Evaluating framing e ects

Similar documents
Risky Choice Framing Effects

Risky Choice Decisions from a Tri-Reference Point Perspective

Framing the frame: How task goals determine the likelihood and direction of framing effects

The effect of decision frame and decision justification on risky choice

Group size and the framing effect: Threats to human beings and animals

Using Credible Advice to Overcome Framing Effects

Explaining outcome type interactions with frame: Aspiration level and the value function

Framing effects: An analytic holistic perspective

Analyzing Framing Effecty by an Experiment among Students in Turkey

Gender bias in risk aversion: evidence from multiple choice exams

Teorie prospektu a teorie očekávaného užitku: Aplikace na podmínky České republiky

Psychology Department, University of South Dakota, USA

The Interplay between Theory and Experiments. Leeat Yariv y. June 23, 2010

The secular increase in test scores is a ``Jensen e ect''

Shaping Consumer Perception to Motivate Online Shopping: A Prospect Theory Perspective

Profiling the Risk Attitudes of Clients by Financial Advisors: The Effects of Framing on Response Validity

What a speaker s choice of frame reveals: Reference points, frame selection, and framing effects

Paradoxes and Violations of Normative Decision Theory. Jay Simon Defense Resources Management Institute, Naval Postgraduate School

Rationality in Cognitive Science

Political Preference Formation: Competition, Deliberation, and the (Ir)relevance of Framing Effects*

How often did I do it? Experienced ease of retrieval and frequency estimates of past behavior

Multiple Framing: Verbal, Facial, and Vocal Cues in Risky Choice

Risk attitude in decision making: A clash of three approaches

Thinking about product attributes: Investigating the role of unconscious valence processing in attribute framing

Attention, Frame Condition and Decision Making Under Risk:

A new look at the Asian disease problem: A choice between the best possible outcomes or between the worst possible outcomes?

Appendix III Individual-level analysis

It is Whether You Win or Lose: The Importance of the Overall Probabilities of Winning or Losing in Risky Choice

UNIVERSITY OF DUBLIN TRINITY COLLEGE. Faculty of Arts Humanities and Social Sciences. School of Business

Information can kill

Subjects Motivations

7 Action. 7.1 Choice. Todd Davies, Decision Behavior: Theory and Evidence (Spring 2010) Version: June 4, 2010, 2:40 pm

An Experimental Comparison of the Fairness Models by Bolton and Ockenfels and by Fehr and Schmidt

Education and Preferences: Experimental Evidences from Chinese Adult Twins

Attributions of responsibility and affective reactions decision outcomes Zeelenberg, Marcel; van der Pligt, J.; de Vries, N.K.

Effects of Sequential Context on Judgments and Decisions in the Prisoner s Dilemma Game

Susceptibility to anchoring effects: How openness-toexperience influences responses to anchoring cues

Was Bernoulli Wrong? On Intuitions about Sample Size

Social Cues and Verbal Framing in Risky Choice

The Fragile Basic Anchoring Effect

COOPERATION 1. How Economic Rewards Affect Cooperation Reconsidered. Dan R. Schley and John H. Kagel. The Ohio State University

Overcoming Frames and Ethical Dilemmas: The Effects of Large Numbers on Decision-Making. Alexander Johnson, Bryce Jones, Andrew Kent, Alex Polta

Contingent focus model of Decision Framing under Risk Satoshi Fujii 1 & Kazuhisa Takemura 2. Tokyo Institute of Technology, Japan

Are Experimental Economists Prone to Framing Effects? A Natural Field Experiment

Volume 30, Issue 3. Boundary and interior equilibria: what drives convergence in a beauty contest'?

Minimal conditions for the creation of a unit relationship: the social bond between birthdaymates

Representativeness Heuristic and Conjunction Errors. Risk Attitude and Framing Effects

Are We Rational? Lecture 23

Psychological Perspectives on Visualizing Uncertainty. Barbara Tversky Stanford University

Self-framing of Risky Choice

Choice set options affect the valuation of risky prospects

Editorial. An audit of the editorial process and peer review in the journal Clinical Rehabilitation. Introduction

On the Making of an Experience: The E ects of Breaking and Combining Experiences on their Overall Evaluation

Virtual Mentor Ethics Journal of the American Medical Association September 2005, Volume 7, Number 9

Conceptually driven encoding episodes create perceptual misattributions

The Influence of Hedonic versus Utilitarian Consumption Goals on the Compromise Effect. Abstract

Is a picture worth a thousand words? The interaction of visual display and attribute representation in attenuating framing bias

Problems of Policy Implementation in Distributed Decision Systems. Paul Slovic. Decision Research/A Branch of Perceptronics, Inc.

Does observation of others a ect learning in strategic environments? An experimental study*

Adaptive Aspirations in an American Financial Services Organization: A Field Study

Wendy J. Reece (INEEL) Leroy J. Matthews (ISU) Linda K. Burggraff (ISU)

Do Warriors, Villagers and Scientists Decide Differently? The Impact of Role on Message Framing

Mini-Course in Behavioral Economics Leeat Yariv. Behavioral Economics - Course Outline

Lucid dreaming: associations with internal locus of control, need for cognition and creativity

Asking and answering research questions. What s it about?

Oct. 21. Rank the following causes of death in the US from most common to least common:

Effect of Choice Set on Valuation of Risky Prospects

Frequency versus probability formats in statistical word problems

Behavioral Economics - Syllabus

14.11 Lecture 2: Public Health Messages How to Convince Others to Adopt Healthy Behaviors?

Silence is Golden. Suggested Donations in Voluntary Contribution Games

Why Prosocials Exhibit Greater Cooperation

Dissecting the risky-choice framing effect: Numeracy as an individual-difference factor in weighting risky and riskless options

Testing contingency hypotheses in budgetary research: an evaluation of the use of moderated regression analysis $

Gender specific attitudes towards risk and ambiguity an experimental investigation

Trait motivational correlates of athleticism

15 The External Validity of Laboratory Experiments: The Misleading Emphasis on Quantitative E ects

Comparative Ignorance and the Ellsberg Paradox

Cowles Foundation for Research in Economics at Yale University

Alternative Payoff Mechanisms for Choice under Risk. by James C. Cox, Vjollca Sadiraj Ulrich Schmidt

Why Does Similarity Correlate With Inductive Strength?

Class 12: The Foreign-Language Effect:Thinking in a Foreign Tongue Reduces Decision Biases. Keysar, Hayakawa, & An Ted Gibson 9.59J/24.

The role of background knowledge in speeded perceptual categorization

4/26/2017. Things to Consider. Making Decisions and Reasoning. How Did I Choose to Get Out of Bed...and Other Hard Choices

Effects of valence and framing in decision-making: Assessing decision-makers perceived domains of choice

Macquarie University ResearchOnline

The influence of (in)congruence of communicator expertise and trustworthiness on acceptance of CCS technologies

Stackelberg in the Lab: The E ect of Group Decision Making and Deliberation Periods

Decision-Making Models in Foreign Policy

Decision biases in intertemporal choice and choice under uncertainty: Testing a common account

Assessment and Estimation of Risk Preferences (Outline and Pre-summary)

Thought and Knowledge

Games 2011, 2, ; doi: /g OPEN ACCESS

Contingent Weighing of Past and Future Decision Outcomes

ASSOCIATION FOR CONSUMER RESEARCH

RESEARCH ARTICLE. GENDER DIFFERENCES IN RISK TAKING: EVIDENCE FROM A MANAGEMENT INSTITUTE Amit Kapoor 1

Minimax Regret in Practice - Four Examples on Treatment Choice 1

Healthy choices in context: How contextual cues can influence the persuasiveness of framed health messages

Nudges: A new instrument for public policy?

An Experimental Study of Ambiguity and Vagueness in the Announcement Game

Transcription:

Journal of Economic Psychology 22 2001) 91±101 www.elsevier.com/locate/joep Evaluating framing e ects James N. Druckman * Department of Political Science, University of Minnesota, 1414 Social Sciences Building, 267-19th Avenue South, Minneapolis, MN 55455-0410, USA Received 25 July 2000; accepted 10 October 2000 Abstract This paper examines Tversky and Kahneman's well-known Asian disease framing problem A. Tversky, D. Kahneman, Science 211 1981) 453±458). I describe an experiment where respondents received a version of the disease problem using a survival format, a mortality format, or both formats. The results from the survival and mortality formats replicate Tversky and Kahneman's original experiment both in terms of statistical signi cance and, in contrast to some other studies, in terms of magnitude. I then argue that the ``both format'' condition constitutes an important and previously unused baseline for evaluating the strength of framing e ects. This standard of comparison provides a way to evaluate the impact of a frame on unadulterated preferences ± that is, preferences una ected by a particular frame. The implications for future framing e ect experiments are discussed. Ó 2001 Elsevier Science B.V. All rights reserved. PsycINFO classi cation: 2260; 2340 JEL classi cation: C91; D81 Keywords: Framing e ect * Corresponding author. Tel.: +1-612-626-1672; fax: +1-612-626-7599. E-mail address: druckman@polisci.umn.edu J.N. Druckman). 0167-4870/01/$ - see front matter Ó 2001 Elsevier Science B.V. All rights reserved. PII: S 0 1 6 7-4870 00)00032-5

92 J.N. Druckman / Journal of Economic Psychology 22 2001) 91±101 1. Introduction In their famous experiment, Tversky and Kahneman 1981) provided participants with the following scenario: Imagine that the US is preparing for the outbreak of an unusual Asian disease, which is expected to kill 600 people. Two alternative programs to combat the disease have been proposed. Assume that the exact scienti c estimates of the consequences of the programs are as follows... Some respondents N ˆ 152) then received a description of the programs using a survival format: If Program A is adopted, 200 people will be saved. If Program B is adopted, there is a 1/3 probability that 600 people will be saved, and a 2/3 probability that no people will be saved. Of these respondents, 72% expressed a preference for Program A ± the risk-averse alternative. Another group of respondents N ˆ 155) received a description of the same exact programs except it used a mortality format: If Program C is adopted, 400 people will die. If Program D is adopted, there is a 1/3 probability that nobody will die, and a 2/3 probability that 600 people will die. Only 22% of these respondents opted for Program C, even though it is the same risk-averse alternative as Program A, and Program D is the same riskseeking alternative as Program B. This result re ects a general tendency for people to be risk-averse when exposed to a gains survival) format and risk-seeking when exposed to a losses mortality) format. Traditionally, such a shift in risk preferences due to alternative descriptions of the problem is called a ``framing e ect'' see Levin, Schneider, & Gaeth, 1998 for distinctions among types of framing e ects). Tversky and Kahneman's work on framing e ects ± and in particular their Asian disease problem ± has spawned numerous literatures throughout

the social sciences e.g., Zaller, 1992; Camerer, 1995; Levin et al., 1998; Li, 1998). In this paper, I build on these literatures by addressing two issues. First, I present an experiment designed to replicate Tversky and Kahneman's original Asian disease experiment just described). This is interesting because several other replication attempts have produced a framing e ect smaller than the one rst documented by Tversky and Kahneman. I discuss a possible explanation for these variations in the magnitude of framing e ects. Second, I o er a new baseline for evaluating the existence and/or strength of framing e ects. Speci cally, I compare respondent's preferences from the survival and mortality formats i.e., conditions mimicking the original experiment) with preferences from a newly included) condition where respondents received both formats simultaneously. The advantage of this standard of comparison, relative to other standards that I will discuss, is that it serves as an empirically derived baseline that may approximate preferences in the absence of an effect from either the survival or mortality format. The experimental results reveal that, contrary to common assertions e.g., Kuhberger, 1998, 235), the mortality format may not have a stronger effect on preferences than the survival format. Before turning to the experiment, I offer a more detailed discussion of why a replication is important and why a new standard of evaluation is useful. 1.1. Replication J.N. Druckman / Journal of Economic Psychology 22 2001) 91±101 93 Scholars attempting to replicate Tversky and Kahneman's 1981) Asian disease experiment have had mixed success. Some replication attempts have failed to nd a signi cant framing e ect e.g., Miller & Fagley, 1991), while others have successfully mimicked the original experiment e.g., Bless, Betsch, & Franzen, 1998). More generally, it seems that while the e ect is highly reliable Kuhberger, 1998), the magnitude of the e ect tends to be smaller than that found in the original experiment e.g., Fagley & Miller, 1990; Bohm & Lind, 1992; Kuhberger, 1995, 235; see Levin et al., 1998 for an overview). Fagley and Miller 1997, 357) explain that ``Framing results have been mixed, particularly if one looks at the magnitude of the e ect...'' In what follows, I present an experiment that attempts to replicate the original results; as I will discuss, my replication attempt di ers from many others in that I use the original problem without alteration and ask subjects to reply only to the original problem and no other problems).

94 J.N. Druckman / Journal of Economic Psychology 22 2001) 91±101 1.2. Evaluating framing e ects Two approaches have been taken to evaluate the existence and/or strength of framing e ects Kuhberger, 1995, p. 235; Kuhberger, 1998, pp. 30±31; Wang, 1996; Levin et al., 1998, p. 153). The rst approach is sometimes called a unidirectional e ect or a choice shift. This approach entails comparing the percentage of participants who opted for the risk-averse alternative or the risk-seeking alternative) in the gains survival) format with the percentage of participants who opted for the risk-averse alternative or the risk-seeking alternative) in the losses mortality) format. For example, using Tversky and Kahneman's original data, 72% opted for the risk-averse alternative in the gains format and 22% opted for it in the losses format. These percentages signi cantly di er from one another, so one would conclude that there is a ``framing e ect'' using this standard of comparison. This evaluative approach reveals just how di erent preferences can be when one frame is used instead of another objectively identical) frame. Moreover, by using frames that push preferences in opposite directions e.g., towards more risk-averse behavior versus more risk-seeking behavior), this approach provides insight into the maximal power of framing. The other approach ± sometimes called a bidirectional e ect or a choice reversal ± entails the investigation of if 1) risk-averse choices predominant for the gains format and 2) risk-seeking choices predominant for the losses format Wang, 1996). This requires that signi cantly greater than a risk-neutral) 50% of respondents opt for the risk-averse alternative under the gains format and signi cantly fewer than 50% of respondents opt for the risk-averse alternative under the losses format. Using Tversky and Kahneman's original data again, 72% is signi cantly greater than 50% and 22% is signi cantly below it, and thus, one would conclude that a framing e ect occurred using this standard of comparison as well. This bidirectional approach has the advantage of revealing if one frame causes a majority of subjects to opt for one alternative e.g., the risk-averse alternative) while the other frame causes the majority to opt for the other alternative e.g., the risk-seeking alternative). Identifying such a majority reversal in preference can be important for those interested in if di erent frames can generate majority support for one alternative instead of another. Wang 1996, pp. 154±155) o ers another justi cation for the bidirectional approach, arguing that only when the formats push preferences signi cantly away from 50% in the predicted directions) does the e ect

J.N. Druckman / Journal of Economic Psychology 22 2001) 91±101 95 violate the description invariance assumption underlying expected utility theory. That is, the assumption that ``di erent representations of the same choice problem should yield the same preference'' Tversky & Kahneman, 1987, p. 69). The status of this justi cation is unclear, however, because even when a unidirectional e ect occurs, it still suggests that some percentage of the respondents violate the preference invariance assumption even if it does not suggest that a majority violate the assumption). Put in another way, evidence of violations of preference invariance among some respondents need not require a bidirectional e ect. Indeed, Tversky and Kahneman 1987, pp. 70±71) themselves cite a framing experiment that results in signi cant di erence between formats but not signi cant di erences from 50% in the predicted directions) as a prime example of an invariance violation. While Tversky and Kahneman's original result is signi cant using either of the two evaluative approaches, it is easy to nd examples where the two approaches lead to very di erent conclusions Kuhberger, 1998, pp. 30±31). For example, imagine that 35% opted for the risk-averse alternative in the gains format and 5% opted for it in the losses format. Then, the 50% baseline approach or the bidirectional approach) implies either no framing e ect because 35% does not exceed 50%) or a reverse framing e ect because 35% may be signi cantly below 50%). In contrast, assuming a su ciently large N, 35% and 5% might well be signi cantly di erent from one another in the expected relative) direction; thus, one would conclude that there is a framing e ect using the unidirectional approach. Apart from evaluating if framing e ects occurred, these approaches also have implications for the strength of di erent e ects. Most notably, those who use the 50% baseline often conclude that the losses format is stronger than the gains format because it results in a larger deviation from 50% ± for example, 22% is further from 50% than is 72% see, e.g., Kuhberger, 1995, p. 235). In any given study, both approaches for evaluating framing e ects could be used, as each provides distinct insights ± the unidirectional approach reveals the relative impact of alternative frames on preferences while the bidirectional approach reveals if a majority preference reversal occurred. However, neither approach provides insight into another question: what is the impact of a given frame on unadulterated preferences ± that is, preferences una ected by a particular frame? In many real-world circumstances, individuals receive a single frame that may or may not move their prior unadulterated) preference e.g., they receive a single frame from a strategic

96 J.N. Druckman / Journal of Economic Psychology 22 2001) 91±101 politician or salesperson); it is thus important to somehow evaluate the impact of frames on unadulterated preferences. The unidirectional approach fails to capture this process because it compares preferences shaped by one frame with preferences shaped by another frame. One could argue that bidirectional approach applies in that it reveals how far a single frame can move preferences from a risk-neutral 50%. Since the programs have the same expected values, if decision-makers are risk-neutral, they will be indi erent and randomly choose each program with equal 50% probability.) However, there is no reason to assume that respondents have risk-neutral preferences before being exposed to the problem. Indeed, it may be the case that in the absence of in uence from the gains or losses format, people would exhibit risk-seeking or risk-averse behavior and not risk-neutral behavior). For example, imagine that 15% instead of 50%) opted for the risk-averse alternative in the absence of in- uence from a losses or gains) format. In this case, if 45% opted for the risk-averse alternative when given the gains format, then, assuming a large N, we would conclude that the frame did in fact signi cantly affect unadulterated preferences. We would not reach this conclusion using the 50% baseline. Evaluating the e ect of a frame on unadulterated preferences thus requires the measurement of prior risk preferences. A general risk-taking propensity measure may be inappropriate, however, since risk attitudes tend to vary across speci c problems e.g., Wang, 1996). In the experiment that follows, I attempt to gauge prior risk attitudes for this problem by incorporating a new condition that includes both the gains survival) and losses mortality) information. The idea is that by exposing respondents to both formats, the impact of each of the formats on risk attitudes will cancel out. This will serve as an appropriate empirically derived standard to evaluate the impact of a frame on unadulterated preferences. Note that using both formats in this way differs from Kuhberger 1995) in that it does not separate out domain effects from framing effects because the goal is to have the domains cancel each other out. It is of course possible that when presented together, one of the formats will be more salient and push preferences in a certain direction; however, previous work on a di erent problem by Levin, Johnson, and Davis 1987, p. 52) suggests that a format with both types of data e.g., gains and losses data) is ``neutral in evaluation''. In some sense, this new survival±mortality format serves as the control group that has not been included in prior Asian disease experiments.

J.N. Druckman / Journal of Economic Psychology 22 2001) 91±101 97 2. Method I randomly assigned 320 student participants from a large US public university) to one of three conditions. The conditions asked participants to respond to a version of the Asian disease problem that used either 1) the survival format N ˆ 69), 2) the mortality format N ˆ 79), or 3) a format that included both survival and mortality data N ˆ 172). These three variations of the problem constitute the three conditions.) Using students in the experiment should not limit its generalizability. Indeed, based on a meta-analysis of 136 framing effect studies with nearly 30,000 participants, Kuhberger 1998, p. 36) nds that the behavior of student participants does not signi cantly differ from the behavior of nonstudent participants. The survival and mortality formats were as in the original experiment, described above. An example of the ``both'' survival-mortality format is: If Program A is adopted, 200 people will be saved and 400 people will die. If Program B is adopted, there is a 1/3 probability that 600 people will be saved and nobody will die, and a 2/3 probability that no people will be saved and 600 people will die. The relatively large number of participants exposed to the survival±morality format is due to exposing them randomly) to one of four versions of this format, where the order of the programs and outcome statistics varied. In presenting the results, I merge these four versions because no signi cant di erences between them were found. Participants were debriefed at the conclusion of the experiment. 3. Results Of the participants who received the survival format, 68.1% opted for Program A ± the risk-averse alternative. In contrast, only 22.8% of the participants who received the mortality format opted for Program C ± the identical risk-averse alternative. To test for a statistically signi cant difference between the two formats, I use a difference of proportions test that is

98 J.N. Druckman / Journal of Economic Psychology 22 2001) 91±101 analogous to a difference-of-means test except that it applies to the case of two proportions from two samples or conditions Blalock, 1979, pp. 232± 233). The difference of proportions test indicates that the difference between the two formats is highly signi cant z ˆ 5.54, P < 0.01). Moreover, both the survival format and the mortality format results signi cantly differ from 50% in the expected directions k 2 1 ˆ 9:06; P < 0:01; k2 1 ˆ 23:41; P < 0:01, respectively). This result is quite close to a replication of Tversky and Kahneman's original experiment, both in terms of signi cance and magnitude. Also, in contrast to Fagley and Miller 1990, 1997) but consistent with Miller and Fagley, 1991, p. 520), women were no more susceptible to framing e ects than men. Speci cally, when given the survival format, 61% of women and 74% of men opted for the risk-averse alternative; when given the mortality format, 21% of women and 26% of men opted for the risk-averse alternative. Of the participants who received a format with both survival and morality data, 43.6% preferred the risk-averse alternative. This is approximately midway between the survival format result 68.1%) and the mortality format result 22.8%). It also is marginally statistically signi cantly di erent from a risk-neutral 50% k 2 1 ˆ 2:81; P < 0:10. I next discuss the implications of these results. 4. Discussion The successful replication is consistent with several studies that also nd a statistically signi cant framing e ect. However, unlike some of these studies, the magnitude of the framing e ect reported here approaches the magnitude found in the original experiment. A possible explanation for this nding is that, like Bless et al.'s 1998) similar replication, participants were exposed to only one problem and the original problem was used without alteration also see Takemura, 1994). In contrast, several of the replication attempts that produce signi cant but smaller framing e ects expose participants to several problems and/or slightly alter the original problem Miller and Fagley, 1991; Bohm and Lind, 1992; Kuhberger, 1995; Wang, 1996; Zickar and Highhouse, 1998). Indeed, Bless et al. 1998) demonstrate that framing e ects can be quite sensitive to slight contextual changes. The format with both mortality and survival data provides a new baseline for evaluating the impact of the frames. If the survival and mortality formats neutralize one another, making this format an unadulterated

J.N. Druckman / Journal of Economic Psychology 22 2001) 91±101 99 measure of prior risk preferences, then the result of 43.6% suggests that participants had a slight albeit marginally signi cant) tendency towards risk-seeking, in the absence of in uence from a format. Thus, if the survival format alone had pushed participants signi cantly away from 43.6%, then it would have had an important e ect on initial preferences), even if it did not signi cantly di er from 50%. While 43.6% is only marginally signi cantly di erent from 50%, it still highlights the potential problem of assuming a risk-neutral 50% as an indication of unadulterated preferences. In short, there is no reason to assume that the respondents are risk-neutral; a better approach is to measure prior preferences so as to evaluate the impact of a frame on unadulterated preferences. In many contexts, individuals receive just one frame e.g., from a politician or salesperson) and thus understanding the e ect of a single frame on prior, unadulterated preferences is signi cant. Notice also that if we treat 43.6% as an empirically derived baseline, then neither the survival nor the mortality format was more in uential since 43.6% approximates the mid-point between these singular formats). In contrast, using a 50% baseline gure suggests that, consistent with prior interpretations, the mortality format had a stronger in uence than the survival format because it deviates more from the risk-neutral 50% baseline i.e., 27.2% versus 18.1%). As mentioned, another explanation for the result from the format with both mortality and survival data is that the participants actually were riskneutral or even risk-averse) ex ante and, when given the morality±survival format, the mortality description was more salient than the survival description and consequently it pushed participants in a risk-seeking direction, albeit to a lesser extent than the mortality format alone). Irrespective of whether this is true, the results presented here suggest an important amendment to the way in which we evaluate framing e ects. As discussed, the unidirectional and bidirectional approaches have their advantages; however, neither provides an estimate of the impact of a single frame on unadulterated preferences. In contrast, the empirically derived baseline used here may provide such an estimate. In future framing experiments, all three approaches or other analogous alternatives) could be used so that we can estimate the impact of the frames relative to one another, evaluate majority preference reversals, and judge the impact of each frame on unadulterated preferences. Framing e ects clearly play a substantial role in the decisionmaking process, and thus, we should evaluate them from each of these varying perspectives.

100 J.N. Druckman / Journal of Economic Psychology 22 2001) 91±101 Acknowledgements I thank Gregory Bovitz, Daniel Druckman, Nicole Druckman, and the anonymous reviewers for helpful advice. References Blalock, H. M. 1979). Social statistics. New York: McGraw-Hill. Bless, H., Betsch, T., & Franzen, A. 1998). Framing the framing e ect: the impact of context cues on solutions to the `Asian disease' problem. European Journal of Social Psychology, 28, 287± 291. Bohm, P., & Lind, H. 1992). A note on the robustness of a classical framing result. Journal of Economic Psychology, 13, 355±361. Camerer, C. 1995). Individual decision making. In J. H. Kagel, & A. E. Roth Eds.), The handbook of experimental economics pp. 587±703). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Fagley, N. S., & Miller, P. M. 1990). The e ect of framing on choice: interactions with risktaking propensity, cognitive style, and sex. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 16, 496± 510. Fagley, N. S., & Miller, P. M. 1997). Framing e ects and arenas of choice: your money or your life? Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 71, 355±373. Kuhberger, A. 1995). The framing of decisions: a new look at old problems. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 62, 230±240. Kuhberger, A. 1998). The in uence of framing on risky decisions: a meta-analysis. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 75, 23±55. Levin, I. P., Johnson, R. D., & Davis, M. L. 1987). How information frame in uences risky decisions: between-subjects and within-subject comparisons. Journal of Economic Psychology, 8, 43± 54. Levin, I. P., Schneider, S. L., & Gaeth, G. J. 1998). All frames are not created equal: a typology and critical analysis of framing e ects. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Making Processes, 76, 149±188. Li, S. 1998). Can the conditions governing the framing e ect be determined? Journal of Economic Psychology, 19, 133±153. Miller, P. M., & Fagley, N. S. 1991). The e ects of framing, problem variations, and providing rationale on choice. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 17, 517±522. Takemura, K. 1994). In uence of elaboration on the framing of decision. The Journal of Psychology, 128, 33±39. Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. 1981). The framing of decisions and the psychology of choice. Science, 211, 453±458. Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. 1987). Rational choice and the framing of decisions. In R. M. Hogarth, & M. W. Reder Eds.), Rational choice: the contrast between economics and psychology. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Wang, X. T. 1996). Framing e ects: dynamics and task domains. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 68, 145±157.

J.N. Druckman / Journal of Economic Psychology 22 2001) 91±101 101 Zickar, M. J., & Highhouse, S. 1998). Looking closer at the e ects of framing on risky choice: an item response theory analysis. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 75, 75± 91. Zaller, J. 1992). The nature and origins of mass opinion. New York: Cambridge University Press.