Intentional Action and Side Effects in Ordinary Language. The chairman of the board of a company has decided to implement

Similar documents
The Good, the Bad and the Blameworthy: Understanding the Role of Evaluative Reasoning in Folk Psychology. Princeton University

It is often implied, and sometimes explicitly asserted, that folk psychology is best

On Trying to Save the Simple View

The Concept of Intentional Action: A Case Study in the Uses of Folk Psychology * Joshua Knobe UNC-Chapel Hill

intentional action. This received wisdom is challenged by experiments conducted by

Is implies ought: Are there ethical cognitive biases?

Slide 1. Slide 2. Slide 3. Is implies ought: Are there ethical cognitive biases? What are cognitive biases? categories

Directions and Challenges in Studying Folk Concepts and Folk Judgments

Chapter 1. Dysfunctional Behavioral Cycles

Supplementary Material for Malle, Knobe, and Nelson (2007). Actor-observer asymmetries in explanations of behavior: New answers to an old question.

Moral Judgments and Intuitions about Freedom. Jonathan Phillips and Joshua Knobe. [Published in Psychological Inquiry, 20:30-36]

Eliminative materialism

THRIVING ON CHALLENGE NEGATIVE VS. POSITIVE AUTHENTICITY & ABUNDANCE ONLINE COACHING

Building Friendships: Avoid Discounting

LEAVING EVERYONE WITH THE IMPRESSION OF INCREASE The Number One Key to Success

Person as scientist, person as moralist

Mentoring. Awards. Debbie Thie Mentor Chair Person Serena Dr. Largo, FL

HEPATITIS C LESSONS PART 4

A New Angle on the Knobe Effect: Intentionality Correlates with Blame, not with Praise

Disclosing medical errors to patients: Recent developments and future directions

BASIC VOLUME. Elements of Drug Dependence Treatment

National Inspection of services that support looked after children and care leavers

UNDERSTANDING CAPACITY & DECISION-MAKING VIDEO TRANSCRIPT

AFSP SURVIVOR OUTREACH PROGRAM VOLUNTEER TRAINING HANDOUT

SENTENCING ADVOCACY WORKSHOP. Developing Theories and Themes. Ira Mickeberg, Public Defender Training and Consultant, Saratoga Springs, NY

I don t want to be here anymore. I m really worried about Clare. She s been acting different and something s not right

Surprising Connections Between Knowledge and Action: The Robustness of the Epistemic Side-Effect Effect *

Look to see if they can focus on compassionate attention, compassionate thinking and compassionate behaviour. This is how the person brings their

A report about. Anxiety. Easy Read summary

Appreciating Diversity through Winning Colors. Key Words. comfort zone natural preference

Managing Your Emotions

Behaviorism: An essential survival tool for practitioners in autism

Is What is Worse More Likely? The Probabilistic Explanation of the Epistemic Side-Effect Effect

Motivational Interviewing

CHIROPRACTIC ADJUSTMENTS TRIGGER STROKE

Dealing with Complaints and Difficult Customers

Social Biases and Pressures. Critical Thinking

Choosing Life: Empowerment, Action, Results! CLEAR Menu Sessions. Substance Use Risk 5: Drugs, Alcohol, and HIV

A Difference that Makes a Difference: Welfare and the Equality of Consideration

Whose psychological concepts?

Fluoride: Friend or Foe? By Daniel X 5/31/05

BASIC VOLUME. Elements of Drug Dependence Treatment

Reframing Perspectives

15.301/310, Managerial Psychology Prof. Dan Ariely Recitation 8: T test and ANOVA

To conclude, a theory of error must be a theory of the interaction between human performance variability and the situational constraints.

SMS USA PHASE ONE SMS USA BULLETIN BOARD FOCUS GROUP: MODERATOR S GUIDE

ELEPHANT IN THE OFFICE!

Cognition 116 (2010) Contents lists available at ScienceDirect. Cognition. journal homepage:

The mind is everything. What you think, You become. Buddha

Introduction to Research Methods

THE INTEGRITY PROFILING SYSTEM

A Knobe Effect for Belief Ascriptions *

State of Connecticut Department of Education Division of Teaching and Learning Programs and Services Bureau of Special Education

Review of National Disability Insurance Scheme Decisions Practice Direction

The Folk Concept of Intentional Action: Empirical approaches. Florian Cova. Swiss Centre for Affective Sciences, University of Geneva

Helping the smoker decide to quit

Sacking clients: what to do when the relationship breaks down

Resilience and Thriving in the Face of Change and Adversity Presenter: Bill Hefferman. all rights reserved PeopleFirm LLC 2016

Living a Healthy Balanced Life Emotional Balance By Ellen Missah

Effective Intentions: The Power of Conscious Will

Step 2 Challenging negative thoughts "Weeding"

Understanding Drug Addiction & Abuse

Acting intentionally and the side-effect effect: Theory of mind and moral judgment

FOREVER FREE STOP SMOKING FOR GOOD B O O K L E T. StopSmoking. For Good. What If You Have A Cigarette?

WORKSHEET 1 DO YOU HAVE HUNGRY GHOSTS?

Emotions as Evaluative Feelings. Bennett Helm (2009) Slides by Jeremiah Tillman

Connecting to the Guest. Dr. John L. Avella Ed.D Cal State Monterey Bay

Head Up, Bounce Back

Recording Transcript Wendy Down Shift #9 Practice Time August 2018

CAUSING OTHERS TO WANT YOUR LEADERSHIP

5 MISTAKES MIGRAINEURS MAKE

This is an edited transcript of a telephone interview recorded in March 2010.

Unit 3: EXPLORING YOUR LIMITING BELIEFS

Apparently at the moment the Queensland Ombudsman is investigating and is as is the Crime and Misconduct Commission.

Choosing Life: Empowerment, Action, Results! CLEAR Menu Sessions. Substance Use Risk 2: What Are My External Drug and Alcohol Triggers?

Ending Stigma with Recovery Messaging

Table of Contents FOREWORD THE TOP 7 CAUSES OF RUNNING INJURIES 1) GET IN SHAPE TO RUN... DON T RUN TO GET IN SHAPE.

Fears. Thanissaro Bhikkhu April, 2003

Practical Counseling Strategies for Speech-Language Pathologists (3-hour version)

FIGURE 1-The Cognitive Model. Core belief. I m incompetent. Intermediate belief. If I don t understand something perfectly, then I m dumb

Research Designs. Internal Validity

Why Is Mommy Like She Is?

Ep #89: Diets. Full Episode Transcript. Brooke Castillo. With Your Host. The Life Coach School Podcast with Brooke Castillo

Difficult Conversations

When Your Partner s Actions Seem Selfish, Inconsiderate, Immature, Inappropriate, or Bad in Some Other Way

Making Connections: Early Detection Hearing and Intervention through the Medical Home Model Podcast Series

An exploration of the impact of self-harm in an inpatient adolescent setting on staff: A qualitative study

Ex Phil: Free Will. A. Why it Matters Whether Incompatibilism is Intuitive (29-35)

Neighbourhood Connections report on the 2016 External Partner Survey

Exploring YOUR inner-self through Vocal Profiling

Self-Esteem Discussion Points

2/14/18. Richard Wiseman examined thousands of people trying to attain their goals Finish a project Get a job Stop smoking Lose weight

Ingredients of Difficult Conversations

Helping Your Asperger s Adult-Child to Eliminate Thinking Errors

Self-Handicapping Variables and Students' Performance

Interviewing Skills and Strategy Global Connections Large Churches Forum 24 June 2010

How to Work with the Patterns That Sustain Depression

Metabolism is All About Burning Calories. Most people talk about your metabolism like it s all about burning calories.

Trading Success Overcoming Fear In Trading. By Lyle Wright

Increase your Rapport skills in Health and Well-being, Business and Relationships

Transcription:

Intentional Action and Side Effects in Ordinary Language JOSHUA KNOBE Knobe, J. (2003). Intentional Action and Side Effects in Ordinary Language. Analysis, 63, 190-193. The chairman of the board of a company has decided to implement a new program. He believes (1) that the program will make a lot of money for his company and (2) that the program will also produce some other effect x. But the chairman doesn t care at all about effect x. His sole reason for implementing the new program is that he believes it will make a lot of money for the company. In the end, everything proceeds as anticipated: the program makes a lot of money for the company and also produces effect x. Here it appears that, although the chairman foresaw that x would result from his behaviour, he did not care either way whether x actually occurred. Let us say, then, that x was a side-effect of his behaviour. The question I want to address here is: Shall we say that the chairman brought about this side-effect intentionally? This question goes to the heart of a major controversy regarding the proper analysis of the concept of intentional action. So, for example, on Alfred Mele s (2001) analysis, it is always wrong

to say that a side-effect was brought about intentionally. 1 By contrast, on Michael Bratman s (1984; 1987) analysis, there are circumstances under which side-effects can truly be said to have been brought about intentionally. Numerous other authors have come down on one side or the other of this issue. Now, when we encounter a controversy like this one, it can sometimes be helpful to ask ourselves what people would ordinarily say about the situation under discussion. Would people ordinarily say that the side-effects of a behaviour were brought about intentionally? Clearly, ordinary language does not here constitute a court of final appeal. (Even if it turns out that people ordinarily call side-effects intentional, we might conclude that they are truly unintentional.) Still, it does seem plausible that the examination of ordinary language might provide us with some useful guidance about difficult cases like this one. In an earlier publication, the experimental psychologist Bertram Malle and I provided empirical support for the conclusion that people only consider an effect to have been brought about intentionally when the agent was specifically trying to bring about that effect (Malle & Knobe 1997). I now that think that this conclusion was too hasty. The truth is that a person s intuitions as to whether or not a given side-effect was produced intentionally can be influenced by that person s attitude toward the specific sideeffect in question (Harman 1976). Thus, it would be a mistake to ask for a general answer to the question as to whether people will think that an agent intentionally brought about some side-effect x. 1 Mele (2003) now retracts this view in response to an earlier version of the present paper.

People s judgements will depend in a crucial way on what x happens to be. In particular, it will make a great deal of difference whether they think that x is something good or something bad. 1. First Experiment To test this hypothesis, I conducted a simple experiment. Subjects were 78 people spending time in a Manhattan public park. Each subject was randomly assigned to either the harm condition or the help condition. Subjects in the harm condition read the following vignette: The vice-president of a company went to the chairman of the board and said, We are thinking of starting a new program. It will help us increase profits, but it will also harm the environment. The chairman of the board answered, I don t care at all about harming the environment. I just want to make as much profit as I can. Let s start the new program. They started the new program. Sure enough, the environment was harmed. These subjects were then asked to determine how much blame the chairman deserved for what he did (on a scale from 0 to 6) and to say whether they thought the chairman intentionally harmed the environment. Subjects in the help condition received a vignette that was exactly the same, except that the word harm was replaced by help :

The vice-president of a company went to the chairman of the board and said, We are thinking of starting a new program. It will help us increase profits, and it will also help the environment. The chairman of the board answered, I don t care at all about helping the environment. I just want to make as much profit as I can. Let s start the new program. They started the new program. Sure enough, the environment was helped. These subjects were then asked to determine how much praise the chairman deserved (on a scale from 0 to 6) and whether they thought the chairman intentionally helped the environment. As predicted, the two conditions elicited two radically different patterns of responses. In the harm condition, most subjects (82%) said that the agent brought about the side-effect intentionally, whereas in the help condition, most subjects (77%) said that the agent did not bring about the side-effect intentionally. This difference was highly statistically significant χ 2 (1, N = 78) = 27.2, p <.001. 2. Second Experiment Of course, we should be reluctant to reach any general conclusions on the basis of just one experiment. Perhaps the results obtained in experiment 1 can be explained in terms of some highly specific fact about the way people think about corporations and environmental damage. To test the generality of the effect, I therefore ran a second experiment. The vignettes used in this

second experiment had the same basic structure as those used in experiment 1, but the story was transposed from a corporate setting (with a chairman affecting the environment) to a military setting (with a lieutenant affecting a squad of soldiers). Subjects were 42 people spending time in a Manhattan public park. Once again, subjects were randomly assigned to either a harm condition or a help condition. Subjects in the harm condition were asked to read the following vignette: A lieutenant was talking with a sergeant. The lieutenant gave the order: Send your squad to the top of Thompson Hill. The seargent said: But if I send my the squad to the top of Thompson Hill, we ll be moving the men directly into the enemy s line of fire. Some of them will surely be killed! The lieutenant answered: Look, I know that they ll be in the line of fire, and I know that some of them will be killed. But I don t care at all about what happens to our soldiers. All I care about is taking control of Thompson Hill. The squad was sent to the top of Thompson Hill. As expected, the soldiers were moved into the enemy s line of fire, and some of them were killed. These subjects were then asked to determine how much blame the lieutenant deserved for what he did and whether or not he intentionally put the soldiers in the line of fire. Subjects in the help condition received a quite similar vignette:

A lieutenant was talking with a seargent. The lieutenant gave the order: Send your squad to the top of Thompson Hill. The seargent said: If I send my squad to the top of Thompson Hill, we ll be taking the men out of the enemy s line of fire. They ll be rescued! The lieutenant answered: Look, I know that we ll be taking them out of the line of fire, and I know that some of them would have been killed otherwise. But I don t care at all about what happens to our soldiers. All I care about is taking control of Thompson Hill. The squad was sent to the top of Thompson Hill. As expected, the soldiers were taken out of the enemy s line of fire, and they thereby escaped getting killed. These subjects were then asked to determine how much praise the lieutenant deserved for what he did and whether or not he intentionally took the soldiers out of the line of fire. Once again, the two conditions elicited two radically different patterns of responses. In the harm condition, most (77%) subjects said that the agent brought about the side-effect intentionally, whereas in the help condition most (70%) subjects said that the agent did not bring about the side-effect intentionally. This difference was statistically significant, χ 2 (1, N = 42) = 9.5, p <.01. 3. Explaining the Results Why do people respond so differently to vignettes that seem, at least in certain respects, to be so similar? Here subjects ratings of praise and blame may provide an important clue. I therefore

combined the praise and blame ratings from the two experiments and ran a new series of tests. Overall, subjects said that the agent deserved a lot of blame in the harm condition (M = 4.8) but very little praise in the help condition (M = 1.4), t (120)= 8.4, p <.001, and the total amount of praise or blame that subjects offered was correlated with their judgements about whether or not the side-effect was brought about intentionally, r (120) =.53, p <.001. In other words, there seems to be an asymmetry whereby people are considerably more willing to blame the agent for bad side-effects than to praise the agent for good side-effects. And this asymmetry in people s assignment of praise and blame may be at the root of the corresponding asymmetry in people s application of the concept intentional: namely, that they seem considerably more willing to say that a side-effect was brought about intentionally when they regard that side-effect as bad than when they regard it as good. Princeton University Princeton, New Jersey 08544-1006 jknobe@princeton.edu References Bratman, M. 1984. Two faces of intention. Philosophical Review 93: 375 405. Bratman, M. 1987. Intention, Plans, and Practical Reason. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Harman, G. 1976. Practical reasoning. Review of Metaphysics 29: 431 463. Malle, B. F. & Knobe, J. 1997. The folk concept of intentionality. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 33: 101 121. Mele, A. 2001. Acting intentionally: probing folk notions. In Intentions and Intentionality: Foundations of Social Cognition. ed. B. F. Malle, L. J. Moses, & D. Baldwin, 27 43. Cambridge, MA: M. I. T. Press. Mele, A. 2003. Intentional Action: Controversies, Data, and Core Hypotheses. Philosophical Psychology 16. 325-340.