Strategic Uncertainty and Risk Attitudes: The Experimental Connection*

Similar documents
Poverty in dictator games: Awakening solidarity

The Game Prisoners Really Play: Preference Elicitation and the Impact of Communication

Accepting Zero in the Ultimatum Game Does Not Reflect Selfish. preferences

TITLE: MEN ARE FROM MARS, WOMEN FROM VENUS, ONLY WITH INCENTIVES

Effects of Sequential Context on Judgments and Decisions in the Prisoner s Dilemma Game

Belief Formation in a Signalling Game without Common Prior: An Experiment

Appendix: Instructions for Treatment Index B (Human Opponents, With Recommendations)

Online Appendix A. A1 Ability

HYPOTHETICAL AND REAL INCENTIVES IN THE ULTIMATUM GAME AND ANDREONI S PUBLIC GOODS GAME: AN EXPERIMENTAL STUDY

Introduction to Game Theory Autonomous Agents and MultiAgent Systems 2015/2016

Assessment and Estimation of Risk Preferences (Outline and Pre-summary)

Emanuela Carbonara. 31 January University of Bologna - Department of Economics

GROUP DECISION MAKING IN RISKY ENVIRONMENT ANALYSIS OF GENDER BIAS

Testing the level of consistency between choices and beliefs in games using eye-tracking

Veronika Grimm, Friederike Mengel. Let me sleep on it: Delay reduces rejection rates in Ultimatum Games RM/10/017

Multiple Switching Behavior in Multiple Price Lists

Behavioral Game Theory

Beliefs and (In)Stability in Normal-Form Games

Which determines Dictating the Risk, risk preference or social image? Experimental evidence-

Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization

Supplementary Information Appendix for: Prenatal Sex Hormones (2D:4D Digit Ratio) and Social Integration

Cooperation in a Prisoners Dilemma with Losses. Results from an Experimental Study.

Experimental Testing of Intrinsic Preferences for NonInstrumental Information

Games With Incomplete Information: Bayesian Nash Equilibrium

Adjustment Patterns and Equilibrium Selection in Experimental Signaling Games

PREFERENCE REVERSAL: AN EXPERIMENTAL INVESTIGATION OF ECONOMIC AND PSYCHOLOGICAL HYPOTHESES*

Volume 30, Issue 3. Boundary and interior equilibria: what drives convergence in a beauty contest'?

Inequity and Risk Aversion. in Sequential Public Good Games

A Possible Explanation to Yea-saying in Contingent Valuation Surveys*

Take it or leave it: experimental evidence on the effect of time-limited offers on consumer behaviour Robert Sugden* Mengjie Wang* Daniel John Zizzo**

Sequential Decision and Strategy Vector Methods in Ultimatum Bargaining: Evidence on the Strength of Other- Regarding Behavior

Behavioral Game Theory

Fairness and Reciprocity in the Hawk-Dove game

COOPERATION 1. How Economic Rewards Affect Cooperation Reconsidered. Dan R. Schley and John H. Kagel. The Ohio State University

Contributions and Beliefs in Liner Public Goods Experiment: Difference between Partners and Strangers Design

CeDEx Discussion Paper Series ISSN

DIFFERENCES IN THE ECONOMIC DECISIONS OF MEN AND WOMEN: EXPERIMENTAL EVIDENCE*

Performance in competitive Environments: Gender differences

Long-Term Commitment and Cooperation

KRANNERT SCHOOL OF MANAGEMENT

ULTIMATUM GAME. An Empirical Evidence. Presented By: SHAHID RAZZAQUE

Identity, Homophily and In-Group Bias: Experimental Evidence

Alternative Payoff Mechanisms for Choice under Risk. by James C. Cox, Vjollca Sadiraj Ulrich Schmidt

Eliciting Beliefs by Paying in Chance

Infinitely repeated games in the laboratory: four perspectives on discounting and random termination

Examining differences between two sets of scores

Supporting Information

When Do Groups Perform Better Than Individuals? A Company Takeover Experiment. Institute for Empirical Research in Economics University of Zurich

Title. Author(s)Takahashi, Nobuyuki. Issue Date Doc URL. Type. Note. File Information. Adaptive Bases of Human Rationality

IN THE iterated prisoner s dilemma (IPD), two players

An Experiment to Evaluate Bayesian Learning of Nash Equilibrium Play

Cooperation in Risky Environments: Decisions from Experience in a Stochastic Social Dilemma

Statistics and Probability

Lecture 2: Learning and Equilibrium Extensive-Form Games

Experimenter Demand Effects and Altruism towards the Experimenter

Koji Kotani International University of Japan. Abstract

The Effect of Stakes in Distribution Experiments. Jeffrey Carpenter Eric Verhoogen Stephen Burks. December 2003

Gender composition in teams

Feldexperimente in der Soziologie

Does the elicitation method impact the WTA/WTP disparity?* Sarah Brebner a and Joep Sonnemans a,b,c a

Using Experimental Methods to Inform Public Policy Debates. Jim Murphy Presentation to ISER July 13, 2006

Endowment Effects in Contests

How to identify trust and reciprocity

The role of training in experimental auctions

Social Status and Group Norms: Indirect Reciprocity in a Helping Experiment

EXPERIMENTAL ECONOMICS INTRODUCTION. Ernesto Reuben

Today s lecture. A thought experiment. Topic 3: Social preferences and fairness. Overview readings: Fehr and Fischbacher (2002) Sobel (2005)

Size of Ellsberg Urn. Emel Filiz-Ozbay, Huseyin Gulen, Yusufcan Masatlioglu, Erkut Ozbay. University of Maryland

Asymmetric and Endogenous Within-Group Communication in Competitive Coordination Games

The Impact of the Degree of Responsibility and Mutual Decision Making on Choices under Risk

Choice set options affect the valuation of risky prospects

JENA ECONOMIC RESEARCH PAPERS

Experimental evidence 1

Equilibrium Selection In Coordination Games

Comparative Ignorance and the Ellsberg Paradox

How Different Choice Strategies Can Affect the Risk Elicitation Process

Equilibrium Cooperation in Three-Person, Choice-of-Partner Games

Clicker quiz: Should the cocaine trade be legalized? (either answer will tell us if you are here or not) 1. yes 2. no

Aspiration Levels and Educational Choices. An experimental study

Paradoxes and Violations of Normative Decision Theory. Jay Simon Defense Resources Management Institute, Naval Postgraduate School

The Way to Choose: How Does Perceived Knowledge Flow

Risk aversion and preferences for redistribution: a laboratory experiment

Potential Surprise Theory as a theoretical foundation for scenario planning

Hedging and Ambiguity

HOT VS. COLD: SEQUENTIAL RESPONSES AND PREFERENCE STABILITY IN EXPERIMENTAL GAMES * August 1998

Topic 3: Social preferences and fairness

The Behavioural Consequences of Unfair Punishment

The Foundations of Behavioral. Economic Analysis SANJIT DHAMI

Altruistic Behavior: Lessons from Neuroeconomics. Kei Yoshida Postdoctoral Research Fellow University of Tokyo Center for Philosophy (UTCP)

The Evolution of Cooperation: The Genetic Algorithm Applied to Three Normal- Form Games

Cooperation among behaviorally heterogeneous players in social dilemma with stay or leave decisions

Let the Dummy Talk! - Unilateral Communication and Discrimination in Three-Person Dictator Experiments -

Learning and Transfer: An Experimental Investigation into Ultimatum Bargaining

Paradoxes and Mechanisms for Choice under Risk By James C. Cox, Vjollca Sadiraj, and Ulrich Schmidt

Social Norms and Reciprocity*

Leadership with Individual Rewards and Punishments

Risk attitude in decision making: A clash of three approaches

Discounting Future Pain: Effects on Self-Reported Pain

Incentives to cheat under loss aversion

Friendship in a Public Good Experiment

Transcription:

Cuadernos de Economía. Vol. 27, 139-152, 2004 Strategic Uncertainty and Risk Attitudes: The Experimental Connection* Pablo Brañas-Garza 1 Francisca Jiménez-Jiménez Departamento de Economía, U. de Jaén, centra Antonio J. Morales GaMes, Departamento de Teoría e Historia Económica, U. de Málaga RESUMEN Este trabajo aporta evidencia experimental sobre la relación entre la aversión al riesgo y las creencias de los jugadores sobre las acciones que tomarán sus rivales en un juego del Dilema de Presos. Los resultados más relevantes son: (i) los aversos al riesgo tienden a pensar que su rival no cooperará, (ii) los amantes del riesgo dan * The idea of this paper came from Nikolaos Georgantzís and Robin Pope, who encourage us to analyse the relationship between beliefs and risk attitudes. Of course, all errors are ours. Financial support from centra: is gratefully acknowledged. Pablo Brañas acknowledges the hospitality of IESA-CSIC during this research. Antonio J. Morales acknowledges (partial) financial support from DGICYT grant nº PB98-1408. 1 Corresponding author: Departamento de Teoría e Historia Económica, Universidad de Granada, Campus de la Cartuja s/n. 18071 Granada. e-mail: pbg@iesaa.csic.es; phone: 00-34-958-246192; fax: 00-34-958-244046.

140 PABLO BRAÑAS-GARZA, FRANCISCA JIMÉNEZ-JIMÉNEZ Y ANTONIO J. MORALES mayor probabilidad de cooperación a sus rivales y (iii) finalmente, los sujetos que consideran que su rival es racional son más aversos que aquéllos que piensan que su oponente cometerá algún error. Palabras clave: teoría de la utilidad esperada, riesgo estratégico, dilema de presos. ABSTRACT In this paper we obtain empirical evidence of the relationship between individuals risk attitudes and individuals beliefs on their rival s choices in the Prisoners Dilemma game. We find that (i) risk-averse subjects seem to think that their opponent will defect, (ii) risk-loving individuals tend to think that their opponent will cooperate with higher probabilities, and (iii) finally, those subjects who believe that the rival will behave rationally are more risk averse than those subjects that believe that the rival will make a mistake, who on average are risk neutral. Keywords: Expected utility theory, Risk attitudes, Strategic risk, Prisoners Dilemma. JEL Classification: C91, C71, D81 1.INTRODUCTION Economic theory rationalises human behaviour by assuming that it is the output of an optimisation problem, in which the decision maker maximises his utility. To this end, it is assumed that economic agents are endowed with a utility function which complies with several properties. In strategic environments, decision makers are assumed to form beliefs about their rivals intended play and to act accordingly, i.e., by maximising expected utility. However, economic theory does not impose any conditions to the factors affecting the formation of beliefs. Even more, this seems an empirical rather than a theoretical question. In this paper we perform an experimental investigation about the relationship (if any) between some properties of the utility function and the beliefs hold by decision makers in strategic environments. In particular, we are interested in the interaction between attitudes toward risk (pure risk) and beliefs in strategic environments (strategic risk). We will analyse this interaction in one of the most popular games: The Prisoners Dilemma. We will use the experimental results reported in Brañas-Garza and Morales (2004, BGM hereafter). These authors analyse subjects behaviour in two games in order to

STRATEGIC UNCERTAINTY AND RISK ATTITUDES 141 THE EXPERIMENTAL CONNECTION get knowledge of subjects beliefs on rival s cooperativeness in the Prisoners Dilemma game. In this paper we complement that analysis by incorporating a third «game» included in those experimental sessions but not reported in BGM. The third game was precisely aimed at getting knowledge of subjects attitude toward risk. Our findings indicate that attitudes toward risk are related to beliefs in strategic environment. We do observe that subjects with more risk aversion think that their rival will defect in the Prisoners Dilemma game. In contrast, risk-loving subjects think that their opponent will cooperate with positive probability. Also, those subjects who believe that the rival will behave rationally are more risk-averse than those subjects that believe that the rival will make a mistake, who on average are risk neutral. Up to now, there exists little evidence on the existence of any relationship between the strategic uncertainty and the attitudes toward risk. Sabater and Georgantzís (2002) study the role of risk aversion on players behaviour in repeated prisoners dilemma games. They find that risk aversion relates negatively with the disposition to cooperate. Specifically, the most risk-averse players choose Nash strategies more often than the less risk-averse ones. However, these authors focus on the importance of the risk aversion on the players actions, not on the beliefs they hold, like us. The rest of the paper is structured as follows. Section 1 explains the experimental design describing in detail the methodology and procedures. Section 2 presents the main results obtained from the experiment and section 3 concludes. 2.DESIGN Our research is based on the comparison of a subject s responses across two parallel situations, both involving uncertainty and risk. To rationalise behaviour, we will assume that the decision-makers behave as maximising expected utility. Under this within-subject design, first we propose an experimental setting to test for our individuals risk attitudes. Second, subjects face two different strategic games: An Entry game and a Prisoners Dilemma game. This second setting allows us to estimate the subjects beliefs about their rival s behaviour. Each of the two experimental settings is described in the following subsections 2. 2 Although this design may generate some order effects, BGM treatment 2 (not reported here) rejects any rank-order effects. BGM treatment 2 consist only of a PDG without any previous game

142 PABLO BRAÑAS-GARZA, FRANCISCA JIMÉNEZ-JIMÉNEZ Y ANTONIO J. MORALES 2.1. Testing for attitudes toward risk In decision making under risk, there exists a wide variety of elicitation and classification techniques according to the attitudes toward risk (asking individuals the willingness to pay, the willingness to accept or using a lottery choice procedure). The experimental literature shows that subjects exhibit a significant degree of heterogeneity in the attitudes toward risk and that this is an important issue to take into account in games like auctions, negotiation or investment decisions. It is important to point out that our objective here is to control the individual behaviour under risk and to obtain a classification based on the risk attitudes distribution, not to measure attitudes toward risk. To test for individual risk attitudes, we consider a slightly modified version of Holt and Laury (2002). Concretely, we ask subjects to choose between a sure amount of money and a lottery. However, in contrast to the general tendency in the literature, we do not offer directly the lottery but the following two-player game 3 : Figure 1.Game 0 E NE E 4,4 8,3 NE 3,8 0,0 In this game, individuals were told that they were the player 1 and that player 2 s choice would be selected by the toss of a fair coin; hence, player 2 would play each action with a 50% of probability. The sequence players followed was: First, they had to decide which strategy they will play and, second, they had to fill in the following payments card (see figure 2). (for 55 subjects) and not any difference is found between the data used in this paper and treatment 2 data set. Both the Mann-Whitney (Z = 0, 78; p = 0, 43) and Kolmogorov-Smirnov (Z = 0, 30; p = 1, 00) tests do no reject the null hypothesis of equal distribution between data from treatment 1 (used here) and treatment 2 (rank-order control). 3 The characteristics of this game are similar to those of the games used in the second experimental setting.

STRATEGIC UNCERTAINTY AND RISK ATTITUDES 143 THE EXPERIMENTAL CONNECTION Figure 2.Payment Card 1ST CHOICE: PLAY OR 1 EURO FOR SURE 2ND CHOICE: PLAY OR 2 EURO FOR SURE 3RD CHOICE: PLAY OR 3 EURO FOR SURE 4TH CHOICE: PLAY OR 4 EURO FOR SURE 5TH CHOICE: PLAY OR 5 EURO FOR SURE 6TH CHOICE: PLAY OR 6 EURO FOR SURE 7TH CHOICE: PLAY OR 7 EURO FOR SURE 8TH CHOICE: PLAY OR 8 EURO FOR SURE 9TH CHOICE: PLAY OR 9 EURO FOR SURE 10TH CHOICE: PLAY OR 10 EURO FOR SURE As we can see, the payments card is a set of ten decisions where each of them consists of choosing between a sure amount of money (ranked from 1 to 10) or playing the game. We assume that when filling the payment card, the individual considers that the relevant row of the above game is the one corresponding to his chosen strategy. Hence, the game reduces to a lottery and therefore, an individual would choose to play the lottery if the sure monetary payoff is lower than the certain equivalent of the lottery. Note that the amount of money at which the individual switches from playing the game to the sure amount of money is precisely the certain equivalent of the lottery, which we will named the elicited value of the game. As an example, consider the dominant strategy for the player 1. It gives either 4 or 8 with the same probability. This implies that under Expected Utility Theory, we can only characterise the respondents attitudes toward risk into this interval. So, a value of 6 would mean that he is a risk neutral person. If the value is lower than 6, the individual would be risk averse and risk loving if his value was greater than 6. There exist however two experimental behavioural patterns under risk that the expected utility framework does not explain, that is, the attraction to and the repulsion from chance see Pope (1997) for a discussion of the «utility and disutility of chance» from both a descriptive and normative point of view and Albers et al. (2000) for experimental evidence for attractions to chance. In our experiment, an elicited value smaller than the minimum available payoff might reflect repulsion from chance. In contrast, an elicited value greater than the maximum available payoff might reflect an attraction to chance. In this research, rather than excluding these individuals we will incorporate them in our analysis into two categories: Repulsion and Attraction from chance. Hence, we

144 PABLO BRAÑAS-GARZA, FRANCISCA JIMÉNEZ-JIMÉNEZ Y ANTONIO J. MORALES might have up to five categories of risk attitudes to classify individuals according to the elicited value in game 0: Repulsion (1-3), Aversion (4-5), Neutrality (6), Loving (7-8) and Attraction (0-10). 2.2. Eliciting values on rival s cooperativeness on the Prisoners Dilemma This section summarises the methodology followed by BGM. The experiment involves two games: An Entry game and a Prisoner s Dilemma game. Individuals were first asked to choose the strategy (Enter or Not enter) in each game and, after playing each game, they were invited to fill in the payments card. Figure 3 plots the payoffs matrices of both games. Figure 3.Game 1 & Game 2 E NE E 4,4 8,3 NE 3,8 0,0 Entry Game E NE E 4,4 8,3 NE 3,8 7,7 Prisoner s Dilemma Two remarks are in place. First, note that game 1 is the same as game 0 used to characterize the players risk attitudes. However in game 1, the player 2 is a subject randomly selected among all participants and therefore player 1 s subjective beliefs on player 2 s actions play an important role in player 1 s behaviour. In particular, his belief or his subjective probability of player 2 choosing the dominated strategy critically affects his value of the game elicited by the payments card. Second, notice that the unique difference between games 1 and 2 is the outcome yielded by the pair of the dominated strategies (NE, NE). In particular, both games are dominance solvable and the unique prediction based on dominance criteria is that players will choose the dominant strategy E. But in the Entry game there is no scope for cooperation whereas in the Prisoners Dilemma game comes out the possibility of cooperation. Our methodology is to compare players elicited values across these two games. Note that any difference in values, i.e. any change in beliefs, can be interpreted as motivated by the appearance of the cooperative dilemma. Hence, the comparison of

STRATEGIC UNCERTAINTY AND RISK ATTITUDES 145 THE EXPERIMENTAL CONNECTION players values across games provides us with information about beliefs and also about how players regard the possibility of cooperation in the Prisoners Dilemma. As a result of the comparison between the elicited values across the two games, subjects can be classified according to the following taxonomy 4 : Rational rival: This individual thinks that his rival will play the rational strategy in both games with probability 1. This implies that the elicited value in both games corresponds to the minimum available payoff 5. Trembling-hand rival: This individual believes that the rival will use the same completely mixed strategy in both games. That is, he thinks that with the same positive probability, the rival will deviate from the rational strategy in both games. Payoffs rival: This individual thinks that his rival will use a different mixed strategy in each game. That is, he supposes that the social issue attached to the Prisoners Dilemma game will affect his rival s behaviour. We will now review our experimental findings in the next section. 3.RESULTS We first present a table displaying the number of experimental subjects in each category. Note that individuals are classified by both beliefs and risk attitudes. Quite fortunately, there are subjects in every category with the unique exception of Rational rival-attraction players (see table 1) 6. 4 In BGM there was also a classification according to played actions. In this paper, however, we do not draw such distinction because our emphasis is on beliefs rather than actions. 5 Brosig (2002) performs a different classification of individual predictions about rival actions in PD games. These predictions are based on pre-play communication without monitoring. 6 Using Wilcoxon non-parametric test for 2-related samples we observe that there exist strong differences (x 2 = 2, 79; p= 0, 00) between valuation in game 0 (risk aversion test) and game 1 (entry game). This result illustrates that individuals perceive the difference between playing against a machine and against a human rival.

146 PABLO BRAÑAS-GARZA, FRANCISCA JIMÉNEZ-JIMÉNEZ Y ANTONIO J. MORALES Table 1.Experimental Results RATIONAL T-HAND PAYOFF TOTAL REPULSION 3 1 2 6 AVERSION 10 7 16 33 NEUTRAL 4 9 12 25 LOVING 2 9 6 17 ATTRACTION 0 2 1 3 TOTAL 19 28 37 84 There are two obvious ways to analyse the relationship between attitudes toward risk and beliefs. The first one would be the study of the distribution of beliefs (strategic risk) conditional to risk attitudes. The second one would be to explore the distribution of risk aversion within each group of individuals ranked by their beliefs. In the next sections we undertake both. 3.1. Strategic Risk conditional to Risk Attitudes In this section we first cluster subjects conditional to their attitude toward risk. This analysis will help us to understand whether risk attitude affects the formation of beliefs on rival s actions in the Prisoners Dilemma game. Table 2 and Figure 4 illustrate the experimental results. Table 2.Beliefs By Risk Att.(%) RATIONAL T-HAND PAYOFF TOTAL REPULSION 50,0% 16,7% 35,3% 6 AVERSION 30,3% 21,2% 48,5% 33 NEUTRAL 16,0% 36,0% 48,0% 25 LOVING 11,8% 52,9% 33,3% 17 ATTRACTION 0,0% 66,7% 33,3% 3 TOTAL 19 28 37 84 Figure 4 give us a clearer picture. Rational rival individuals are more probable in categories of enhanced risk aversion while T-Hand rival subjects are more numerous in risky stadiums. The former shows a decreasing trend along the risk axis and the later run in opposite direction. However, Payoff Rival subjects do not follow any clear trend, being equally distributed along the risk intervals.

STRATEGIC UNCERTAINTY AND RISK ATTITUDES 147 THE EXPERIMENTAL CONNECTION Figure 4 100% 75% 50% 25% 0% Repul.Aversion Neutral Loving Atract. Rational T-Hand Payoff By focusing on rational rival players, we can get knowledge of the evolution of the fraction of the population who believes that their rival will behave rationally in the Prisoners Dilemma. Our result shows that the higher the risk aversion, the higher the belief that the rival will be rational. Hence, there is positive correlation between risk aversion and beliefs on rival s rationality 7. The evolution of T-Hand players suggests that the higher the risk love, the higher the belief that the rival will make a mistake and play the cooperative action. Finally, by considering the evolution of payoffs rival players we can get knowledge of the fraction of the population who believes that cooperation is an issue for their rival in the Prisoners Dilemma. Our results suggest that there is no correlation between this belief and the attitude toward risk. Our interpretation of the above results is as follows. Notice that in the Prisoners Dilemma game and, regardless of the action played by a given individual, the higher his belief on the rival playing the cooperative action, the higher his payoff. Hence, it 7 Recall that we use rational in the traditional sense (EUT).

148 PABLO BRAÑAS-GARZA, FRANCISCA JIMÉNEZ-JIMÉNEZ Y ANTONIO J. MORALES is as if a risk averse player is pessimistic about getting a good payoff whereas a risk loving player is somehow optimistic about it. 3.2. Risk Attitudes conditional to Strategic Risk In this section we perform a complementary analysis. We classify subjects by beliefs and then we characterize their attitudes toward risk, i.e. specifically we analyse their certain equivalent. This sort of analysis is appropriate to detect different attitudes toward risk among different group of individuals. Next table illustrates the main descriptive statistics for each group: Rational rival, T-Hand rival and Payoff rival subjects. Table 3.Descriptive statistics RATIONAL T-HAND PAYOFF N 19 28 37 AVERAGE 4,68 6,21 5,40 MEDIAN 5 6 6 MODE 4-5 6 6 ST. DEV. 1,63 1,61 1,38 VAR.2,67 2,61 1,91 MIN.1 1 3 MAX.7 10 9 A simple visual inspection reveals differences on the average certain equivalent among groups (see row 2, table 3). T-Hand rival subjects are, on average, risk-neutral but both Payoffs rival and Rational rival subjects are risk-averse. The statistical analysis confirms differences among distributions. Kruskall- Wallis non-parametric test for k = 3 unrelated samples rejects the null hypothesis of equal distribution of samples (X 2 =11, 56; p = 0, 00), that is, observations are not drawn from the same population. Median test (X 2 = 6, 03; p= 0, 04) also rejects for a 5% significance level. So rational, t-hand and payoffs individuals differ in their attitudes toward risk. In order to clarify results we run 2-samples tests. Rational rival subjects vs. T-Hand rival subjects: Mann-Witney test rejects (Z= 3, 22; p = 0, 00) equal distribution among samples; Kolmogorov-Smirnov rejects (Z = 1, 34; p = 0, 05) for?= 5%. Then, Rational rival and T-Hand rival individuals are different in risk aversion.

STRATEGIC UNCERTAINTY AND RISK ATTITUDES 149 THE EXPERIMENTAL CONNECTION Rational rival subjects vs. Payoff rival subjects: Mann-Witney test does not reject (Z= 1, 39; p = 0, 16) equal distribution and Kolmogorov-Smirnov also does not reject (Z = 0, 701; p = 0, 71) the null hypothesis. So, we do not observe differences, in risk aversion, between Rational rival and Payoff rival individuals. Payoff rival subjects vs. T-Hand rival subjects: Mann-Witney test rejects for? =1% (Z= 2, 38; p=0, 01) equal distribution among samples but Kolmogorov- Smirnov also does not reject (Z=1, 15; p =0,, 15) the null hypothesis. Summarising, there exist weak differences among T-Hand rival and Payoff rival individuals. Table 4 below illustrates the distribution of population (relative frequency in %) by certain equivalents in each group. Table 4.Relative frequencies by groups (%) REPULSION AVERSE NEUTRAL LOVING ATTRAC. 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 RATIONAL 5-10 26 26 21 10 - - - PAYOFF - - 5-27 16 32 13 2 - T-HAND 3 - - - 25 32 25 7 3 3 Figure 5 illustrates the cumulative frequencies of the certain equivalent in each group. Observe that the largest percentage of averse individuals and the smallest percentage of risk loving subjects are found within the Rational group. Exactly the opposite to the T-Hand category which displays the largest risk loving share and the smallest percentage of risk averse subjects. Clearly, both groups run in the opposite direction. In the Payoff group, the risk attitudes distribution is more balanced, subjects are distributed more uniformly along the risk categories.

150 PABLO BRAÑAS-GARZA, FRANCISCA JIMÉNEZ-JIMÉNEZ Y ANTONIO J. MORALES Figure 5.Cumulative Frequencies 1 0,9 0,8 0,7 0,6 0,5 0,4 0,3 0,2 0,1 0 0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 Rational T-Hand Payoff 4.CONCLUDING REMARKS In this paper we have investigated empirically the relationship between attitudes toward risk and beliefs on rival cooperativeness in the Prisoners Dilemma game. We have found empirical evidence that risk attitudes affects the beliefs on the rival s choices: (i) The higher the risk aversion, the higher the belief that the rival will behave rationally, and (ii) The higher the risk love, the higher the belief that the rival will make a mistake and play the cooperative action. We offer an interpretation of these findings. Notice that in the Prisoners Dilemma game and regardless of the action played by a given individual, the higher his belief on the rival playing the cooperative action, the higher his payoff. Hence, it is as if a risk averse player is pessimistic about getting a good payoff whereas a risk loving player is somehow optimistic about it. Also, in a complementary analysis, we have also found that those subjects who believe that the rival will behave rationally are more risk averse than those subjects that believe that the rival will make a mistake, who on average are risk neutral. Statistical analysis confirms these ideas.

STRATEGIC UNCERTAINTY AND RISK ATTITUDES 151 THE EXPERIMENTAL CONNECTION Given that a very few research has been done in this field, this paper has intended to open a research agenda on the «connection» between beliefs and risk attitudes. 4.REFERENCES ALBERS, Wulf; POPE, Robin; SELTEN, Reinhart and VOGT, Bodo, «Experimental Evidence of Attractions to Chance», German Economic Review 1 (2), 113-119, 2000. BRAÑAS-GARZA, Pablo and MORALES, Antonio J. «How do subjects assess the Social Trade-off involved in the Prisoner s Dilemma?», 2004. BROSIG, Jeanette, «Identifying Cooperative Behavior: some Experimental Results in a PD Game», Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization 47 (3), 275-290, 2002. HOLT, Charles A. and LAURY, Susan K., «Risk Aversion and Incentive Effects», American Economic Review 92, 1644-1655, 2002. POPE, Robin, «Attractions to and Repulsion from Chance», in Werner Lainfellner and Eckehart Köhler (eds.), Game Theory, Experience, Rationality, Kluwer Dordrecht Institute of Vienna Circle Year Book, 95-107, 1997. SABATER GRANDE, Gerardo and GEORGANTZÍS, Nikolaos, «Accounting for Risk Aversion in Repeated Prisioners Dilemma Games: An experimental Test», Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization 48 (1), 37-50, 2002.