Chapter 1

This excerpt from. Intentions and Intentionality. Bertram F. Malle, Louis J. Moses and Dare A. Baldwin, editors The MIT Press.

CONTENT ANALYSIS OF COGNITIVE BIAS: DEVELOPMENT OF A STANDARDIZED MEASURE Heather M. Hartman-Hall David A. F. Haaga

CHAPTER 6 CONCEPTUAL DEVELOPMENT

The Grateful Disposition: Links to Patterns of Attribution for Positive Events. Sharon L. Brion. Michael E. McCullough. Southern Methodist University

Science is a way of learning about the natural world by observing things, asking questions, proposing answers, and testing those answers.

Actor-Observer Bias One of the most established phenomenon in social psychology YOUR behavior is attributed to OTHER S behavior is attributed to

Personal Philosophy of Leadership Kerri Young Leaders 481

Gamble Evaluation and Evoked Reference Sets: Why Adding a Small Loss to a Gamble Increases Its Attractiveness. Draft of August 20, 2016

Living My Best Life. Today, after more than 30 years of struggling just to survive, Lynn is in a very different space.

The Logic of Data Analysis Using Statistical Techniques M. E. Swisher, 2016

Chapter Eight: Multivariate Analysis

Probabilities and Research. Statistics

Instructional Goals in Psychology Psychology students Understanding of the Scientific Foundation of the Discipline

Study on Gender in Physics

Changing the Status Quo: Industry Leaders Perceptions of Gender in Family Films. Executive Summary * Stacy L. Smith, PhD

EMPATHY AND COMMUNICATION A MODEL OF EMPATHY DEVELOPMENT

The social brain. We saw that people are better than chance at predicting a partner s cooperation. But how?

Chapter Eight: Multivariate Analysis

Heavy Smokers', Light Smokers', and Nonsmokers' Beliefs About Cigarette Smoking

Student Success Guide

Introduction to Research Methods

Interviews IAEA. International Atomic Energy Agency

individual differences strong situation interactional psychology locus of control personality general self-efficacy trait theory self-esteem

The Scientific Method

Effective Intentions: The Power of Conscious Will

The! Lie Detection Cheat Sheet!

Behaviorism: Laws of the Observable

Behaviorism: An essential survival tool for practitioners in autism

Chapter 02 Lecture Outline

Concerns with Identity Theory. Eliminative Materialism. Eliminative Materialism. Eliminative Materialism Argument

Incorporating quantitative information into a linear ordering" GEORGE R. POTTS Dartmouth College, Hanover, New Hampshire 03755

Acceptance of Help as a Function of Similarity of the Potential Helper and Opportunity To Repay'

Conventional questionnaire

4. gaze direction and decisions How does gaze direction affect decision-making?

Interviewing Skills and Strategy Global Connections Large Churches Forum 24 June 2010

Search Inside Yourself. Mindfulness-Based Emotional Intelligence for Leaders. Day 2

SUPPLEMENTARY INFORMATION

INTRODUCTION TO SYMBOLIC INTERACTION: SYMBOLIC INTERACTION, PERSPECTIVES AND REFERENCE GROUPS LECTURE OUTLINE

Module 8: Medical and Mental Health Care of CSEC Victims

Time to Give Up the Dogmas of Attribution: An Alternative Theory of Behavior Explanation

Autonomy as a Positive Value Some Conceptual Prerequisites Niklas Juth Dept. of Philosophy, Göteborg University

Social Biases and Pressures. Critical Thinking

PUBLIC OPINION, THE MASS MEDIA, AND B.F. SKINNER. Public Opinion

Ross Jeffries Speed Seduction

School of Psychology. Professor Richard Kemp. Cognitive Bias: Psychology and Forensic Science

Controlled Test of the Analgesic and Relaxant Properties of Nitrous Oxide

Gender Differences Associated With Memory Recall. By Lee Morgan Gunn. Oxford May 2014

INTERVIEWS II: THEORIES AND TECHNIQUES 1. THE HUMANISTIC FRAMEWORK FOR INTERVIEWER SKILLS

Autism and Communication

Everyone asks and answers questions of causation.

Transcription:

Supplementary Material for Malle, Knobe, and Nelson (2007). Actor-observer asymmetries in explanations of behavior: New answers to an old question. Study A1 Bertram F. Malle and Sarah E. Nelson In this study we tested a relatively simple account of actor-observer asymmetries in behavior explanations that observers and actors form explanations with different purposes in mind. Specifically, observers might be primarily interested in predicting the actor s future behavior (e.g., Heider, 1958), whereas actors might be primarily interested in making their own actions understood (Buss, 1978). As a result, observers try to find generally guiding information about the agent that explains not only the current behavior but also related behaviors in the future. When explaining intentional behavior, a search for CHR explanations and, among reasons, a preference for desire reasons, would serve this purpose best; when explaining unintentional behavior, a search for trait causes would serve it best. By contrast, an actor s attempt to make herself understood would favor reason explanations, especially belief reasons that reveal idiosyncratic information and thus render the action intelligible. If this logic is valid, then the actor-observer asymmetries should disappear (or drastically decrease) once both actors and observers provide explanations with the same purpose in mind. Study A1 tested this possibility. Methods Participants and procedure. Fifty-nine undergraduate students completed the experiment in exchange for credit toward an introductory psychology course requirement. Each participant was asked to explain up to six behaviors, roughly half from the actor perspective and half from the observer perspective. The behaviors were selected idiographically from a life event story that the participant had recorded on audiotape at the outset of the study. While the participant completed an unrelated filler task, the experimenter listened to the tape and attempted to select six intentional behaviors mentioned in the story, half of them performed by the participant and half by other people in the story. Then the behaviors were turned into why-questions (e.g., Why did you get up at midnight?, Why did your step mom tell you to come home? ) and posed to the participant in a brief interview. The experimenter emphasized that the participant s answers would be tape-recorded and later played back to another person (the audience ). Purpose manipulation. Instructions that manipulated the purpose of the explanations were randomly assigned across participants. In the understand condition (N = 14), the experimenter emphasized that with your answers about each event, you need to make the

audience understand why the people involved in the event (you or someone else) acted or felt a certain way. So the audience will hear the question about a particular event in the story, then they ll hear your answer, and then they ll indicate how well they understood each relevant person in the story. That may sometimes be difficult for them, but your goal is to help them understand. In the predict condition (N = 12), the experimenter emphasized that with your answers about each event, you need to help the audience predict what happens next in the story right after the event. So they will hear the question about a particular event in the story, then they ll hear your answer, and then they ll have to predict what happens next in the story. That may sometimes be difficult for them, but your goal is to help them predict, without giving it away in your words, what happens next in the story. Two additional conditions were added after some participants reported that it was difficult for them to follow the instructions. In both new conditions, participants received a very brief instruction before each why-question. In the past condition (N = 14), they were asked: You [or other person] did [behavior]. Think about that behavior. Keeping it in mind, now explain why you [other person] did X. In the next condition (N = 15), they were asked: You [or other person] did [behavior]. Think about what you [other person] did next. Keeping this in mind, now explain why you [other person] did X. We assumed that the past and next instructions would be easily comprehensible approximations to the understand and predict conditions, respectively. Coding. All explanations were transcribed from the audiotapes and classified for codability. We excluded 7% of behaviors that had ambiguous agents (primarily we statements) and 1% of answers that were claim backings. A small number of unintentional behaviors were eliminated from analyses because they would not have constituted a useful sample for analysis. The remaining codable explanations were classified according to the F.Ex coding scheme as in all other studies. Analysis. Instruction was a four-level between-subject factor, broken down into three contrasts: complex vs. simple instructions (understand/predict vs. past/next), understand vs. predict, and past vs. next. Each participant provided both actor explanations and observer explanations, and the multiple behaviors that participants explained made it possible to analyze perspective as a within-subject factor. Degrees of freedom varied across analyses because some participants had missing values for certain explanation parameters (e.g., no intentional behavior explanations from the observer perspective).

Results The results were based on a total of 841 explanations for 295 behaviors (276 intentional, 19 unintentional). Actor explanations comprised 55% of all explanations. Folk-conceptual hypotheses. The Reason hypothesis was supported, as actors provided 2.43 reasons and 0.60 CHRs whereas observers provided 1.66 reasons and 1.10 CHRs per intention behavior, F(1, 100) = 25.4, p <.001, d = 1.0. However, this effect did not interact with any of the three instruction contrasts (ps >.30). For behaviors explained by reasons, actors provided 1.74 belief reasons and 0.63 desire reasons whereas observers provided 1.10 belief reasons and 0.57 desire reasons, F(1, 98) = 5.3, p <.05, d = 0.46, supporting the belief hypothesis. Once more, the predicted effect did not interact with any of the three instruction contrasts (ps >.70). For behaviors explained by belief reasons, actors offered 1.57 unmarked beliefs and 0.56 marked beliefs whereas observers offered 1.05 unmarked beliefs and 0.52 marked beliefs, F(1, 87) = 2.8, p <.10, d = 0.37, supporting the marker hypothesis. Again, the effect did not interact with any of the instruction contrasts (ps >.36). Traditional hypotheses. The person-situation hypothesis was tested on causal history of reason explanations and reasons contents. In the first case, actors offered 1.02 person CHRs and and 0.28 situation CHRs whereas observers offered 0.91 person CHRs and 0.52 situation CHRs. This pattern was not significant, F(1, 70) = 1.6, p =.21, and went counter to the hypothesis, d = 0.29. In the second case, actors offered 1.12 reasons with person content and 0.86 reasons with situation content whereas observers offered 0.72 reasons with person content and 1.03 reasons with situation content. This was a significant effect counter to the hypothesis, F(1,98) = 4.8, p <.05, d = 0.44. No interaction with any instruction contrast emerged. The trait hypothesis was tested on person factors in causal history explanations and was not supported, whereby actors used 0.34 traits and 0.85 nontraits wheras observers used 0.46 traits and 0.95 nontraits, F (1, 53) < 1, d = 0.01.

Study A2 Sarah E. Nelson and Bertram F. Malle This study, a shortened and updated version of a first-year project paper submitted to the University of Oregon Psychology Department by Sarah E. Nelson in 1999, was originally designed to test the sensitivity of behavior explanations to individual differences in personal agency beliefs and manipulated agency mindsets (portrayals of human action as free vs. causally determined ). These factors did not have a noteworthy impact on explanations, but the explanation task allowed actor-observer comparisons of intentional action explanations. Method Participants. Participants were 96 college students enrolled in psychology courses at the University of Oregon who participated as part of a course requirement. Procedure and Materials. This study originally consisted of three parts that were treated as separate studies with separate consent forms. Only the third part is of direct relevance here. In that part, participants were asked to remember specific positive and negative intentional actions they or someone else performed and to explain those actions. (In the first part, participants filled out several attitude measures, including one about personal agency. In the second part, they were assigned to read a passage that either argued for causal determinism or free will as the fundamental principle underlying human action. Very few effects of these two variables were found in the data. ) The primary measure requested a set of free-response explanations. The questionnaire consisted of four questions that asked participants to remember times they or someone else performed specific actions and explain why those actions were performed. (See Table 1.) Each subject explained one positive and one negative action in the actor role and one positive and one negative action in the observer role. Thus, role (actor, observer) and valence (positive, negative) were within-subject factors. Order of questions and pairing of perspective with specific behaviors was counterbalanced across participants. Coding of explanations. The explanations were coded according to the F.Ex coding scheme (Malle, 1998/2006), which reliably detects a variety of modes of explanation and types within each mode (Malle, 1999). Two coders classified the explanations. A small number of explanations that falsely construed the target actions as unintentional were eliminated, and

Table 1. Actions that participants were asked to remember and explain Positive Actor Remember a time you helped someone. Remember a time you gave somebody something (not on a special occasion). Negative Remember a time you intentionally took something that wasn t yours (without the other person s permission). Remember a time you intentionally hurt someone (physically or mentally). Observer Remember a time someone helped you. Remember a time someone gave you something (not on a special occasion). Remember a time someone intentionally took something of yours (without your permission). Remember a time someone intentionally hurt you (physically or mentally). so were statements with no explanatory content (e.g., mere evaluations). Reliability was calculated based on the coders initial responses, and disagreements were settled through discussion. Overall agreement for whether a behavior was codable or not was 90%. Comparison of codings revealed 93% agreement (κ =.80) on explanation types (whether an explanation was a reason or a causal history), 98% agreement (κ =.94) on reason type (desire, belief, or valuing), 98% agreement (κ =.96) on mental state markers, 94% agreement (κ =.88) on causal history type (person or situation), and 94% agreement (κ =.90) on trait vs. nontrait. Results In several within-subject analyses of variance, the explanation parameters of interest were examined as a function of actor-observer role. In all cases, the dependent variable was the mean number of explanations given per subject or a proportion of explanations given per subject. Reasons and causal histories. The predicted reason asymmetry was found, F(1,95) = 21.4, p <.001, d = 0.66. Participants gave more reasons as actors (M = 1.57) than as observers (M = 1.17), but they gave more causal histories as observers (M =.60) than as actors (M =.39). Beliefs and desires. Evidence for the belief asymmetry was present but weaker than in other studies, F(1,90) = 2.1, p =.15, d =.22. Actors offered more beliefs (M = 1.16) than observers did (M = 0.91) but not fewer desires (Ms = 0.42 and 0.39 for actors and observers, respectively). This asymmetry was the only one that interacted with valence such that for

positive actions, actors and observers differed substantially and significantly but for negative actions they did not. We are currently testing the replicability of this effect. Marked and unmarked beliefs. The marker asymmetry held reliably and right at the average effect size of previous studies, F(1,70) = 5.5, p <.05, d = 0.41. Traditional asymmetries. Because people explained only intentional actions, the personssituation hypothesis was tested for causal history of reason explanations and for the content of reasons. However, neither of the two tests showed significant person-situation differences (both ds = 0.02). The trait hypothesis was tested for traits in person factors of causal history explanations and showed a strong effect, with actors offering 0.13 traits against 1.06 nontraits and observers offering 0.53 traits against 0.72 nontraits, F(1,15) = 4.1, p =.06, d = 0.77. It should be noted, however, that this results is based on only 16 participants and limited to causal history explanations.