Augmenting Minimalism: A Deep Prototype Theory. Strevens (2000) argues and defends (2001a and 2001b) causal minimalism, a

Similar documents
Open Research Online The Open University s repository of research publications and other research outputs

9.85 Cognition in Infancy and Early Childhood. Lecture 10: Identity, Essences and Transformation

Deference in Categorisation: Evidence for Essentialism?

Definitions of Nature of Science and Scientific Inquiry that Guide Project ICAN: A Cheat Sheet

What is analytical sociology? And is it the future of sociology?

Finding the Cause: Examining the Role of Qualitative Causal Inference through Categorical Judgments

Categorisation of Sexual Orientation: a Test of Essentialism

Defining emotion: a clinical perspective

Why are different features central for natural kinds and artifacts?: the role of causal status in determining feature centrality

Further Properties of the Priority Rule

24.500/Phil253 topics in philosophy of mind/perceptual experience

Naturalizing the Mind, by Fred Dretske. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, Pp. 208.

Concepts Are Not a Natural Kind* Edouard Machery

Audio: In this lecture we are going to address psychology as a science. Slide #2

Origins of the Belief in Good True Selves. 1- Harvard University. 2- University of Waterloo. 3- Texas A&M University

Cognition 110 (2009) Contents lists available at ScienceDirect. Cognition. journal homepage:

Behaviorism: An essential survival tool for practitioners in autism

Relations between premise similarity and inductive strength

The Common Priors Assumption: A comment on Bargaining and the Nature of War

Essentialist Reasoning and Knowledge Effects on Biological Reasoning in Young Children

U. T. Place, Is consciousness a brain process?

Water is and is not H2O. Kevin Tobia Yale University. George Newman Yale University. Joshua Knobe Yale University

Infants' Agent Individuation: It's what's on the Inside that Counts

What is Psychology? Science versus Intuition 1 a. What is psychology? (from text) b. Note the revision from class:

The Intelligent Design controversy: lessons from psychology and education. forthcoming in Trends in Cognitive Science, February 2006

Douglas L. Medin and Sandra Waxman Northwestern University

Five-year-olds beliefs about the discreteness of category boundaries for animals and artifacts

Durkheim. Durkheim s fundamental task in Rules of the Sociological Method is to lay out

Eliminative materialism

City Research Online. Permanent City Research Online URL:

Are Category Labels Features or Naïve Assumption?

On A Distinction Between Access and Phenomenal Consciousness

MIND BODY Problem. distinction: body soul. Mind-Body Problem 1. Psychology of Religous. Beliefs

Book review of Herbert I. Weisberg: Bias and Causation, Models and Judgment for Valid Comparisons Reviewed by Judea Pearl

THE RELIABILITY OF EYEWITNESS CONFIDENCE 1. Time to Exonerate Eyewitness Memory. John T. Wixted 1. Author Note

Instructor s Test Bank. Social Research Methods

IAT 801 Qualitative Research Methods - Four Different Traditions, Week 2

Papineau on the Actualist HOT Theory of Consciousness

Reduction. Marie I. Kaiser, University of Cologne, Department of Philosophy, Germany,

The Inferential Model of Concepts Joshua Cowley

Causal Determinism and Preschoolers Causal Inferences

NEUROPHILOSOPHICAL FOUNDATIONS 1

Materialism and the Mind and Body Problem:

INTERVIEWS II: THEORIES AND TECHNIQUES 5. CLINICAL APPROACH TO INTERVIEWING PART 1

Concepts and Categories

Category coherence and category-based property induction

1.2. From concrete features to abstract values

Levels of Explanation Reconceived

Selection by Consequences as a Causal Mode in a Science of Behavior. Jay Moore UW-Milwaukee

The DSM-5 Draft: Critique and Recommendations

Perception, Biology, Action, and Knowledge

City, University of London Institutional Repository

Cognitive Modeling. Lecture 9: Intro to Probabilistic Modeling: Rational Analysis. Sharon Goldwater

Competency Rubric Bank for the Sciences (CRBS)

Cognitive Modeling. Mechanistic Modeling. Mechanistic Modeling. Mechanistic Modeling Rational Analysis

Experimental Design. Dewayne E Perry ENS C Empirical Studies in Software Engineering Lecture 8

Chapter Eight: Multivariate Analysis

NEUROPHILOSOPHICAL FOUNDATIONS 1

Temporalization In Causal Modeling. Jonathan Livengood & Karen Zwier TaCitS 06/07/2017

Autonomy as a Positive Value Some Conceptual Prerequisites Niklas Juth Dept. of Philosophy, Göteborg University

My Heart Made Me Do It: Children s Essentialist Beliefs About Heart Transplants

Domain differences in the structure of artifactual and natural categories

The interplay of domain-specific and domain general processes, skills and abilities in the development of science knowledge

Representational Content and Phenomenal Character

Chapter 8 Statistical Principles of Design. Fall 2010

Categorization as causal reasoning

II. The Behavioral Approach to Understanding Cognition

Functionalism. (1) Machine Functionalism

The good ship Theseus: The effect of valence on object identity judgments

Chapter 11 Nonexperimental Quantitative Research Steps in Nonexperimental Research

Cross-cultural similarities in category structure

Chapter Eight: Multivariate Analysis

Consciousness and Theory of Mind: a Common Theory?

VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW IN BRIEF

NEUROPHILOSOPHICAL FOUNDATIONS

COMMENTARY ON KELLY S COSMETIC SURGERY : INTEGRATING VALUES THROUGH THREE ETHICS TESTS

The Logic of Categorization

Running head: INDIVIDUAL DIFFERENCES 1. Why to treat subjects as fixed effects. James S. Adelman. University of Warwick.

PUBLIC OPINION, THE MASS MEDIA, AND B.F. SKINNER. Public Opinion

Assignment 4: True or Quasi-Experiment

PSYCHOLOGICAL CONSCIOUSNESS AND PHENOMENAL CONSCIOUSNESS. Overview

What is Science 2009 What is science?

COHERENCE: THE PRICE IS RIGHT

Cognitive Psychology

Research Ethics and Philosophies

Blackhawk School District

Question 2: Non-parametric Adjustment of an Observational Study

Paper prompts Do either one but not both

Color Science and Spectrum Inversion: A Reply to Nida-Rümelin

Running head: SIMULTANEOUS SUPERIORITY, NOT A SELECTION BIAS 1

In the broadest sense of the word, the definition of research includes any gathering of data, information, and facts for the advancement of knowledge.

hij Teacher Resource Bank

Social and cultural influences on causal models of illness

H.O.T. Theory, Concepts, and Synesthesia: A Reply to Adams and Shreve

Genetic condition decisionmaking and slippery slopes DAVE ARCHARD PHILOSOPHY, QUB

Unit 4 Structure, Function and Information Processing

Persuasive Speech. Persuasive Speaking: Reasoning with Your Audience

David Chalmers, The hard problem of consciousness

The effect of causal knowledge on judgments of the likelihood of unknown features

A Special Place in Our Minds: Examining the Serial Position Effect

Transcription:

Luke Swartz Philosophy 189 Augmenting Minimalism: A Deep Prototype Theory Strevens (2000) argues and defends (2001a and 2001b) causal minimalism, a theory of naïve natural kind categorization in which people make categorization decisions based solely on causal laws, without appealing to essences. Specifically, he describes K-laws, which are statements of the form all K s have P, where K is a category and P is a property. Strevens theory is an attractive alternative to essentialism, but, as he admits himself, minimalism must make certain assumptions about people s naïve theories in order to be meaningful (2001a, p. 74). I shall elaborate and extend on Strevens assumptions, positing a deep prototype theory to allow minimalism to explain data it could not otherwise. What data does minimalism not explain? Specifically, minimalism does not adequately distinguish between those properties of natural kinds that are more relevant to categorization and those that are less relevant to categorization. For example, Ahn (1998) cites a number of studies that show how changes in molecular structure (e.g. chromosomes in biological kinds) were more likely to influence subjects categorization of natural kinds. I ran a similar, informal experiment on five subjects to gauge their categorization on natural kinds, modeled on Keil s (1989) experiments on transformations from raccoons to skunks:

Method Five subjects were recruited by skillful enticements of making a contribution to science. Each was presented, either orally or on paper, with a set of situations involving a scientist who performs various operations on a raccoon. (See Appendix for a list of the situations.) After each situation, subjects were asked to rate to what extent the resulting animal is a skunk either marking on a written Likert-like continuous scale between and, or responding orally on a scale from 1 = not to 10 =. Written answers were converted to the 1 to 10 scale using a ruler. As in Keil (1989), subjects were asked to explain their reasoning. Results Subjects, like those in Keil s study, refused to believe that spraypainting a stripe on a raccoon and adding a skunk smell would make it a skunk (all rated this as a 1, or definitely not a skunk). As the racoon s organs were gradually replaced, however, subjects were more and more willing to say that it is a skunk. Several subjects were especially committed to the importance of the brain: Indeed, two people refused to budge from a 1 rating until it was replaced. As one said, The brain is the key! Does it think like a skunk? After all the raccoon s organs and skin were replaced with those of a skunk, every subject but one rated it as 8 or 9 (i.e. close to definitely a skunk ). Several subject noted that it would retain a raccoon s skeletal structure, and thus did not rate it a 10. Subjects were generally unconvinced by the replacement of reproductive DNA, rating it an average of 1.8; however, replacing all DNA was rated higher (4.6).

The final question, involving DNA replacement and speeding up of metabolic processes, was rated an average of 7.2, nearly as high as the replacement of organs and skin case. Discussion: Implications for Minimalism There definitely seem to be some features (e.g. the brain) that are more important to categorization of natural kinds than others (e.g. skin). How can minimalism attempt to explain this? Recall that minimalism sets up a series of K-laws, such as All raccoons have bushy eyes and All skunks smell. Also recall that, in the absence of relevant, contrary causal data, minimalism suggests that we make our categorization decisions solely on the basis of characteristic observable properties (Strevens 2001a, p. 74). Minimalism easily explains the surface change case (question #1), in which the raccoon is made to look and smell like a skunk: While its surface properties are identical to that of a skunk, we know that these properties (smelliness, having a stripe, etc.) are caused not by being a skunk but by the scientist s having painted them on. That is, the K-laws for skunks are not invoked as causally important, as we have another explanation for what caused the skunk-like surface properties. However, minimalism at least unaugmented by assumptions beyond those articulated in Strevens (2001a) does not account for why people are much more likely to call the animals in later questions skunks. As in the surface change case, one has an alternate explanation for all the observable properties: they are skunk-like not because the animal is a skunk, but rather because a scientist added them. In particular, minimalism does not explain why replacing one property such as skin is less important to categorization decisions than another such as the brain or other internal

organs. There is no inherent reason why minimalism should treat these traits any differently in fact, since the internal organs are generally not observable, one might argue that minimalism holds that they do not play a role in categorization! A minimalist might reply, Well, the subjects know that the skunk organs, skin, etc. all came from a real raccoon, and thus the K-laws hold for the transplanted parts. That is, they have their properties because they are skunk organs. Thus, the more of these parts that you add to the raccoon, the more the skunk K-laws take hold. This is a tempting theory, as it does not need to posit any additional assumptions about categorical reasoning. However, this still doesn t explain why some skunk parts (such as the brain) are more important than others. Ahn s Alternative Ahn (1998) proposes an alternative theory, the causal status hypothesis, in which features that are more causally central are more important to categorization. In simple terms, cause factors are more important than the effect factors that they cause. This might partially explain the importance of the brain, as it causes all (or almost all) behavioral features of a biological category. However, the causal status hypothesis does not explain the importance of other internal organs over skin the observable skin property does not causally depend on internal organs. Ahn also seems committed to essentialism; in Ahn et al. (2001), she and her coauthors argue that people hold essentialist beliefs, and that essentialism explains this feature centrality of cause factors while minimalism does not. If people hold any essentialist beliefs about biological kinds, it is likely to be that DNA is that essence;

however, the questions about DNA replacement revealed that only when the DNA begins to change the raccoon organs into skunk organs were a majority of the subjects willing to classify the animal as a skunk. That is, changing the DNA (the putative essence) was not enough: one has to make that change tantamount to the organ transplant example before people will commit to the animal s skunkhood. If the essentialist theory is correct (and if people do indeed believe that DNA is the basic biological essence), then changing the DNA in the first place should have been enough to sway the subjects. Augmenting Minimalism I propose to augment minimalism so that it can account for differences between different properties in the categorization of natural kinds: In place of Strevens assumption about characteristic observable properties of a natural kind we do the following: Take the entire set of observable properties of a natural kind K ( observable including those properties which are not at the surface level yet are observable to science, such as internal organs) For each property P, we assign a weight W based on its importance to that category For each P, we posit a K-law that all K s have P, adjusted by W (that is, if W is low, then we are less committed to the idea that all K s have P)

The extent to which an object we want to classify corresponds to these weighted K-laws then determines whether it will be classified as an instance of K. Because the weights are similar to those proposed by prototype theory, I call the weighted K-laws the deep prototype. In place of essentialism s potentially-unknowable essence (Figure 1), we augment basic minimalism (Figure 2) with an additional module which helps define what it is to be part of a category in this case, what it is to be a skunk (Figure 3). (Note that the weights of the lines emanating from the deep prototype correspond to the weights thus, having a skunk brain is weighted higher than being smelly or striped.) smelliness Being a skunk Essence of skunkhood stripedness Figure 1: Essentialism (based on Strevens, 2000) Being a skunk smelliness stripedness Figure 2: Basic Minimalism (based on Strevens, 2000)

smelliness Being a skunk stripedness deep skunk prototype skunk brain Figure 3: Minimalism Augmented by Deep Prototype Note that deep does not mean less observable, nor does it (necessarily) mean more causally central, as in Ahn (1998). Rather, deep distinguishes this prototype from that of basic prototype theory, which only appeals to surface properties. Because the deep prototype retains the basic structure of minimalism, it escapes from prototype theory s failure to account for the Keil (1989) experiments: As in Strevens (2000), we can still appeal to causal reasoning to explain why people are not led astray by changes in surface properties. How can one determine the weights used in the prototypes? Since we are attempting to model how people make categorization decisions, we can run empirical tests (such as the informal experiment described above) to determine how important various properties are to various categories. For example, having a human brain may be especially important to being classified as a human (as opposed to another primate), but having a sparrow brain might be less important to being classified as a sparrow (as opposed to another bird).

Conclusion Thus, while basic minimalism fails to adequately explain some of our categorization decisions about natural kinds, one can add an additional assumption to the theory namely, the existence of a deep prototype which increases minimalism s explanatory power without diminishing its other strengths. An enterprising philosophercognitive scientist might be able to extend deep prototype minimalism to cover all natural kinds, and perhaps even artifacts, thus explaining the work of human categorization with a parsimonious, yet empirically-grounded theory.

References Ahn, W. (1998). Why are different features central for natural kinds and artifacts?: The role of causal status in determining feature centrality. Cognition, 69, 135-178. Ahn, W., C. Kalish, S.A. Gelman, D. L. Medin, C. Luhman, S. Atran, J. D. Coley, and P. Shafto. (2001). Why essences are essential in the psychology of concepts: Commentary on Strevens (2000). Cognition, 82, 59-69. Keil, F. (1989). Concepts, kinds and conceptual development. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Strevens, M. (2000). The essentialist aspect of naïve theories. Cognition, 74, 149-175.. (2001a). Only causation matters: reply to Ahn et al. Cognition, 82, 71-76.. (2001b). Further comments on Ahn et al. Available at http://www.stanford.edu/~strevens/research/cogsci/ahnetal/

Appendix: Experiment Questions Place an X on the line where you feel it should be feel free to write in why you think what you think (or just tell the experimenter as you go along). A scientist takes a raccoon, and spraypaints a white stripe on it, and implants a skunk smell -producing device into it. It now looks and smells exactly like a skunk. A scientist takes another raccoon, removes its skin and replaces it with skunk skin, and transplants a skunk smell -producing organ from a skunk. It now looks and smells exactly like a skunk. A scientist takes another raccoon, and replaces all of its internal organs (heart, lungs, liver, etc.) with skunk organs, except for its brain. However, on the outside, it still looks like a raccoon. A scientist takes another raccoon, and replaces all of its internal organs (heart, lungs, liver, etc.) with skunk organs, including its brain. However, on the outside, it still looks like a raccoon.

A scientist takes another raccoon, and replaces all of its internal organs (heart, lungs, liver, etc.) with skunk organs, including its brain. The scientist also replaces its skin with skunk skin. It now looks exactly like a skunk. A scientist takes another raccoon, and replaces its reproductive DNA with skunk DNA, such that if it mates with a skunk, the two animals will produce a skunk. On the outside, it still looks like a raccoon. Is it (the animal whose DNA was replaced) a skunk? A scientist takes another raccoon, and replaces all of its DNA with skunk DNA. On the outside, it still looks like a raccoon. A scientist takes another raccoon, and replaces all of its DNA with skunk DNA. The scientist also replaces its skin with skunk skin. It now looks exactly like a skunk. A scientist takes another raccoon, and replaces all of its DNA with skunk DNA. The animal is given a treatment to speed up its metabolism, such that the new DNA will cause its skin and other organs to gradually be replaced with skunk skin and organs.