The Relation Between Perception and Action: What Should Neuroscience Learn From Psychology?

Similar documents
Topic 11 - Parietal Association Cortex. 1. Sensory-to-motor transformations. 2. Activity in parietal association cortex and the effects of damage

Online publication date: 08 June 2010

Chapter 3: 2 visual systems

Perception of Faces and Bodies

Consciousness The final frontier!

The Integration of Features in Visual Awareness : The Binding Problem. By Andrew Laguna, S.J.

EDGE DETECTION. Edge Detectors. ICS 280: Visual Perception

Computational Explorations in Cognitive Neuroscience Chapter 7: Large-Scale Brain Area Functional Organization

Identify these objects

DISORDERS OF PATTERN RECOGNITION

FAILURES OF OBJECT RECOGNITION. Dr. Walter S. Marcantoni

5.8 Departure from cognitivism: dynamical systems

Fundamentals of Cognitive Psychology, 3e by Ronald T. Kellogg Chapter 2. Multiple Choice

Competing Frameworks in Perception

Competing Frameworks in Perception

Change Blindness. The greater the lie, the greater the chance that it will be believed.

Neural codes PSY 310 Greg Francis. Lecture 12. COC illusion

Key questions about attention

Attention and Scene Perception

Clinical and Experimental Neuropsychology. Lecture 3: Disorders of Perception

LISC-322 Neuroscience Cortical Organization

Henry Molaison. Biography. From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Cortical Organization. Functionally, cortex is classically divided into 3 general types: 1. Primary cortex:. - receptive field:.

Disorders of Object and Spatial perception. Dr John Maasch Brain Injury Rehabilitation Service Burwood Hospital.

The Neuroscience of Vision III

How do individuals with congenital blindness form a conscious representation of a world they have never seen? brain. deprived of sight?

COGS 101A: Sensation and Perception

Why do we need vision? We need vision for two quite different but complementary reasons We need vision to give us detailed knowledge of the world beyo

The Concept of Simulation in Control-Theoretic Accounts of Motor Control and Action Perception

Phil 490: Consciousness and the Self Handout [16] Jesse Prinz: Mental Pointing Phenomenal Knowledge Without Concepts

CONSCIOUSNESS. Phil/Psych 256. Chris Eliasmith

Classification of Inhibitory Function

Neuroscience Tutorial

MSc Neuroimaging for Clinical & Cognitive Neuroscience

Introduction. Visual Perception Aditi Majumder, UCI. Perception is taken for granted!

Lateral Geniculate Nucleus (LGN)

Higher Cortical Function

SENSATION AND PERCEPTION KEY TERMS

Learning Objectives.

Human Paleoneurology and the Evolution of the Parietal Cortex

(Visual) Attention. October 3, PSY Visual Attention 1

Psych 333, Winter 2008, Instructor Boynton, Exam 2

psychology of visual perception C O M M U N I C A T I O N D E S I G N, A N I M A T E D I M A G E 2014/2015

Motor Systems I Cortex. Reading: BCP Chapter 14

Excellent Network Courses. Department of Neurology Affiliated hospital of Jiangsu University

Psychology of visual perception C O M M U N I C A T I O N D E S I G N, A N I M A T E D I M A G E 2014/2015

Cortical Visual Symptoms

Vision II. Steven McLoon Department of Neuroscience University of Minnesota

Presence and Perception: theoretical links & empirical evidence. Edwin Blake

Selective Attention. Inattentional blindness [demo] Cocktail party phenomenon William James definition

Greg Hickok: The myth of mirror neurons

Theoretical Neuroscience: The Binding Problem Jan Scholz, , University of Osnabrück

PSY 310: Sensory and Perceptual Processes 1

Neuroimaging of high-level visual functions. Visual awareness

PSYC 222 Motivation and Emotions

PSYCHOLOGICAL SCIENCE. Research Article

Commentary to Dijkerman & de Haan: Somatosensory processes subserving perception

H.O.T. Theory, Concepts, and Synesthesia: A Reply to Adams and Shreve

PSYC 441 Cognitive Psychology II

Max Planck Institut für biologische Kybernetik. Spemannstraße Tübingen Germany

Cerebral Cortex: Association Areas and Memory Tutis Vilis

Vision and Action. 10/3/12 Percep,on Ac,on 1

An Introduction to the CBS Health Cognitive Assessment

Frank Tong. Department of Psychology Green Hall Princeton University Princeton, NJ 08544

Introduction. Chapter The Perceptual Process

2012 Course: The Statistician Brain: the Bayesian Revolution in Cognitive Sciences

Arnold Trehub and Related Researchers 3D/4D Theatre in the Parietal Lobe (excerpt from Culture of Quaternions Presentation: Work in Progress)

CS/NEUR125 Brains, Minds, and Machines. Due: Friday, April 14

On the Time of Peripheral Sensations and Voluntary Motor Actions. Text

PERCEPTION AND ACTION

Change Blindness. Change blindness is the inability to recognize changes to objects in the environment

Dynamic functional integration of distinct neural empathy systems

Prof. Greg Francis 7/31/15

The brain and behaviour

Object vision (Chapter 4)

Senses are transducers. Change one form of energy into another Light, sound, pressure, etc. into What?

Sensation and Perception

Mirror neurons in the infant brain are formed by the interactions between self and other. M. Iacoboni SELF AND OTHER. J. A. Pineda COGS171 UCSD

Rules of apparent motion: The shortest-path constraint: objects will take the shortest path between flashed positions.

Carnegie Mellon University Annual Progress Report: 2011 Formula Grant

SLHS1402 The Talking Brain

A View of the Physical/Mental Boundary from the Mind Side

Giacomo Rizzolatti - selected references

Computational Models of Visual Attention: Bottom-Up and Top-Down. By: Soheil Borhani

Inside Your Patient s Brain Michelle Peterson, APRN, CNP Centracare Stroke and Vascular Neurology

Dr. Mark Ashton Smith, Department of Psychology, Bilkent University

Is Leisure Theory Needed For Leisure Studies?

Definition Slides. Sensation. Perception. Bottom-up processing. Selective attention. Top-down processing 11/3/2013

Cognitive Neuroscience History of Neural Networks in Artificial Intelligence The concept of neural network in artificial intelligence

= add definition here. Definition Slide

COGS 101A: Sensation and Perception

PSYC 441 Cognitive Psychology II

Hierarchically Organized Mirroring Processes in Social Cognition: The Functional Neuroanatomy of Empathy

The Conscious Brain: How attention engenders experience, by Jesse Prinz. New York:

Sensation and Perception

PS3021, PS3022, PS4040

Cognitive Neuroscience Attention

Perception and Action Are Inseparable

1.1 FEATURES OF THOUGHT

Orientation Specific Effects of Automatic Access to Categorical Information in Biological Motion Perception

Transcription:

ECOLOGICAL PSYCHOLOGY, 13(2), 117 122 Copyright 2001, Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Inc. The Relation Between Perception and Action: What Should Neuroscience Learn From Psychology? Patrick R. Green Department of Applied Psychology Heriot-Watt University Edinburgh, Scotland Research in neuroscience is making progress toward understanding the dorsal mechanisms responsible for the fast modulation by optical information of actions such as reaching and grasping. The function of ventral visual pathways is not to support perception, as distinct from action. Instead, it is to control extended actions that unfold over longer time scales and draw on optical information over larger spatial scales, than simple, fast limb movements. Perception and sensation should be regarded as particular forms of extended communicative actions and not as alternative end points for the use of environmental information. The neural mechanisms involved in controlling extended actions are not yet understood, and psychological theory has a role to play in framing their investigation by neuroscience. Milner and Goodale s (1995) theory is an important achievement. It begins with a core set of observations that brain lesions can produce strong and surprising dissociations between different ways of using vision. It then goes on to draw together converging evidence from single-cell physiology and psychophysics into a coherent whole that represents real progress toward understanding the biological systems that link optical stimulation and action. In neuroscience, the theory is usually seen as part of a common coding approach, which rejects the traditional distinction between sensory and motor areas of cerebral cortex (e.g., Gallese & Goldman, 1998; Goodale, 1998; Prinz, 1997). In contrast, ecological (and perhaps also cognitive) theorists are more struck by the wedge that it seems to drive between perception Requests for reprints should be sent to Patrick R. Green, Department of Applied Psychology, Heriot-Watt University, Edinburgh EH14 4AS, Scotland. E-mail: p.r.green@hw.ac.uk

118 GREEN and action. This is because, for neuroscience, much of the excitement surrounding the theory attaches to the dorsal pathway and its close links to premotor areas. These suggest that a fairly small number of fast neural operations between the primary visual and premotor cortex allows actions such as reaching, grasping, or stepping to be modulated by optical information. In contrast, the functions that Milner and Goodale assign to the ventral pathway represent a familiar way of thinking about visual perception in neuroscience. It is easy for such a view to slide into an assumption that the link between perception and action can be fenced off safely above the lateral sulcus, leaving the temporal lobe safe for cognitive mediation. I agree entirely with Michaels s (2000) aim of resisting this way of thinking, but I want to outline a somewhat different way of doing so, one that I argue asserts the place of psychology relative to neuroscience more strongly. Is there actually evidence for a single visual pathway outside the dorsal one, with clearly defined functions? Conscious awareness of the surroundings is claimed as an important function of the ventral pathway. However, one should be cautious of ascribing awareness to any single cortical area and remember that a wide variety of brain lesions can produce dissociations between awareness and performance. Sometimes these can be adequately explained as the loss of a ventral pathway required for conscious awareness, as in blindsight (Weiskrantz, 1986) or in visual form agnosia (Goodale, Milner, Jakobson, & Carey, 1991), when visually guided actions are aimed or scaled accurately without awareness of a target object. In other cases, dissociations can be more subtle. In both prosopagnosia (e.g., DeHaan, Young, & Newcombe, 1987) and neglect (e.g., Marshall & Halligan, 1988) there have been demonstrations of patients being unable to report the identity of faces or drawings when asked explicitly but who show covert recognition in implicit tasks, such as associative priming. Results of this kind indicate that in some circumstances recognition can be dissociated from awareness and therefore that both cannot arise from the operation of a single ventral system. A safer conclusion from existing evidence is simply that the dorsal pathway can operate effectively without giving rise to awareness. Another set of functions claimed for the ventral pathway is to form and use representations of objects and events. If one accepts Michaels s (2000) critique of this argument, a more neutral claim could be made that effects of experience and learning on perception occur in the ventral but not the dorsal pathway. However, it is difficult to maintain this as a distinct function unique to ventral areas. If the dorsal pathway is responsible for scaling limb movements in relation to the surrounding environment, it must in some way embody information about the dimensions and dynamic properties of the body. Furthermore, this must be capable of modification through learning so that visuomotor calibration is maintained as the body grows or becomes impaired. It also seems that the dorsal pathway must be involved where the mode of control of fast limb movements changes through learning; Michaels s discussion of learning to use inherently ambiguous optical variables to control the timing of ball punching (Michaels, Zeinstra, & Oudejans, 2001) provides an ex-

PERCEPTION AND ACTION 119 ample. As matters stand, there are no grounds to ascribe learning effects to a ventral system, or systems, alone. If current evidence supports a distinct dorsal pathway, but leaves the number and functions of more ventral pathways an open question, how should psychological theories of visual perception respond? I suggest by assuming that all operations carried out in the brain on optical information are concerned with action. One should not look for separate systems for controlling action on the one hand and for awareness, representation, or learning on the other hand. Rather, the problem is to understand how neural systems are organized to control actions taking place over different temporal and spatial scales. To clarify, consider the following series of things that one might see a person do: 1. Reach toward a door handle and grasp it. 2. Walk toward a door and open it. 3. Get up from a chair and go into another room. 4. Stop reading a book and go to the kitchen to get a snack. At each step, one sees an action that extends over a longer period of time and subsumes the action at the previous step. At the same time, one also sees that the temporal and spatial extent of the environmental information used to control the action becomes wider. At Step 1 it includes the position and dimensions of the door handle. At Step 2 it includes the layout of furniture, walls and door, and the dynamic properties of door handles and doors (both in general and in this specific case). At Step 3 the layout of the rooms of the house becomes involved, and at Step 4 such things as the narrative structure of the book and the contents of the refrigerator become involved. Ecological and cognitive theory obviously give very different accounts of the transitions between these examples, but for these purposes they are meant only to illustrate a crucial property of human action: that its control must involve systems working concurrently at a range of temporal and spatial scales. In these terms, the dorsal pathway can be seen as a distinct system controlling action at the smallest scales. The evidence indicates that it modulates limb movements quickly and that it has narrow temporal (Goodale, Jakobson, & Keillor, 1994; Westwood, Chapman, & Roy, 2000) and spatial (Murphy, Carey, & Goodale, 1998) windows on the environment. Other systems must come into play to control actions unfolding over longer periods than a second or so. Michaels (2000) suggested that this may be the function of a single ventral pathway, but it is just as likely to involve many cortical areas, among them the ventral areas identified by Milner and Goodale (1995). One can picture patterns of neural activity in cortical areas evolving and then disappearing over many different temporal and spatial scales, ranging from hundreds of milliseconds in local dorsal areas to longer time periods across many areas extending into the ventral region. The result is a dynamic hierarchy of control systems established in the cortex that allow for the se-

120 GREEN rial ordering of actions over different scales simultaneously. Such a model would lead one to expect multiple systems beyond the dorsal pathway and to expect reciprocal interactions between all pathways to achieve synchrony between control systems established over different scales. Working toward an understanding of the control of action at larger scales will, I predict, lead to a fractionation of the supposed ventral pathway into a much more complex model. It is here that psychological theory should look for its role in framing the wider problems for neuroscience to address. If there are no good grounds for assigning perception and action to different brain systems, are there any for treating them separately at a psychological level? Michaels (2000) suggested that sensation, perception, and action can be treated as three different results of stimulation, but I would like to offer an alternative suggestion: that perception and sensation are both forms of action. In particular, they are embedded in more extended communicative actions, or telling actions, to use Michaels s term. This is a particular class of actions that involve communicating something about the world to another person. Such an action must always be a relatively extended one, as its control must draw on information about the person or people making up the audience (or potential audience) as well as other aspects of the surroundings. Communicative actions will engage a hierarchy of smaller units of action, including not only speech or writing but also nonverbal gestures. A particular limb movement, such as shaping the hand to grasp an object, can form part of a number of different communicative actions. To take an everyday example, this movement might be a component of a more extended action to withhold information from another person that the actor is opening a door, by opening the door slowly and therefore quietly. In the more contrived circumstances of an experiment the same movement might be part of an extended action that communicates the size of an object to another person through a pantomime. The same fast, local action can therefore be recruited into many different extended actions, including a variety of communicative ones. As I argued earlier (Green, 1995), the dissociations shown by patients such as DF (Goodale et al., 1991) can be understood as an inability to recruit actions such as hand shaping in this way. To return to the nature of perception and sensation, I suggest that each of these terms covers a variety of actions in which a person prepares to communicate information about some state of affairs in the world to another person. Often, the action is not completed, and the result is a private experience. If it continues into a more extended act, some exchange between people develops, whether a natural everyday one or a more constrained one between experimenter and participant. In an act of perceiving, a person prepares to communicate some property of an object or event that is marked out as important by some physical or social context. This might be a person s age, the speed of a car, or the color of a piece of clothing. Or it might be a property marked out by an experimenter s instructions, such as the attractiveness of a face or the direction of motion of a grating. Depending on the interests of the experimenter, these two sets of properties may of course overlap. An

PERCEPTION AND ACTION 121 act of sensation is similar but involves properties of an object or event defined in a way more closely related to physical parameters. In this view, perception and sensation are not precisely defined or clearly separated but instead are broad and overlapping sets of phenomena. Both always involve some act of selecting properties of the world as part of a developing communicative action that may or may not go to completion with a verbal exchange. Treating sensation and perception in this way does not undermine the use of psychophysical methods to study how people use stimulation provided by the environment. These methods work by establishing a defined and controlled communicative action and investigating how it changes as properties of stimulation are varied. These relations then provide one with knowledge about constraints on the use of environmental stimulation or allow one to deduce the properties of particular neural operations on that stimulation. Psychophysical methods cannot step inside the system that links stimulation to action or give one direct access to components of that system. In particular, perception and sensation are not components but are particular modes of operation of the whole system. I strongly agree with Michaels s (2000) argument that ecological psychology must assert its place in framing the problems that neuroscience should address. However, I believe that the best way to achieve that aim is to maintain the fundamental importance of the link between stimulation and action and to place questions about the organization of action at the center of those problems. How is action controlled at many different temporal and spatial scales simultaneously, and how is the information provided by the environment used to achieve that end? REFERENCES DeHaan, E. H. F., Young, A.W., & Newcombe, F. (1987). Face recognition without awareness. Cognitive Neuropsychology, 4, 385 415. Gallese, V., & Goldman, A. (1998). Mirror neurons and the simulation theory of mind-reading. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 2, 493 501. Goodale, M. A. (1998). Visuomotor control: Where does vision end and action begin? Current Biology, 8, R489 R491. Goodale, M. A., Jakobson, L. S., & Keillor, J. M. (1994). Differences in the visual control of pantomimed and natural grasping movements. Neuropsychologia, 32, 1159 1178. Goodale, M. A., Milner, A. D., Jakobson, L. S., & Carey, D. P. (1991). A neurological dissociation between perceiving objects and grasping them. Nature, 349, 154 156. Green, P. R. (1995). Perception and aesthetic appreciation: Does the answer lie in the structure of the stimulus or the structure of action? Ecological Psychology, 7, 379 383. Marshall, J. C., & Halligan, P. W. (1988). Blindsight and insight in visuospatial neglect. Nature, 336, 766 767. Michaels, C. F. (2000). Information, perception, and action: What should ecological psychologists learn from Milner and Goodale (1995)? Ecological Psychology, 12, 241 258. Michaels, C. F., Zeinstra, E. B., & Oudejans, R. R. D. (2001). Information and action in punching a falling ball. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 54A, 69 93. Milner, A. D., & Goodale, M. A. (1995). The visual brain in action. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.

122 GREEN Murphy, K. J., Carey, D. P., & Goodale, M. A. (1998). The perception of spatial relations in a patient with visual form agnosia. Cognitive Neuropsychology, 15, 705 722. Prinz, W. (1997). Perception and action planning. European Journal of Cognitive Psychology, 9, 129 154. Weiskrantz, L. (1986). Blindsight. Oxford, England: Clarendon. Westwood, D. A., Chapman, C. D., & Roy, E. A. (2000). Pantomimed actions may be controlled by the ventral visual stream. Experimental Brain Research, 130, 545 548.