HERO. Rational addiction theory a survey of opinions UNIVERSITY OF OSLO HEALTH ECONOMICS RESEARCH PROGRAMME. Working paper 2008: 7

Similar documents
Bounded Rationality, Taxation, and Prohibition 1. Suren Basov 2 and Svetlana Danilkina 3

What is analytical sociology? And is it the future of sociology?

Causality and Statistical Learning

Causality and Statistical Learning

Incentive compatibility in stated preference valuation methods

ECONOMIC MODELS OF ADDICTION AND APPLICATIONS TO CIGARETTE SMOKING AND OTHER SUBSTANCE ABUSE

Consistency in REC Review

"Games and the Good" Strategy

Addiction in the Quasi-Hyperbolic Model

The Economics of tobacco and other addictive goods Hurley, pp

Beyond Subjective and Objective in Statistics

Dancing at Gunpoint: A Review of Herbert Gintis Bounds of Reason

An Experimental Investigation of Self-Serving Biases in an Auditing Trust Game: The Effect of Group Affiliation: Discussion

CHAPTER 3 METHOD AND PROCEDURE

Prof. Dr. Daniel Krähmer: Behavioral Economics SS16 1. Lecture Notes

The Game Prisoners Really Play: Preference Elicitation and the Impact of Communication

The Psychology of Behavioral Economics

Behavioral Economics, Past, Present and Future by Richard Thaler [AER 2016]

Behavioural Economics University of Oxford Vincent P. Crawford Michaelmas Term 2012

The idea of an essentially contested concept is incoherent.

Virtual Mentor Ethics Journal of the American Medical Association September 2005, Volume 7, Number 9

Chapter 1 Social Science and Its Methods

Environmental Psychology in Context 1. Special Issue of the Journal of Environmental Psychology. Edited by David Uzzell and Gabriel Moser

7. Provide information - media campaigns such as know your units, labelling on drinks

Autonomy as a Positive Value Some Conceptual Prerequisites Niklas Juth Dept. of Philosophy, Göteborg University

Durkheim. Durkheim s fundamental task in Rules of the Sociological Method is to lay out

Whose psychological concepts?

TIPSHEET QUESTION WORDING

Discovering Diversity Profile Group Report

Rational Behavior in Cigarette Consumption: Evidence from the United States

This is a repository copy of Ruling Minds: Psychology in the British Empire, by Erik Linstrum.

Insight Assessment Measuring Thinking Worldwide

GPP 501 Microeconomic Analysis for Public Policy Fall 2017

Annual Report 2005 of the Mortality Forum

What Constitutes a Good Contribution to the Literature (Body of Knowledge)?

Elementary School Social Studies PreK Grade 2

By Mats Alvesson & Jörgen Sandberg (Constructing Research Questions, Sage 2013)

Writing does not occur in a vacuum. Ask yourself the following questions:

What is Experimental Economics? ECO663 Experimental Economics. Paul Samuelson once said. von Neumann and Morgenstern. Sidney Siegel 10/15/2016

POLI 343 Introduction to Political Research

Views, values and contexts in Honour

Critical Thinking and Reading Lecture 15

Recognizing Ambiguity

Econ 270: Theoretical Modeling 1

PSYCHOLOGISM VS. CONVENTIONAL VALUES by L.A. Boland

The Interactive Effects of Ethical Norms and Subordinate Recommendations on Accounting Decisions

SUPPLEMENTARY INFORMATION

Applying GRADE-CERQual to qualitative evidence synthesis findings paper 4: how to assess coherence

Promoting Development of Advanced Morality among Adolescents. Suraj Ketan Samal. University of Nebraska-Lincoln

Clicker quiz: Should the cocaine trade be legalized? (either answer will tell us if you are here or not) 1. yes 2. no

Identifying best practice in actions on tobacco smoking to reduce health inequalities

THEORY OF REASONED ACTION

Value Differences Between Scientists and Practitioners: A Survey of SIOP Members

0457 GLOBAL PERSPECTIVES

An Introduction to Behavioral Economics

Comparing Direct and Indirect Measures of Just Rewards: What Have We Learned?

Shaping the Economics of Happiness: The Fundamental Contributions of Richard A. Easterlin

Rational Choice Theory I: The Foundations of the Theory

Mommy Wars Redux: A False Conflict

THE INTEGRITY PROFILING SYSTEM

SOCIAL AND CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY

A23C581 Consumer Behavior. Introductory lecture 19 February 2018

On the diversity principle and local falsifiability

Blackhawk School District

The Economics of Smoking

Research on happiness and economics

INTERVIEWS II: THEORIES AND TECHNIQUES 5. CLINICAL APPROACH TO INTERVIEWING PART 1

E-BOOK EXAMPLES OF SOCIAL PSYCHOLOGY

Peer workers and Service innovation. Experiences from Norway, Sweden and Canada. Karl-Johan Johansen and Dag Øivind Antonsen

Theory and Methods Question Bank

Home Economics Students Perception of the Relevance of Consumer Education to Clothing Choice in Nigeria (Pp )

Dancing at gunpoint. A review of Herbert Gintis s The bounds of reason: game theory and the unification of the behavioral sciences

Assignment 4: True or Quasi-Experiment

Is Leisure Theory Needed For Leisure Studies?

Cohesive Writing Module: Introduction

COACHING I 7. CORE COMPETENCIES

Spiritual, Moral, Social and Cultural Development at The Grove Primary School

Global Food Security Baseline Survey

Assurance Engagements Other Than Audits or Reviews of Historical Financial Information

Generalization and Theory-Building in Software Engineering Research

23C581 Consumer Behavior Introductory lecture 3 November 2016

Happiness. A Revolution in Economics

Reasons and Emotions that Guide Stakeholder s Decisions and Have an Impact on Corporate Reputation

Cognitive domain: Comprehension Answer location: Elements of Empiricism Question type: MC

the examples she used with her arguments were good ones because they lead the reader to the answer concerning the thesis statement.

PDRF About Propensity Weighting emma in Australia Adam Hodgson & Andrey Ponomarev Ipsos Connect Australia

Mental Health and Optimal Avoidance Behavior

The Psychology of Inductive Inference

Journal of Political Economy, Vol. 93, No. 2 (Apr., 1985)

GE SLO: Ethnic-Multicultural Studies Results

Abstracts. An International Journal of Interdisciplinary Research. From Mentalizing Folk to Social Epistemology

Professional Ethics. Introduction

MBA SEMESTER III. MB0050 Research Methodology- 4 Credits. (Book ID: B1206 ) Assignment Set- 1 (60 Marks)

VOLUME B. Elements of Psychological Treatment

Are Experimental Economists Prone to Framing Effects? A Natural Field Experiment

Perception-Based Evidence of Validity

A MODEL OF STUDENTS UNIVERSITY DECISION- MAKING BEHAVIOR

Knowledge in economics: game-theoretic vs market-process

Prepare for tobacco industry interference

Transcription:

Rational addiction theory a survey of opinions Hans Olav Melberg Institute of Health Management and Health Economics UNIVERSITY OF OSLO HEALTH ECONOMICS RESEARCH PROGRAMME Working paper 2008: 7 HERO

Rational addiction theory a survey of opinions Hans Olav Melberg* University of Oslo Institute for Health Management and Health Economics, HERO Health Economics Research Programme at the University of Oslo HERO 2008 * Hans Olav Melberg, Institute of Health Management and Health Economics, University of Oslo, PO Box 1089, Blindern, N-0317 Oslo, Norway, and e-mail for correspondence: hans.melberg@gmail.com Health Economics Research Programme at the University of Oslo Financial support from The Research Council of Norway is acknowledged. ISSN 1501-9071 (print version.), ISSN 1890-1735 (online), ISBN 82-7756-191-1

Abstract This paper reports briefly on some of the results from a survey of academics who have written about the theory of rational addiction. The topic is important in itself because if the literature is viewed by its participants as an intellectual game, then policy makers should be aware of this so as not to derive actual policy from toy models. More generally, the answers shed light on the nature of economics and how many economists think about model building, evidence requirements and the policy relevance of their work. A majority of the respondents believe the literature is a success story that demonstrates the power of economic reasoning. At the same time they also believe the empirical evidence to be weak, and they disagree both on the type of evidence that would validate the theory and the policy implications. Taken together this points to an interesting gap. On the one hand most of the respondents claim that the theory has valuable real-world implications. On the other hand they do not believe the theory has received empirical support. Keywords Rational addiction theory, survey of opinions of economists, disagreement on evidence criteria and interpretation of evidence. 1

1 INTRODUCTION It has been argued that rational addiction theory is a success story that demonstrates the power of applying economic analysis to topics that used to be viewed as outside the realm of economics. In the words of Orphanides and Zervos (1998) the literature initiated by Becker and Murphy (1988) shows that harmful addictive behaviour is largely consistent with the standard axioms of rational, forward looking utility maximization and should no longer be considered a challenge to standard economic analysis. In contrast to this, it has also been claimed that rational addiction theory is absurd, that the silliness of theories such as rational addiction raises the question of how it can be taken seriously and that the literature is more an intellectual game than a true effort to understand addiction (Rogeberg 2004). Given the importance of explaining addiction as a phenomenon in itself, and as a case study of economic imperialism in general, it was decided to investigate how economists working within this area viewed their work and the literature. This is important because if the literature really is viewed by its participants as an intellectual game, then policy makers should be aware of this so as not to derive actual policy from toy models. More generally, the answers shed light on the nature of economics and how many economists think about model building, evidence requirements and the policy relevance of their work. To examine what the field itself thinks about rational addiction theory, we conducted a survey among authors who had published one or more articles about rational addiction. Three main topics are covered. First, do economists take rational addiction seriously as plausible theory of addiction? Second, do they agree on the kind of 2

evidence that is relevant to test the theory and the extent to which the rational addiction literature provide this evidence? Third, what, if any, implications do they believe the theory has? Previous research on the opinions of economists has already established that there is significant normative and positive disagreement on many economic issues (Alston 1992, Davis 1997, Frey 1992). It also seems that ideology is not the only or major driving force behind these disagreements (Caplan 2002, Mayer 2001). No previous survey has been conducted on the topic of rational addiction, but there is some relevant related research. For instance, Goldfarb et al (2001) have shown that theories of addiction may be underdetermined in the sense that existing data may not be sufficient to distinguish between competing theories. Also, Yuengert (2006) has demonstrated that multiple research goals can lead to different evaluations of rational addiction theory. Hence, the contribution of the current survey is not mainly to argue that there is disagreement or express surprise at the fact that there seems to be a tendency to arrive at different conclusions when faced with the same evidence. Instead, and in contrast to previous surveys of economists, the current survey is limited to rational addiction and this allows it to focuses explicitly on the links between overall views of the literature, evidence requirements and policy implications. By focusing on one topic and combining and contrasting the answers in these three categories it becomes possible not only to discover disagreements, but to reveal puzzling internal tensions. For instance, one of the major results from the survey is the puzzling finding that the theory of rational addiction represents a success story with quite strong implications, while at the same time it is admitted that the empirical evidence is often very weak. 3

2 METHOD The survey was limited to researchers who had published articles with the phrase "rational addiction" in the title, as a keyword or in the abstract of the article. Working papers, books and publications in languages other than English were excluded. In order to create a list of the most important papers and authors, we created a database with the top 200 references from google.scholar using the search phrase "rational addiction" and combined this with the results from searches in EconLit, ISI Web of Science and PubMed using the phrase "Rational Addiction." In the end, these searches yielded a list of 111 articles with 156 authors or co-authors. Both e-mail and regular mail was used to make the selected sample aware of the survey. 34 authors were lost because of incomplete contact information. This means that 122 were invited to participate in the survey. 64 of these responded by answering our questions (52%). The survey consisted of 25 questions and most of these were in the form of statements to which respondents indicated their extent of agreement/disagreement a scale from 1 to 5 where 1 was I completely disagree and 5 was I completely agree. 3 RESULTS AND DISCUSSION It has been argued that Economics has increasingly become an intellectual game played for its own sake and not for its practical consequences for understanding the economic world (Blaug 1998). This may be true, but from the survey it seems clear that the sentiment is not shared by many economists. Few - but not insignificantly so - agreed to the statement that rational addiction theories is part of an intellectual game 4

with no practical significance (17%). Instead, a large majority of the respondents, 72%, believed that rational addiction theory illustrates the power of economic analysis. This is comforting in the sense that it indicates that the participants really do believe in their work as having importance beyond getting papers published. However, for those who argue that rational addiction theories are patently absurd, the dominant belief that the theory illustrates the power of economic analysis may be more unsettling than comforting. In order for a theory to be powerful it should ideally have a solid empirical foundation and important implications. Unless these conditions are satisfied, the strong belief in the theory may be unsettling as a sign of ideological arrogance in the face of empirical facts. For this reason it is interesting to examine exactly what it is that makes the respondents believe the theory and which implications they believe it has. Testing a theory requires consensus on the kind of evidence that is relevant and the interpretation of that evidence. There are many possible model selection criteria (Goldfarb 2001, Yuengert 2006), but the rational addiction literature has typically focused on whether the theory is consistent with the data on the demand for drugs and price changes. There seems to be a general consensus about the relevance of this type of evidence (see Table 1). For instance, a large majority agreed that the theory should be consistent with macro-level evidence on the demand of addictive goods (74%). Interestingly, the kind of evidence believed to be most relevant, was also the area in which many respondents believed the data gave the weak support to the theory. Only 27% agreed that the theory was consistent with the macro-evidence on elasticities and consumption patterns. 5

Table 1: Evidence relating to theory In general, rational addiction theory should be/is consistent with Yes, rational addiction theory should be Yes, the data indicate that the theory really is the standard axioms of economic choice-theory 52 % 53 % what we know about how people make decisions 57 % 27 % the actual beliefs of real consumers or consistent with what is known about such physical and other effects of drugs 61 % 22 % data on the market demand for addictive goods (elasticities, usage patterns, etc.) 74 % 27 % There was less agreement on the relevance of evidence at the individual level about how people actually make decisions. A majority, 57%, believed the theory should be consistent with evidence of this kind, but 20% disagreed. To some extent this reflects the attitude that all that matters is whether the model acts as-if it is compatible with macro implications that comes out of the model as opposed to the behavioural assumptions that goes into the model. As for the assumptions that go into that model, there was, surprisingly, no general consensus on whether rational addiction theory should be based on the standard axioms of economic choice theory. The contribution by Becker and Murphy (1988) claims to be an extension of this framework, but the respondents are divided about whether this is how we should model addiction. Part of the reason for this may be that interpretations of standard theory differ. For instance, following Becker and Murphy (1988) the standard approach often employs exponential discounting. Other 6

contributions emphasise hyperbolic discounting, weakness of will or related mechanisms that can create time inconsistent behaviour (Ainslie 1991; Loewenstein 1999). One might argue that the precise functional form of time preferences is not an essential axiom of the standard rational choice frame, but since opinions on this differ, the respondents also differ in their answers. One of the questions that divided the field most was whether the theory of rational addiction should be interpreted as an as-if theory. The rational addiction literature has often been criticised for making very strong assumptions about the rationality of the individuals who engage in substance abuse. Typically the users are not only seen as capable of responding to incentives, but being able to create a long term plan of how much drugs to use taking into account how the use will affect their future desire to use drugs (i.e., rational taste planning). When confronted with the criticism that many substance users seem not to have such a plan for their career, the usual defense is Friedeman s (1953) as-if justification: All that matters is whether the agents act as if their behaviour is determined by a rational plan of how much to consume at various points in time, not whether the addicts actually make a rational plan. 38% of the respondents in the survey agreed with this as-if argument, while 43% disagreed. Moreover, even those who agreed that an as-if model was enough for the theory to be relevant, did not believe that consumers of addictive goods actually behave as-if the models were correct. Only 27% of the sample agreed that the consumers behave as-if the model was correct. 7

Table 2: Economists opinions on rational addiction and implications The Rational Addiction literature Disagree Neutral Agree provides insights into how addicts choose that are relevant for psychologists and treatment professionals 42 % 19 % 39 %... contains insights on the welfare consequences of addictive goods and public policies towards these 22 % 22 % 56 % provides evidence that addictions are actually a sequence of rational choices maximising welfare/utility 53 % 20 % 27 %... provides useful tools for predicting how addicts in the aggregate will respond to incentives 25 % 30 % 44 %... extends and enriches consumer theory 16 % 11 % 73 % Given the hesitation to agree that the theory is empirically verified, one might expect similar hesitation about the insights the theory has to offer or its usefulness in policy analysis (Table 2). In fact, the respondents split into two roughly equal and opposing factions when asked whether the rational addiction literature provided insight that were relevant for how to treat addictions: 39% agreed and 42% disagreed. To some extent one might expect that those who are reluctant to draw treatment implications from the theory are the same individuals who only take the theory as an as-if theory since they focus more on predictive success than explanatory success. However, a cross-tabulation of the answers show that almost half of the as-if adherents also argued that the rational addiction literature had implications for treatment of addicts. The same puzzling gap between the empirical evidence behind the theory and claims about the theories insights can be seen when the respondents are asked about aggregate policy implications. A majority agree that the theory gives insight into the welfare 8

consequences of addictive goods (56%) at the same time that they do not believe one of its major assumptions - that addicts rationally choose an optimal and welfare maximizing path of consumption over time (27% agreed with this). Similarly, while agreeing that the empirical basis was weak, 73% agreed that the literature extends and enriches consumer theory. 4 CONCLUSION There are at least two main possible interpretations of the results from this survey. The charitable interpretation is that although the participants judge the theory to be empirically shaky, what is believed to be true yields enough insight to judge the literature as an overall success. The less charitable interpretation would be to argue that the survey reveals a puzzling belief that theories can be used to derive important and valid policy implications even when its assumptions are not believed and the theory is admitted to have weak empirical support. To distinguish between these two interpretations would require a more subjective assessment the value of the insights and whether they are enough to qualify as a success story. This survey has only identified what may be an interesting gap and as such it only constitutes the raw material for further investigation and discussion. Acknowledgements The survey was funded by the Health Economics Research Programme (HERO) at the University of Oslo and it was created and conducted in cooperation with Ole Jørgen Røgeberg. 9

REFERENCES Ainslie, G. (1991) Derivation of rational economic behavior from hyperbolic discount curves, American Economic Review 81: 334-340. Alston, R. M., J. R. Kearl, and M. B. Vaughan. (1992) Is There a Consensus among Economists in the 1990s?, American Economic Review 82: 203-09. Becker, G. S. and K. M. Murphy (1988) A Theory of Rational Addiction, Journal of Political Economy 96: 675-700. Blaug, M. (1998) Disturbing Currents in Modern Economics, Challenge 11: 1-11. Caplan, B. (2002) Systematically Biased Beliefs About Economics: Robust Evidence of Judgemental Anomalies from the Survey of Americans and Economists on the Economy, Economic Journal 112: 433-58. Davis, W. L. (1997) Economists Perceptions of Their Own Research: A Survey of the Profession, American Journal of Economics and Sociology 56: 159 72. Frey, B. S., and R. Eichenberger (1992) Economics and Economists - a European Perspective, American Economic Review 82: 216-20. Friedman, M. (1953) The Methodology of Positive Economics, In Essays in Positive Economics, Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, pp. 3 43. 10

Goldfarb, R. S., T. C. Leonard, and S. M. Suranovic (2001) Are Rival Theories of Smoking Undetermined? Journal of Economic Methodology 8: 229-51. Loewenstein, G. (1999) A Visceral Account of Addiction, In J. Elster and O. J. Skog, Getting Hooked, Cambridge University Press, pp. 235-265. Mayer, T. (2001) The Role of Ideology in Disagreeements among Economists: A Quantitative Analysis, Journal of Economic Methodology 8: 253-73. Orphanides, A. and D. Zervos (1995) Rational Addiction with Learning and Regret, Journal of Political Economy 103: 739-58. Rogeberg, O. (2004) Taking Absurd Theories Seriously: Economics and the Case of Rational Addiction, Philosophy of Science 71: 263-285. Yuengert, A. M. (2006) Model Selection and Multiple Research Goals: The Case of Rational Addiction, Journal of Economic Methodology 13: 77-94. 11