Instructions for use

Similar documents
Title. Author(s)Takahashi, Taiki. CitationMedical Hypotheses, 65(4): Issue Date Doc URL. Type. File Information

Author(s) Takahashi, Taiki; Oono, Hidemi; Rad

Instructions for use

choice behavior for monetary gain and loss than healthy subjects- an analysis

JEL D81, D91, I Tel&Fax:

NIH Public Access Author Manuscript J Exp Psychol Learn Mem Cogn. Author manuscript; available in PMC 2016 January 01.

Choice set options affect the valuation of risky prospects

Amount of Reward Has Opposite Effects on the Discounting of Delayed and Probabilistic Outcomes

Decision biases in intertemporal choice and choice under uncertainty: Testing a common account

[To appear in NeuroEndocrinology Letters] Molecular neuroeconomics of crime and punishment:

Paradoxes and Violations of Normative Decision Theory. Jay Simon Defense Resources Management Institute, Naval Postgraduate School

What is Experimental Economics? ECO663 Experimental Economics. Paul Samuelson once said. von Neumann and Morgenstern. Sidney Siegel 10/15/2016

Are We Rational? Lecture 23

econstor Make Your Publications Visible.

Discounting of Monetary and Directly Consumable Rewards Sara J. Estle, Leonard Green, Joel Myerson, and Daniel D. Holt

Mini-Course in Behavioral Economics Leeat Yariv. Behavioral Economics - Course Outline

TIME DISCOUNTING FOR PRIMARY AND MONETARY REWARDS *

[ NEL 2010] Stress hormones predict hyperbolic time-discount rates six months later in adults.

Behavioural Economics University of Oxford Vincent P. Crawford Michaelmas Term 2012

Integrated versus segregated accounting and the magnitude effect in temporal discounting

Subjective Hazard Rates Rationalize Irrational Temporal Preferences

Behavioral Economics - Syllabus

Perception of Anticipatory Time in Temporal Discounting

Decision Rationalities and Decision Reference Points. XT Wang Psychology Department University of South Dakota. Three Kinds of Decisions

The Psychology of Rare Events: Challenges to Managing Tail Risks

Delay discounting: concepts and measures

HERO. Rational addiction theory a survey of opinions UNIVERSITY OF OSLO HEALTH ECONOMICS RESEARCH PROGRAMME. Working paper 2008: 7

Prior Beliefs and Experiential Learning in a Simple Economic Game

The Foundations of Behavioral. Economic Analysis SANJIT DHAMI

Risky Choice Decisions from a Tri-Reference Point Perspective

Gender specific attitudes towards risk and ambiguity an experimental investigation

Effect of Choice Set on Valuation of Risky Prospects

Nudges: A new instrument for public policy?

The Effects of Delay and Probabilistic Discounting on Green Consumerism

Behavioural and Emotional Economics Bachelor Seminar Seminar announcement - Summerterm Background, target audience and organization

IN DECISION NEUROSCIENCE

Separation of Intertemporal Substitution and Time Preference Rate from Risk Aversion: Experimental Analysis

Money Earlier or Later? Simple Heuristics Explain Intertemporal Choices Better Than Delay Discounting Does

Assessment and Estimation of Risk Preferences (Outline and Pre-summary)

Effects of Sequential Context on Judgments and Decisions in the Prisoner s Dilemma Game

Education and Preferences: Experimental Evidences from Chinese Adult Twins

DELAYED REWARD AND COST DISCOUNTING. JAMES G. MURPHY Auburn University. RUDY E. VUCHINICH and CATHY A. SIMPSON University of Alabama, Birmingham

On the diversity principle and local falsifiability

Subjective socioeconomic status and cigarette smoking interact to delay discounting

Behavioral Economics Lecture 1 An Introduction to Behavioral Economics

WITHIN-SUBJECT COMPARISON OF REAL AND HYPOTHETICAL MONEY REWARDS IN DELAY DISCOUNTING MATTHEW W. JOHNSON AND WARREN K. BICKEL

Time Discounting: Delay Effect and Procrastinating Behavior

Framing Effects in Intertemporal Choice: A Nudge Experiment

A Belief-Based Account of Decision under Uncertainty. Craig R. Fox, Amos Tversky

UNIVERSITY OF DUBLIN TRINITY COLLEGE. Faculty of Arts Humanities and Social Sciences. School of Business

Does time inconsistency differ between gain and loss? An intra-personal comparison using a non-parametric. elicitation method (A revised version)

What Causes Delay Discounting? Andrea M. Angott

Thinking Fast Increases Framing Effects in Risky Decision Making

Decisions based on verbal probabilities: Decision bias or decision by belief sampling?

THE INTERACTION OF SUBJECTIVITY AND OBJECTIVITY IN THE PROCESS OF RISKY INVESTMENT DECISION MAKING

Taiki Takahashi 1. Department of Behavioral Science, Hokkaido University

George Loewenstein, 1 Scott Rick, 2 and Jonathan D. Cohen 3. 1 Department of Social and Decision Sciences, Carnegie Mellon University, Key Words

References. Christos A. Ioannou 2/37

Teorie prospektu a teorie očekávaného užitku: Aplikace na podmínky České republiky

The New Era of Finance: Neurofinance and Investment behavior

Under Review: Please do not reproduce or distribute

It is Whether You Win or Lose: The Importance of the Overall Probabilities of Winning or Losing in Risky Choice

Toward a Mechanistic Understanding of Human Decision Making Contributions of Functional Neuroimaging

Attention, Frame Condition and Decision Making Under Risk:

Interval Effects: Superadditivity and Subadditivity in Intertemporal Choice

PS3003: Judgment and Decision Making

AREC 815: Experimental and Behavioral Economics. Experiments Testing Prospect Theory. Professor: Pamela Jakiela

DFG Research Group 2104

How stress hormones influence judgment, choice and social preferences Tobias Kalenscher Heinrich-Heine University Düsseldorf

Risk attitude in decision making: A clash of three approaches

THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN ADDICTION AND REWARD BUNDLING: AN EXPERIMENT COMPARING SMOKERS AND NON-SMOKERS

Previous outcome effects on sequential probabilistic choice behavior

A quasi-hyperbolic discounting approach to smoking behavior

Time discounting for primary and monetary rewards

Implications of Neuroscience Developments in Understanding Human Behavior for Teaching Agricultural Economics/Agribusiness

Does Working Memory Load Lead to Greater Impulsivity? Commentary on Hinson, Jameson, and Whitney (2003)

Cognitive Development

Contagion Effects in Intertemporal Decision Making

Time and decision making in humans

Discounting in pigeons when the choice is between two delayed rewards: implications for species comparisons

Experimental evidence 1

AN INVESTIGATION OF DECISION- MAKING AND THE TRADEOFFS INVOLVING COMPUTER SECURITY RISK

Economic Decisions for Others: An Exception to Loss Aversion Law

Operant Matching as a Nash Equilibrium of an Intertemporal Game

scope insensitivity and the mere token effect

Well I Never! Risk Perception & Communication

Representativeness Heuristic and Conjunction Errors. Risk Attitude and Framing Effects

The Somatic Marker Hypothesis: Human Emotions in Decision-Making

Decision neuroscience seeks neural models for how we identify, evaluate and choose

Contingent focus model of Decision Framing under Risk Satoshi Fujii 1 & Kazuhisa Takemura 2. Tokyo Institute of Technology, Japan

Prof. Dr. Daniel Krähmer: Behavioral Economics SS16 1. Lecture Notes

Behavioral Economics Comes of Age

Dual or unitary system? Two alternative models of decision making

Discounting Time and Time Discounting: Subjective Time Perception and Intertemporal Preferences

INVESTOR S PSYCHOLOGY IN INVESTMENT DECISION MAKING: A BEHAVIORAL FINANCE APPROACH

Principles of Change:

Dual or unitary system? Two alternative models of decision making

The Role of Orbitofrontal Cortex in Decision Making

Value Function Elicitation: A Comment on Craig R. Fox & Amos Tversky, "A Belief-Based Account of Decision under Uncertainty"

CURRICULUM VITAE (September 2018) Juan D. CARRILLO

Transcription:

TitleA probabilistic choice model based Author(s) Takahashi, Taiki Citation Physica A: Statistical Mechanics an 335-338 Issue Date 2007-12-01 DOI Doc URLhttp://hdl.handle.net/2115/51261 Right Type article (author version) Additional Information File Information 2-TakahashiProbabilisticChoiceTsall Instructions for use Hokkaido University Collection of Scholarly and

A probabilistic choice model based on Tsallis' statistics. Taiki Takahashi 1 1 Direct all correspondence to Taiki Takahashi, Unit of Cognitive and Behavioral Sciences, Department of Life Sciences, School of Arts and Sciences, The University of Tokyo, Komaba, Meguro-ku, Tokyo, 153-8902, Japan (taiki@ecs.c.u-tokyo.ac.jp). Acknowledgements: The research reported in this paper was supported by a grant from the Grant- in-aid for Scientific Research ( 21st century center of excellence grant) from the Ministry of Education, Culture, Sports, Science and Technology of Japan, and Yamaguchi endocrinological disorder research grant.

Abstract Decision under risk and uncertainty (probabilistic choice) has been attracting attention in econophysics and neuroeconomics. This paper proposes a probabilistic choice model based on a mathematical equivalence of delay and uncertainty in decision-making, and the deformed algebra developed in the Tsallis' non-extensive thermodynamics. Furthermore, it is shown that this model can be utilized to quantify the degree of consistency in probabilistic choice in humans and animals. Future directions in the application of the model to studies in econophysics, neurofinance, neuroeconomics, and social physics are discussed. Keywords: Neuroeconomics; Econophysics; Neurofinance; risk; Tsallis's statistics

1. Introduction: Decision under risk and probabilistic uncertainty (probabilistic choice) has been a major topic in microeconomics (e.g., the expected utility theory [1]), behavioral neuroeconomics (e.g. the prospect theory [2]), and econophysics [3]. Studies in behavioral and neuro- economics have revealed that humans and non-human animals discount the value of probabilistic rewards as the receipt becomes more uncertain ("probability discounting") [4]. In order to develop decision theory on probabilistic choice, recent efforts in neuroeconomics have started to combine probabilistic choice processes with intertemporal choice process [4]. Delay discounting in intertemporal choice refers to the devaluation of a delayed reward compared to the value of a sooner reward [5-9]. In this line of investigations into the unification of delay and probability discounting, recent studies in behavioral psychology and neuroeconomics have demonstrated a mathematical equivalence of delay and probabilistic uncertainty (risk) [4,9,10] in reward-seeking behavior and optimal foraging, in several manners. It is noteworthy here that neurofinancial studies reported substance misusers and patients with brain lesions in the orbitofrontal cortex have low degree of risk aversion in investment behavior under risk [11,12]. I introduce, in this paper, a novel framework combining a probabilistic model based on the equivalence of delay and uncertainty, with an intertemporal choice model utilizing the q-exponential function [13,14], of which usefulness has been examined in our previous behavioral study [15]. Notably, the q-exponential function is a well-studied function in a deformed algebra inspired by and developed in Tsallis' non-extensive thermodynamics [16]. This paper is organized in the following manner. In Section 2, I briefly introduce the mathematical equivalence of delay and probabilistic uncertainty, in Section 3, I explain the intertemporal choice model based on Tsallis' statistics and how the model is extended into probabilistic choice, and in Section 4, some conclusions from this study and future study directions by utilizing the present probabilistic choice models are discussed. 2. A mathematical equivalence of delay and uncertainty in decision making As noted above, it has been, in several studies, demonstrated that delay until receipt of gains in intertemporal choice and uncertainty of winning of gains in probabilistic choice may be equivalent. The most well-known account in behavioral ecology and psychopharmacology was proposed by Rachlin et al [4]. In unifying delay

and probability discounting, Rachlin et al hypothesized that a decrease in a probability of winning an uncertain reward corresponds to an increase in a delay until winning the reward. Specifically, an average waiting time until winning an uncertain reward is proportional to (1/p)-1("odds against"), where p is a probability of winning the uncertain reward. Therefore, according to Rachlin et al's hypothesis, decision-making models in intertemporal choice (delay discounting) can straightforwardly be extended into probabilistic choice, after replacing a parameter of delay in intertemporal choice models with the odds against parameter. A recent behavioral study on delay and probability discounting by human subjects has supported the hypothesis [17]. Furthermore, I have also proposed the mathematical equivalence of delay and uncertainty under a Markovian competitive social foraging condition [9], in which a delay is also proportional to (1/p)-1, which may explain anti-social behavior by subjects with strong delay discounting. Taken together, it appears to be a promising direction to establish probabilistic choice models based on the equivalence of delay and odds against. 3. An intertemporal choice model based on Tsallis' statistics Behavioral neuroeconomic studies have been focusing on impulsivity and dynamic consistency in intertemporal choice [7,8,9,15,17]. If agent's intertemporal choice is dynamically consistent, the agent's choice can be considered as rational, i.e., utility-maximizing, behavior, even when the agents dependent on addictive drugs (e.g. a theory of rational addiction) [18]. It can easily be shown that dynamically consistent intertemporal choice behavior is described with the following exponential discount function: V(D) = V(0)exp(-kD) (Equation 1) where V(D) is the subjective value of a reward at delay D until receipt. The free parameter k is an index of impulsivity (preference of sooner but small rewards), i.e., larger k values correspond to steeper delay discounting. In the exponential discount function, a discount rate defined as -(dv/dd)/v=k, independent of delay, confirming the absence of preference reversal. However, behavioral economic studies observed inconsistency in human intertemporal choice. For instance, most people prefer "two cups of coffee available one year and a week later" over "a cup of coffee available one year later", but prefer "a cup of coffee available now" over "two cups of coffee available one week later". This

intertemporal choice behavior is inconsistent, since time-intervals between sooner and delayed rewards are identical (i.e., 7 days) in the two intertemporal choice examples. The traditional account for the observed preference reversal over time is that the following hyperbolic discount equation significantly fits their behavioral data better than Equation 1: V (D)= V(0)/(1+jD). (Equation 2) where j is a free parameter (V and D have the same definition as Equation 1). Large j values again correspond to rapid discounting. In the hyperbolic discount function, the discounting rate =j /(1+jD) (a hyperbolic discount rate) is a decreasing function of delay ("increasing patience"), resulting in preference reversal as time passes [5,6,7,8]. Recently, the following time-discount function (q-exponential discount function) has been proposed by Cajueiro [14] and empirically examined in our previous study [15], in order to continuously parameterize agent's consistency in intertemporal choice: V(D)=V(0)/ exp q (kd)=v(0)/[1+(1-q)kd] 1/(1-q) (Equation 3) where exp q () is the q-exponential function in the deformed algebra inspired by Tsallis' non-extensive thermodynamics, 0 q<1 is a consistency parameter, and k is an impulsivity parameter (V and D have the same definitions as Equation 1 and 2). It is to be noted that large q values corresponds to more consistent intertemporal choice; namely, q 1 corresponds to exponential discounting (complete consistency), while q=0, hyperbolic discounting (complete inconsistency). By utilizing the q-exponential discount function, we have empirically shown that parameter q can continuously parameterize human agents' consistency in intertemporal choice, and most people's intertemporal choice has no consistency [15]. Considering that it is well established, as introduced above, that delay and risk/probabilistic uncertainty may be equivalent in decision-making processes, it is a logical next step to combine the q-exponential discount model with the equivalence of delay and uncertainty. Let us now put the odds against introduced in Equation 3 (Section 2), in stead of delay D. We obtain: V(p)=V(0)/ exp q (k p (1-p)/p) =V(0)/[1+k p (1-q)(1-p)/p] 1/(1-q) (Equation 4)

where p is the probability of winning an uncertain reward and k p is a parameter of delay aversion in repeated probabilistic choices; i.e., larger k p values indicate stronger risk (i.e., delay until winning) aversion (other parameters have the same definitions in Equation 3). This q-exponential probability discounting model, which is a natural extension of the q-exponential discount function combined with the reported equivalence of delay and uncertainty in decision processes, may allow us to continuously parameterize agents' consistency in probabilistic choice in gambling, financial decisions, and lottery. Notably, the equivalence of delay and odds-against in decision-making indicates that the agent spontaneously assumes the system is ergodic, in that a time-averaged frequency of winning is equal to a probability of winning in each trial. As far as I know, this study is the first to apply the concept of ergodicity to social physics. 4. Conclusions and implications for neuroeconomics and econophysics As introduced in Section 3, q in the q-exponential probability discounting model may be capable of expressing each subject's inconsistency in probabilistic choice in a continuous manner (with smaller q values indicating more inconsistent probabilistic choices). As stated earlier, drug addicts, orbitofrontal lesion patients, and pathological gambles have impaired decision-making processes in probabilistic choice. Therefore, future studies should examine whether these subjects are more inconsistent in probabilistic choice, in addition to conventional risk attitude defined in microeconomics, by utilizing the q-exponential probability discount function (equation 4). Since the mathematical characteristics of q-algebra have extensively been examined and generalized [19], the present formulation may readily be utilized in future econophysical studies. Also, because a recent neuroeconomic study reported that neural activity in the orbitofrontal cortex in the brain was correlated with consistency in decision under risk across gain and loss domains [20], future neuroimaging studies in neurofinance and neuroeconomics may be able to identify brain regions responsible for consistency in probabilistic choice defined as parameter q. Moreover, investigating the relationship between the parameter q in the present probability discount model and the risk attitude parameter also based on Tsallis' statistics [2] is important in future studies in social physics and econophysics.

References [1] von Neumann J, Morgenstern O: Theory of Games and Economic Behavior. Princeton, NJ Princeton Univ. Press; 1947. [2] Kahneman D, Tversky A: Prospect Theory: An Analysis of Decision under Risk. Econometrica 1979, 47:263-292. [3] Anteneodo C, Tsallis C, Martinez AS. Risk aversion in economic transactions. 2002 Europhysics Lett. 59 (5): 635-641. [4] Rachlin H, Raineri A, Cross D. Subjective probability and delay. J Exp Anal Behav. 1991 Mar;55(2):233-244. [5] Ainslie G.. Precis of Breakdown of Will. Behav Brain Sci. 2005 28: :635-650 [6] Frederick, S., Loewenstein, G., & O Donoghue, T. Time discounting and time preference: A critical review. Journal of Economic Literature, 40, (2002)351-401. [7] Takahashi T. Loss of self-control in intertemporal choice may be attributable to logarithmic time-perception. Med Hypotheses. 2005;65(4):691-693. [8] Takahashi T. Time-estimation error following Weber-Fechner law may explain subadditive time-discounting. Med Hypotheses. 2006;67(6):1372-1374. [9] Takahashi, T. Queuing theory under competitive social foraging may explain a mathematical equivalence of delay and probability in impulsive decision-making. Med Hypotheses. 2006 ;67(2):276-279. [10] Takahashi T, Oono H, Radford MH. Comparison of probabilistic choice models in humans. Behav Brain Funct. 2007 Apr 20;3(1):20 [11] Shiv B, Loewenstein G, Bechara A, Damasio H, Damasio AR. Investment behavior and the negative side of emotion. Psychol Sci. 2005 16(6):435-439.

[12] Shiv B, Loewenstein G, Bechara A. The dark side of emotion in decision-making: when individuals with decreased emotional reactions make more advantageous decisions. Brain Res Cogn Brain Res. 2005 23(1):85-92. [13] Borges E.P., Physica A 340 (2004), pp. 95 101. [14] Cajueiro D.O. A note on the relevance of the q-exponential function in the context of intertemporal choices. Physica A 364 (2006) 385 388. [15] Takahashi T, Ono H, Radford MHB (2007) Empirical estimation of consistency parameter in intertemporal choice based on Tsallis' statistics Physica A (in press) [16] C. Tsallis, Química Nova 17 (1994), p. 468. [17] Yi R, de la Piedad X, Bickel WK. The combined effects of delay and probability in discounting. Behav Processes. 2006 Sep;73(2):149-155 [18] Becker G.S. Murphy K.M. A theory of rational addiction. Journal of Political Economy 1988 4 675-700. [19] Nivanen et al, Rep. Math. Phys. 52, (2003) 437 [20] De Martino B, Kumaran D, Seymour B, Dolan RJ. Frames, biases, and rational decision-making in the human brain. Science. 2006 313:684-687.