Experimental Testing of Intrinsic Preferences for NonInstrumental Information

Similar documents
Risk Aversion in Games of Chance

Beliefs and Utility - Experimental Evidence on Preferences for Information

Information Cascade Experiments

Appendix: Instructions for Treatment Index B (Human Opponents, With Recommendations)

Belief behavior Smoking is bad for you I smoke

Size of Ellsberg Urn. Emel Filiz-Ozbay, Huseyin Gulen, Yusufcan Masatlioglu, Erkut Ozbay. University of Maryland

Intrinsic Information Preferences and Skewness

Recognizing Ambiguity

Comparative Ignorance and the Ellsberg Paradox

Some Thoughts on the Principle of Revealed Preference 1

More Effort with Less Pay: On Information Avoidance, Belief Design and Performance

Self-Serving Assessments of Fairness and Pretrial Bargaining

Explaining Bargaining Impasse: The Role of Self-Serving Biases

Why do Psychologists Perform Research?

Intrinsic Information Preferences and Skewness

It is Whether You Win or Lose: The Importance of the Overall Probabilities of Winning or Losing in Risky Choice

Cognitive Dissonance under Food-Borne Risk: A Lab Experiment

Rational Choice Theory I: The Foundations of the Theory

Value From Regulatory Fit E. Tory Higgins

On The Correlated Impact Of The Factors Of Risk Aversion On Decision-Making

7 Action. 7.1 Choice. Todd Davies, Decision Behavior: Theory and Evidence (Spring 2010) Version: June 4, 2010, 2:40 pm

Introduction to Behavioral Economics Like the subject matter of behavioral economics, this course is divided into two parts:

Psychological. Influences on Personal Probability. Chapter 17. Copyright 2005 Brooks/Cole, a division of Thomson Learning, Inc.

The Demand For, and Avoidance of, Information

The Way to Choose: How Does Perceived Knowledge Flow

"Games and the Good" Strategy

Deciding Fast and Slow in Risk Decision Making: An Experimental Study

A Rationale for Searching (Imprecise) Health Information

Mini-Course in Behavioral Economics Leeat Yariv. Behavioral Economics - Course Outline

Veronika Grimm, Friederike Mengel. Let me sleep on it: Delay reduces rejection rates in Ultimatum Games RM/10/017

Risky Choice Decisions from a Tri-Reference Point Perspective

Gender specific attitudes towards risk and ambiguity an experimental investigation

Team Acceleration Guide

Online Appendix A. A1 Ability

On the How and Why of Decision Theory. Joint confusions with Bart Lipman

The Influence of Framing Effects and Regret on Health Decision-Making

-electric sandwich press; desk lamp; stopwatch, transistor radio

Making decisions about therapy

C) Use of "credible" sources (experts, authority figures)

GROUP DECISION MAKING IN RISKY ENVIRONMENT ANALYSIS OF GENDER BIAS

Behavioral Game Theory

Risk attitude in decision making: A clash of three approaches

Simpson s paradox (or reversal paradox)

Attitude I. Attitude A. A positive or negative evaluation of a concept B. Attitudes tend to be based on 1)...values 2)...beliefs 3)...

A Belief-Based Account of Decision under Uncertainty. Craig R. Fox, Amos Tversky

Curiosity, Information Gaps, and the Utility of Knowledge

Alternative Payoff Mechanisms for Choice under Risk. by James C. Cox, Vjollca Sadiraj Ulrich Schmidt

Performance in competitive Environments: Gender differences

THE INTEGRITY PROFILING SYSTEM

Doctors Fees in Ireland Following the Change in Reimbursement: Did They Jump?

Bridging the Gap: Predictors of Willingness to Engage in an Intercultural Interaction

DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS AND FINANCE COLLEGE OF BUSINESS AND ECONOMICS UNIVERSITY OF CANTERBURY CHRISTCHURCH, NEW ZEALAND

Academic year Lecture 16 Emotions LECTURE 16 EMOTIONS

Are You a Professional or Just an Engineer? By Kenneth E. Arnold WorleyParsons November, 2014

Endowment Effects in Contests

The effect of decision frame and decision justification on risky choice

PSYC1001 NOTES. Science and Statistics

Behavioral Finance 1-1. Chapter 5 Heuristics and Biases

Multiple Switching Behavior in Multiple Price Lists

Chapter 13 Summary Experiments and Observational Studies

AP STATISTICS 2014 SCORING GUIDELINES

Office of Clinical Research. Information for Participants

Running Head: TRUST INACCURATE INFORMANTS 1. In the Absence of Conflicting Testimony Young Children Trust Inaccurate Informants

This week s issue: UNIT Word Generation. intrinsic commodity practitioner evaluate infer

Take it or leave it: experimental evidence on the effect of time-limited offers on consumer behaviour Robert Sugden* Mengjie Wang* Daniel John Zizzo**

Chapter 13. Experiments and Observational Studies. Copyright 2012, 2008, 2005 Pearson Education, Inc.

How is ethics like logistic regression? Ethics decisions, like statistical inferences, are informative only if they re not too easy or too hard 1

Critical Thinking and Reading Lecture 15

Effects of causal relatedness and uncertainty on integration of outcomes of concurrent decisions

ASSOCIATION FOR CONSUMER RESEARCH

The role of training in experimental auctions

Regression Discontinuity Analysis

Social Identity and Competitiveness

Changing Public Behavior Levers of Change

Lottery winner looks to future

Information Cascade Experiments

5 $3 billion per disease

How Does Analysis of Competing Hypotheses (ACH) Improve Intelligence Analysis?

Dopamine and Reward Prediction Error

Unit 1 History and Methods Chapter 1 Thinking Critically with Psychological Science

Consultation on WHO ART Guidelines

Sleeping Beauty is told the following:

DO WOMEN SHY AWAY FROM COMPETITION? DO MEN COMPETE TOO MUCH?

When Falsification is the Only Path to Truth

Chapter 8: Estimating with Confidence

Do Women Shy Away from Competition? Do Men Compete too Much?

Aspiration Levels and Educational Choices. An experimental study

On Two Points of View Regarding Revealed Preferences and Behavioral Economics

Guilt and Pro-Social Behavior amongst Workers in an Online Labor Market

Paradoxes and Violations of Normative Decision Theory. Jay Simon Defense Resources Management Institute, Naval Postgraduate School

Using Instructional Design Strategies to Foster Curiosity

The Point Illusion: Incorrect Weighting of Absolute Performance in Self-assessments

I. Medical Decision-Making in Situations that Offer Multiple Alternatives

THEORIES OF PERSONALITY II

Anticipated Emotions as Guides to Choice

Experimental Design Notes

Hedging and Ambiguity

Addressing Provider Bias and Needs

More on Methodological Issues in Free-Response Psi Experiments

More Effort with Less Pay: On Information Avoidance, Belief Design and Performance

Transcription:

Experimental Testing of Intrinsic Preferences for NonInstrumental Information By Kfir Eliaz and Andrew Schotter* The classical model of decision making under uncertainty assumes that decision makers care only about final outcomes. The decision makers beliefs enter the model only as a means of weighting the possible material outcomes, yet they do not generate an intrinsic value by themselves. Put differently, they are not part of the domain over which preferences are defined. Consequently, psychological effects of beliefs such as anxiety, suspense, and curiosity are left out of the classical model. A growing trend in the literature argues that the inclusion of beliefs in the domain of preferences accommodates an even richer set of behaviors and allows us to address questions that are left unanswered by the classical model. One particular question that has received much attention is: why do people sometimes avoid information, which is instrumental in making their decisions? For example, why do people who may be at risk of exposure to HIV, the virus that causes AIDS, avoid being tested when such tests are available at no cost (Andrew Caplin and Eliaz 2003)? Such information avoidance is explained by positing that people derive an intrinsic disutility from anticipating a bad outcome. Hence, when deciding whether to obtain information, individuals not only consider the material benefit they could gain from updating their beliefs, but they also consider the implied lottery on their posterior beliefs. This explanation implies the converse, that decision makers may also seek noninstrumental information, i.e., information that will not change their ultimate decision but will allow * Eliaz: Department of Economics, New York University, 269 Mercer St., New York, NY 10003 (e-mail: kfir. eliaz@nyu.edu); Schotter: Department of Economics, New York University, 269 Mercer St., New York, NY 10003 (e-mail: andrew.schotter@nyu.edu). We are most grateful to Andrew Caplin for helpful discussions on this topic. E.g., George A. Akerlof and William T. Dickens (1982), Andrew Caplin and John Leahy (2001, 2004), Markus Brunnermeier and Jonathan Parker (2005), Eliaz and Ran Spiegler (2006). 166 them to refine their priors. This information could be valuable if it reduces the anxiety or suspense of the decision maker as he or she waits for uncertainty to be resolved. In this paper, we suggest an experimental approach to studying these anomalous attitudes toward information. The advantage of an experimental approach is that it allows us to control for the noninstrumentality of information, which is often difficult to determine in real life. To illustrate this, we present an example of an experimental design that tests individuals motives for acquiring information about an irreversible decision that has been made. Specifically, we test the following two hypotheses: (a) when there is a lag between the time a decision has been made and the time all uncertainty about it is resolved, decision makers are willing to pay to refine their priors over the residual uncertainty; and (b) after all uncertainty has been resolved, and the outcome has been revealed, individuals are willing to pay for information on the process that determined that outcome. The first hypothesis is motivated by the idea, first suggested by David M. Kreps and Evan L. Porteus (1978), that individuals may derive an intrinsic value from altering their prior probabilities while they wait for uncertainty to be resolved, either because they want to cut down on the anxiety they face or increase their positive anticipatory feelings. Our second hypothesis is motivated by the idea that individuals may feel better about not having achieved a positive outcome (change in their status quo utility) if they knew that their chances of obtaining the improvement were low to begin with. The experimental exercise we present here builds on our previous work (Eliaz and Schotter 2006, henceforth ES). In that paper, we presented experimental evidence for a confidence effect, the desire of individuals to know the posterior probability that a decision they are about to make is optimal ex post, even when this information has no effect on their decision. The experimental design of ES is simple and

VOL. 97 NO. 2 Experimental Testing and NonInstrumental Information 167 does not require subjects to understand Bayesian updating or engage in strategic thinking to realize that the information offered is noninstrumental for the decision they face. This design also accommodates different questions on the demand for noninstrumental information by either varying the timing in which subjects are offered to pay for information or the timing in which the outcome is revealed. The next section describes the basic experimental design and the different variations that were tested. I. The Experimental Design The instructions described a situation in which $20 was to be placed in one of two boxes, labeled A and B, and subjects were to guess which box contained the money. The process determining where the money is placed is as follows. Imagine two urns, H and L, each containing 100 balls, where each ball is labeled either A or B. Urn L has l. 50 balls labeled A and 100 2 l balls labeled B, while Urn H has h. l balls labeled A and 100 2 h balls labeled B. We select one of the urns at random and draw a ball from that urn. If the ball drawn is labeled A, we place the $20 in box A. Otherwise, we place it in B. Note that no matter which urn is chosen, it is more likely that the $20 is in Box A. All subjects were recruited from the undergraduate population at New York University. They were paid a show-up fee of $3 and were also given an initial endowment of $4, from which they could pay the fees described in the treatments below. The two treatments of interest in ES are the following. In Treatment 1, subjects were asked, before guessing a box, if they were willing to pay a fee to learn which urn would be used to place the $20 in 15 situations. The situations differed in the composition of the two urns (i.e., in the values of h and l) and in the size of the fee (which could either be $0.50, $2 or $4). ES showed that the proportion of subjects who paid for this information was at least 13 percent in all the situations, and rose to 78 percent when h 5 100, l 5 60, and the fee was $0.50. Moreover, the proportion of subjects who paid for the information was increasing in h 2 l and decreasing in the fee (although some subjects were willing to pay $4 for the information). Subjects in Treatment 3 of ES were given the opportunity to pay for information on the urn only after they had guessed a box. Whether or not they agreed to pay, the outcome of the experiment was revealed to them shortly thereafter. This treatment consisted of three sessions in which 16 subjects, in each session, faced only one situation. The three situations that were used were: (a) h 5 100, l 5 60, $0.50 fee; (b) h 5 100, l 5 51, $0.50 fee; and (c) h 5 100, l 5 51, $2 fee. The proportion of subjects who paid for the information in this treatment was substantially lower than in the first treatment. In fact, for situation (a) above, 78 percent of subjects were willing to pay the fee in Treatment 1, while only 6 percent of subjects in Treatment 3 were willing to do so. The experiment we report on adds two new treatments to those described above. The first treatment, Treatment 4, is identical to Treatment 3 except for one variation, the final outcome was revealed three weeks after the date of the experiment, regardless of whether a subject guessed correctly. 2 Hence, for three weeks subjects were in a state of suspense as to whether they had won $20. They could diminish this uncertainty by paying a fee to discover the urn used to place the $20. For this new treatment we recruited 33 subjects who faced the situation in which 78 percent of subjects chose to pay the fee in Treatment 1 of ES, i.e., h 5 100, l 5 60, and the fee was $0.50. Comparisons of the behavior of subjects in Treatments 3 and 4 can be used to test our first hypothesis. In the second new treatment, Treatment 5, the opportunity to pay for information about the urn was given to subjects only after they had guessed a box and were told whether they guessed correctly. As mentioned earlier, the idea was to test whether subjects who did not win would want to know their actual odds of winning. In order to ensure that subjects would not be able to infer these odds from the outcome, we had subjects face a situation in which h 5 80, l 5 51, and the fee was $0.50. The behavior of subjects in this treatment can be used to test our second hypothesis. II. Results The proportion of subjects who paid the fee in Treatments 1 and 3 was 78 percent and 6 percent, 2 Subjects were instructed to leave a self-addressed envelope, which we then used to mail them either $20 or a note saying that their guess was wrong. (At the end of the experiment all subjects were paid whatever balance was left from the initial $7 they received.)

168 AEA PAPERS AND PROCEEDINGS MAY 2007 respectively. This demonstrates that the willingness to pay for information on the urn increases dramatically when the information is offered before the guess is made. A test of proportions easily rejects the hypothesis that the proportion of subjects paying the fee is identical across these two treatments (24.426, p, 0.0000). Hence, when information, which is not instrumental for a given decision, is offered shortly before all uncertainty is resolved, far more subjects are willing to pay for it before that decision is made than after it. A substantial rise in the willingness to pay also occurs when we introduce a delay in the timing in which the outcome is revealed, however. While only 6 percent of the subjects pay the fee in Treatment 3, where the outcome is revealed at the end of the experiment, 18 percent of the subjects paid the fee in Treatment 4, where the outcome was revealed three weeks after the experiment was over. This supports our first hypothesis. Although the difference in proportions is significant only at the 13 percent level, this result suggests that the timing in which uncertainty is resolved might be important, and we might have found significant results had we used a larger prize or allowed for a longer delay. Finally, only a small proportion of subjects in Treatment 5 (2 out of 16) were willing to pay $0.50 to learn ex post their odds of winning. These were subjects who actually guessed correctly, however. This may be explained by an income effect, whereby subjects who earned $20 were willing to pay $0.50 to satisfy their curiosity and learn their odds of winning, whereas those who did not win were unwilling to spend their initial endowment. Consequently, we obtain no evidence in favor of our second hypothesis. Before concluding, it is important to note that we found little or no evidence that our subjects did not realize that the information they were purchasing was, in fact, instrumental since we saw almost no people choosing box B. III. Concluding Remarks This paper is a small piece in a larger program that aims to investigate anomalous attitudes toward information in an attempt to derive behavioral implications of preferences over beliefs. Here, we have focused on the demand for noninstrumental information that may arise from three possible sources: a desire to feel confident when making a decision, a preference for early resolution of uncertainty, and a desire to know ex post what were the odds one faced. While we obtained strong evidence in favor of the first source, we obtained only weak evidence in favor of the second source and no evidence in favor of the third source. We believe that the need to feel confident about one s decision may help explain the tendency of physicians to overprescribe diagnostic tests that are unlikely to change their diagnoses, but merely serve to make them more sure of their recommendations (see the medical references in ES). Further, we expect this effect to be most salient when a decision maker acts as a fiduciary for another person or a principal. In these cases, the agent may be willing to accept risky lotteries over his posterior belief so that he would be able to defend his decisions if they were to turn sour, and he had to explain why he did what he did. Experiments aimed at studying this possible effect of justifiability concerns are likely to be a fruitful area of investigation. Another promising direction for future research would be to study the tendency of individuals to spend more time in search of the best price for some good after they have already purchased that good. In many cases, this tendency may be viewed as another example of a demand for noninstrumental information, as some of the goods for which this ex post search is observed are durable goods (e.g., real estate or cars), which are bought very infrequently. Such ex post search for information is unlikely to be instrumental (used for a future purchase), but may be caused by a confirmatory bias in which individuals derive an intrinsic benefit from obtaining evidence that reinforces their prior belief that a particular state of nature is more likely than another (e.g., that there is no retailer that offers the good they bought at a lower price). 3 References Akerlof, George A., and William T. Dickens. 1982. The Economic Consequences of Cognitive Dissonance. American Economic Review, 72(3): 307 19. 3 See Leeat Yariv (2005) and the references therein.

VOL. 97 NO. 2 Experimental Testing and NonInstrumental Information 169 Brunnermeier, Markus K., and Jonathan A. Parker. 2005. Optimal Expectations. American Economic Review, 95(4): 1092 1118. Caplin, Andrew, and Kfir Eliaz. 2003. AIDS Policy and Psychology: A Mechanism-Design Approach. RAND Journal of Economics, 34(4): 631 46. Caplin, Andrew, and John Leahy. 2001. Psychological Expected Utility Theory and Anticipatory Feelings. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 116(1): 55 79. Caplin, Andrew, and John Leahy. 2004. The Supply of Information by a Concerned Expert. Economic Journal, 114(497): 487 505. Eliaz, Kfir, and Andrew Schotter. 2006. Paying for Confidence: An Experimental Study of Preferences over Beliefs. Unpublished. Eliaz, Kfir, and Ran Spiegler. 2006. Can Anticipatory Feelings Explain Anomalous Choices of Information Sources? Games and Economic Behavior, 56(1): 87 104. Kreps, David M., and Evan L. Porteus. 1978. Temporal Resolution of Uncertainty and Dynamic Choice Theory. Econometrica, 46(1): 185 200. Yariv, Leeat. 2005. I ll See It When I Believe It a Simple Model of Cognitive Consistency. Unpublished.