Single-case probabilities and content-neutral norms: a reply to Gigerenzer

Similar documents
Reasoning with Uncertainty. Reasoning with Uncertainty. Bayes Rule. Often, we want to reason from observable information to unobservable information

Representativeness Heuristic and Conjunction Errors. Risk Attitude and Framing Effects

The role of linguistic interpretation in human failures of reasoning

In press, Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes. Frequency Illusions and Other Fallacies. Steven A. Sloman.

Wason's Cards: What is Wrong?

Response to the ASA s statement on p-values: context, process, and purpose

Appearance properties

On Narrow Norms and Vague Heuristics: A Reply to Kahneman and Tversky (1996)

The Frequency Hypothesis and Evolutionary Arguments

Vagueness, Context Dependence and Interest Relativity

Who Is Rational? Studies of Individual Differences in Reasoning

Are Humans Rational? SymSys 100 April 14, 2011

Answer the questions on the handout labeled: Four Famous Reasoning Problems. Try not to remember what you may have read about these problems!

Comments on David Rosenthal s Consciousness, Content, and Metacognitive Judgments

624 N. Broadway, 3rd Floor, Johns Hopkins University, Baltimore, MD 21205, USA THE EMBRYO RESCUE CASE

Eliminative materialism

Chapter 02 Developing and Evaluating Theories of Behavior

Heuristics & Biases:

Was Bernoulli Wrong? On Intuitions about Sample Size

Empty Thoughts: An Explanatory Problem for Higher-Order Theories of Consciousness

THE CONJUNCTION EFFECT AND CLINICAL JUDGMENT

Skepticism about perceptual content

Testing boundary conditions for the conjunction fallacy: Effects of response mode, conceptual focus, and problem type

This article appeared in a journal published by Elsevier. The attached copy is furnished to the author for internal non-commercial research and

First Problem Set: Answers, Discussion and Background

A conversation with Professor David Chalmers, May 20, 2016 Participants

COGNITIVE ILLUSIONS RECONSIDERED

Perception Search Evaluation Choice

A Difference that Makes a Difference: Welfare and the Equality of Consideration

Recognizing Ambiguity

D F 3 7. beer coke Cognition and Perception. The Wason Selection Task. If P, then Q. If P, then Q

Prediction. Todd Davies Symsys 130 April 22, 2013

On Our Experience of Ceasing to Exist

Confirmation 4 Reasoning by Analogy; Nicod s Condition

The Role of Causality in Judgment Under Uncertainty. Tevye R. Krynski & Joshua B. Tenenbaum

Utility Maximization and Bounds on Human Information Processing

Author's personal copy

Autonomy as a Positive Value Some Conceptual Prerequisites Niklas Juth Dept. of Philosophy, Göteborg University

The Good, the Bad and the Blameworthy: Understanding the Role of Evaluative Reasoning in Folk Psychology. Princeton University

Beyond Subjective and Objective in Statistics

Examples of Feedback Comments: How to use them to improve your report writing. Example 1: Compare and contrast

What role should heroes, saints and sages play within moral theory? While it would be unfair to

Research Ethics and Philosophies

two ways in which things can be colloquially called the same : being that very thing, and not another being like and undistinguishable

Ought Implies Can, Framing Effects, and Empirical Refutations

2 theory [18], that is, between what we should do (according to probability theory) and what we do (according to psychological experiments). Therefore

The Common Priors Assumption: A comment on Bargaining and the Nature of War

Evidence Based On What?

The Role of Causal Models in Statistical Reasoning

Explaining an Explanatory Gap Gilbert Harman Princeton University

Running head: INDIVIDUAL DIFFERENCES 1. Why to treat subjects as fixed effects. James S. Adelman. University of Warwick.

Durkheim. Durkheim s fundamental task in Rules of the Sociological Method is to lay out

FAQ: Heuristics, Biases, and Alternatives

The Role of Causal Models in Reasoning Under Uncertainty

Asch Model Answers. Aims and Context

6. A theory that has been substantially verified is sometimes called a a. law. b. model.

COHERENCE: THE PRICE IS RIGHT

2. Two paradigm cases of self-deception: the cuckold (wishful thinking) and the quarterback (willful self-deception).

What is analytical sociology? And is it the future of sociology?

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

24.500/Phil253 topics in philosophy of mind/perceptual experience

Psy 803: Higher Order Cognitive Processes Fall 2012 Lecture Tu 1:50-4:40 PM, Room: G346 Giltner

On the Conjunction Fallacy in Probability Judgment: New Experimental Evidence

Glossary of Research Terms Compiled by Dr Emma Rowden and David Litting (UTS Library)

Experimental Economics Lecture 3: Bayesian updating and cognitive heuristics

A Direct Object of Perception

UNCORRECTED PROOF. Daniel Steel / Across the Boundaries 01-DanielSteel-chap01 Page Proof page :48pm ACROSS THE BOUNDARIES

John Broome, Weighing Lives Oxford: Oxford University Press, ix + 278pp.

Comparative Ignorance and the Ellsberg Paradox

Roskilde University. Publication date: Document Version Early version, also known as pre-print

ARE EX-ANTE ENHANCEMENTS ALWAYS PERMISSIBLE?

Chapter 11 Decision Making. Syllogism. The Logic

Cognitive domain: Comprehension Answer location: Elements of Empiricism Question type: MC

Psychological. Influences on Personal Probability. Chapter 17. Copyright 2005 Brooks/Cole, a division of Thomson Learning, Inc.

8/23/2017. ECON4260 Behavioral Economics. 1 st lecture Introduction, Markets and Uncertainty. Practical matters. Three main topics

Against Securitism, the New Breed of Actualism in Consequentialist Thought

Bayesian and Frequentist Approaches

Temporalization In Causal Modeling. Jonathan Livengood & Karen Zwier TaCitS 06/07/2017

Critical Thinking Rubric. 1. The student will demonstrate the ability to interpret information. Apprentice Level 5 6. graphics, questions, etc.

the examples she used with her arguments were good ones because they lead the reader to the answer concerning the thesis statement.

Confirmation Bias. this entry appeared in pp of in M. Kattan (Ed.), The Encyclopedia of Medical Decision Making.

Lecture III. Is s/he an expert in the particular issue? Does s/he have an interest in the issue?

LAW RESEARCH METHODOLOGY HYPOTHESIS

The End of the Armchair for Conceptual Analysis? Brian Talbot (draft only)

Is it possible to give a philosophical definition of sexual desire?

Jackson s Empirical Assumptions 1. Stephen Stich Rutgers University. Jonathan Weinberg Indiana University

4/26/2017. Things to Consider. Making Decisions and Reasoning. How Did I Choose to Get Out of Bed...and Other Hard Choices

COGNITIVE BIAS IN PROFESSIONAL JUDGMENT

The psychology of Bayesian reasoning

A response to: NIST experts urge caution in use of courtroom evidence presentation method

Probabilistic judgment

January 2, Overview

Why psychiatry needs philosophy (and vice versa) Tim Thornton, Professor of Philosophy and Mental Health INNOVATIVE THINKING FOR THE REAL WORLD

Quasi-experimental analysis Notes for "Structural modelling".

Active and Passive Euthanasia

CPS331 Lecture: Coping with Uncertainty; Discussion of Dreyfus Reading

Is it possible to gain new knowledge by deduction?

PSY The Psychology Major: Academic and Professional Issues. Module 8: Critical Thinking. Study Guide Notes

We Can Test the Experience Machine. Response to Basil SMITH Can We Test the Experience Machine? Ethical Perspectives 18 (2011):

CT Rubric V.2 ACCEPTABLE (3)

Transcription:

P.B.M. Vranas / Cognition 81 (2001) 105±111 105 COGNITION Cognition 81 (2001) 105±111 www.elsevier.com/locate/cognit Discussion Single-case probabilities and content-neutral norms: a reply to Gigerenzer Peter B.M. Vranas* Department of Philosophy, The University of Michigan, 2215 Angell Hall, Ann Arbor, MI 48109, USA Abstract Gigerenzer (2001) argues that (a) statements about single-case probabilities are problematic because they specify no reference class, and that (b) norms should not be applied to speci c situations in a `content-blind' way. In reply I argue that (a) statements about singlecase probabilities make sense and are unambiguous despite specifying no reference class, and that (b) although Gigerenzer is right that the application of norms to speci c situations should take into account the content of the situations and thus should not be content-blind, Gigerenzer has not undermined the appropriateness of probabilistic and other norms which purport to have force in every situation and are in this sense content-neutral. q 2001 Elsevier Science B.V. All rights reserved. Keywords: Heuristics and biases; Judgment under uncertainty; Norms of reasoning; Frequentism; Concepts of probability; Reference classes 1. Single-case probabilities and reference classes In response to my statement that ªI see no obvious way in which a subjectivist concept of probability is problematicº (Vranas, 2000, p. 182), Gigerenzer tells a story which supposedly ªillustrates one problem with statements about the probability of single events: a reference class is not speci edº (Gigerenzer, 2001, p. 94, this issue). The story concerns a psychiatrist who prescribes Prozac to his depressive patients. Those of his patients to whom he tells (1) become on average more anxious than those to whom he tells (2), because many of the former interpret (1) as (3) rather than (2): * Fax: 11-734-763-8071. E-mail address: vranas@umich.edu (P.B.M. Vranas). 0010-0277/01/$ - see front matter q 2001 Elsevier Science B.V. All rights reserved. PII: S0010-0277(00)00134-7

106 P.B.M. Vranas / Cognition 81 (2001) 105±111 (1) You have a 30±50% probability of developing a sexual problem. (2) Out of every ten patients to whom I prescribe Prozac, three to ve experience a sexual problem. (3) You will experience a problem in 30±50% of your sexual encounters. Now I grant that this story illustrates a practical problem, namely one of miscommunication, but how does it illustrate a theoretical (conceptual) problem with (statements about) single-case probabilities? Maybe Gigerenzer's point is that (1) is ambiguous or does not even make sense until a reference class is speci ed. But this is so only if the `probability' in (1) is frequentist; I will argue that if the probability is objectivist or subjectivist, then we have statements about single-case probabilities which make sense and are unambiguous despite specifying no reference class. Suppose rst that the probability in (1) is objectivist, namely a `chance' or `propensity' (e.g. Giere, 1973; Mackie, 1973, pp. 179±187; Popper, 1959). Then (1) says something like (4): (4) You have a mechanism which causes a sexual problem when triggered and which has a 30±50% chance of being triggered by Prozac. To see why (4) requires no speci cation of a reference class, compare (4) with (5): (5) Three to ve out of every ten patients have a mechanism which causes a sexual problem when triggered and which is always triggered by Prozac; the remaining patients have no such mechanism. If (5) is true then (4) is false, because then your chance of developing a sexual problem is 0 or 1, not 30±50%. Although (5) is about a class of patients, (4) is not: (4) is about a particular patient and is unambiguous (provided that the nature of the `sexual problem' is clari ed) despite specifying no reference class. It may be true that normally one would not assert (4) without having evidence like (2), which does specify a reference class. 1 But this is not necessary: I may believe that each patient has a different chance of developing a sexual problem, and in asserting (4) I may be just guessing that in your case the chance is 30±50%. So the point remains that, even if no reference class is speci ed, (4) makes sense and is unambiguous ± or, more cautiously (since conceptual worries about chances or propensities do exist: HaÂjek, in press; Humphreys, 1985), Gigerenzer has given us no good reason to think otherwise. Similar remarks apply if the probability in (1) is subjectivist, namely a degree of con dence (e.g. Kyburg & Smokler, 1980). Then (1) says something like (6): (6) I am 30±50% con dent that you will develop a sexual problem. This is again a statement about a particular patient which makes sense and is unambiguous despite specifying no reference class (even if normally one would not assert (6) without having evidence like (2), which does specify a reference class). I conclude that the Prozac story illustrates no theoretical problem with (statements about) single-case probabilities ± unless it is assumed that only frequentist probabilities are legitimate, an assumption which Gigerenzer explicitly disavows. 1 Evidence like (2) does not by itself justify belief in (4) rather than (5): further evidence is needed. So I am not saying that the psychiatrist should tell his patients (4) rather than (2).

P.B.M. Vranas / Cognition 81 (2001) 105±111 107 More generally, like many philosophers (cf. Carnap, 1945; Lewis, 1980/1986), I do not see the three main kinds of probability concepts ± objectivist, subjectivist, and frequentist ± as competing. They just are different kinds of concepts: chances or propensities (if such things exist) are not relative frequencies, nor are they degrees of con dence. So from the fact that frequentist probabilities cannot be de ned without specifying a reference class it does not follow that objectivist or subjectivist singlecase probabilities (which require no such speci cation) are problematic. 2. On the appropriateness of content-neutral norms 2.1. Content-neutrality versus content-blindness In response to my statement that ªit is incumbent on him to explain what is wrong with ¼ content-neutral justi cations of probabilistic [and other] normsº (Vranas, 2000, p. 186), Gigerenzer adduces three major considerations ± polysemy, sampling, and reference classes ± which supposedly demonstrate that ªnorms need to be constructed for a speci c situation, not imposed upon in a content-blind wayº (Gigerenzer, 2001, p. 93, this issue). I address these three considerations in the next three subsections, but rst a clari cation is needed. Contrary to what Gigerenzer says, I do not think I am using the term `content-neutral' as he uses the term `content-blind'. Let us say that a norm is content-neutral when it purports to have normative force in every context. The moral norm against murdering, for example, understood as the claim that one should never murder, is content-neutral. I take Gigerenzer to agree that probabilistic norms are content-neutral in this sense, although it is of course a further question whether these content-neutral norms are appropriate (correct), whether they do have normative force in every context. Now let us say that a norm is applied in a content-blind way to a particular context when it is applied without taking into account the speci c features of the context. If one claims, for example, that I violated the norm against murdering because I killed someone, and one does not take into account whether the killing was accidental, then one applies the norm to my situation in a content-blind way. I agree of course with Gigerenzer's point that this is to be avoided, but this point addresses the empirical question of whether I did violate the norm; more relevant to the present, normative discussion is the question of whether I should not violate the norm (whether the norm is appropriate), and answering the empirical question does not amount to answering the normative one. I take then much of the disagreement between Gigerenzer and myself to be only apparent, because we are addressing different questions: some of Gigerenzer's examples concern content-blind applications of content-neutral norms to particular contexts, but I will argue that his examples fail to undermine the appropriateness of content-neutral norms. 2.2. Polysemy and the conjunction rule The conjunction rule is the content-neutral epistemic norm according to which one's degree of con dence in the conjunction of two statements ought not to exceed

108 P.B.M. Vranas / Cognition 81 (2001) 105±111 one's degree of con dence in (either) one of the conjuncts. Tversky and Kahneman (1983) found that, when people were given a description suggesting that Linda is a feminist but not a bank teller and were asked to rank certain statements according to their probability, most people ranked (a) `Linda is a bank teller and is active in the feminist movement' as more probable than (b) `Linda is a bank teller'. Gigerenzer argues that to conclude from these results that most participants violated the conjunction rule would be to apply the rule in a content-blind way: until we nd out how the participants understood the polysemous term `probability' we do not know whether their judgments of probability expressed (i.e. corresponded to) their degrees of con dence. I agree, but then so did Tversky and Kahneman (1983), who explicitly investigated the possibility that ªthe conjunction fallacy ¼ may be viewed as a misunderstanding regarding the meaning of the word probabilityº (p. 303) but concluded that ªthe observed violations of the conjunction rule ¼ are genuine fallacies, not just misunderstandingsº (p. 304). Gigerenzer might reply by adducing evidence to the effect that most participants understood the term `probability' nonmathematically (Hertwig & Gigerenzer, 1999). But regardless of who is ultimately right on the empirical issue of how most participants understood the term `probability', the fact remains that Tversky and Kahneman did address this issue, so Gigerenzer is not entitled to accuse them of applying the conjunction rule in a content-blind way. Moreover, Gigerenzer has not addressed the normative issue of whether the conjunction rule has normative force in the context of Tversky and Kahneman's experiments. Even if most participants understood `probability' nonmathematically and did not express their relative degrees of con dence in statements (a) and (b) when they ranked (a) as more `probable' than (b), arguably their (unexpressed) degrees of con dence in these two statements (as opposed to their `probability' rankings of the two statements) still ought to satisfy the conjunction rule. So Gigerenzer has not undermined the appropriateness of the conjunction rule. 2 2.3. Sampling and calibration Suppose I am asked a series of questions and I indicate, after answering each question, my degree of con dence in the correctness of my answer. If only, for example, 70% of the answers for each of which I indicate a 90% degree of con dence are correct, then these answers exhibit overcon dence: they violate the norm of calibration, according to which the two percentages ought to be equal. Gigerenzer argues that overcon dence disappears in some cases in which people are asked randomly sampled questions but appears with questions which are selectively 2 Even if some participants understood `probability' non-mathematically and did not violate the conjunction rule when they ranked statement (a) as more `probable' than (b), arguably they still committed a reasoning fallacy (distinct from the fallacy of violating the conjunction rule) if they were not justi ed in understanding `probability' non-mathematically. Hertwig and Gigerenzer (1999) argue that they were justi ed, ªbecause a mathematical interpretation would render the experimenter's description of Linda ¼ irrelevant to the requested judgmentº (p. 278). Not so, however: the description of Linda was relevant to some of the statements (e.g. `Linda is active in the feminist movement') whose relative probabilities the participants were asked to evaluate.

sampled to look easier than they are. 3 For example, the question of whether New York or Rome is further south looks easier than it is because it has an apparently obvious but incorrect answer: `Rome, since it is much warmer'. Gigerenzer claims that in such cases of selective sampling the norm of calibration has no force. Why not, however? To modify an example that I borrowed from Kahneman and Tversky (1996, p. 588) (Vranas, 2000, p. 185): would Gigerenzer be indifferent between getting a diagnosis of almost certain recovery from a calibrated and from an overcon dent surgeon, even when the latter is overcon dent only with respect to cases in which recovery looks certain but is in fact unlikely? 4 Gigerenzer has provided at most an explanation, not a justi cation, for overcon dence in cases of selective sampling, so Gigerenzer has not shown that the norm of calibration is inappropriate. 2.4. Reference classes P.B.M. Vranas / Cognition 81 (2001) 105±111 109 Gigerenzer considers a study (Slovic, Monahan, & MacGregor, 2000) in which one group of members of the American Academy of Psychiatry and Law were asked something like (7) and another group were asked something like (8): (7) What is the probability that Mr Jones (an offender) will commit another violent act if given parole? (8) How many among 100 people like Mr Jones will commit another violent act if given parole? Gigerenzer notes that ªthe probability judgments were systematically higher than the frequency judgmentsº but argues that this discrepancy ªneed not be equated with a reasoning fallacyº because (similarly to the Prozac story) some people may have interpreted (7) as (9) rather than (8): (9) If Mr Jones is given parole 100 times, how many times will he commit another violent act? In reply I grant that the above discrepancy does not correspond to a reasoning fallacy, but who says that it does? What exactly is the content-neutral norm whose content-blind application or whose inappropriateness this example is supposed to illustrate? It cannot be a norm to the effect that one's degree of con dence in a statement ought to be equal to one's estimate of `the' corresponding relative frequency: there is no such norm precisely because there is no unique corresponding reference class and thus in general no unique corresponding relative 3 In response to my statement that ªexperimenters are typically careful to ¼ stipulate random samplingº (Vranas, 2000, p. 187), Gigerenzer argues that until recently there was ªno single [calibration] study that used random samplingº (Gigerenzer, 2001, p. 98, this issue). My statement, however, occurred in the context of my discussion not of calibration, but rather of experiments like the Engineer/Lawyer ones, in which experimenters are indeed typically careful to stipulate (though not to use) random sampling: ªin the lawyer±engineer problem, subjects are typically told that the descriptions provided were selected at randomº (Koehler, 1996, p. 8). 4 Responding to an earlier version of this paper, Gigerenzer (pers. commun.) noted in effect that a surgeon who is calibrated with respect to a set of patients will in general be overcon dent with respect to a subset and undercon dent with respect to another subset. True, but this is so regardless of whether patients are sampled randomly or selectively, and need not undermine the norm that the surgeon ought to be (approximately) calibrated with respect to certain large sets of patients.

110 P.B.M. Vranas / Cognition 81 (2001) 105±111 frequency. What about a norm to the effect that one's degree of con dence in a statement ought to be equal to one's estimate of the corresponding relative frequency which one takes to be relevant? Assuming that such a norm is wellde ned, Gigerenzer has given us no reason to believe that it has no normative force in the context of the above study: arguably a participant who understands (7) as being about a degree of con dence and takes the relevant corresponding frequency to be the one in (9) ought to give the same answer to (7) and (9) ± even if not to (7) and (8). I conclude that the above study, like Gigerenzer's other examples, provides no instance of a content-neutral norm which is not appropriate. 2.5. Conclusion In the last three subsections I carried out the negative task of arguing that Gigerenzer has not established the existence of content-neutral norms which fail to be appropriate. In my earlier piece (Vranas, 2000, pp. 185±186) I carried out the positive task of providing three arguments for the appropriateness of (contentneutral) probabilistic norms. Given that Gigerenzer in his reply did not even address (let alone refute) those three arguments, I conclude that the balance of reasons favors the appropriateness of probabilistic norms. On the other hand, I agree with Gigerenzer that the application of a content-neutral appropriate norm to a particular problem can be a tricky matter and may require a thorough examination of the content of the problem. Acknowledgements I wish to thank Eugene Burnstein, Stephen Darwall, John Doris, Allan Gibbard, Gerd Gigerenzer, Vittorio Girotto, James Joyce, and Richard Nisbett for helpful comments. References Carnap, R. (1945). The two concepts of probability. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 5, 513± 532. Giere, R. N. (1973). Objective single-case probabilities and the foundations of statistics. In P. Suppes, L. Henkin, A. Joja, & G. C. Moisil (Eds.), Logic, methodology and philosophy of science (Vol. IV, pp. 467±483). Amsterdam: North Holland. Gigerenzer, G. (2001). Content-blind norms, no norms, or good norms? A reply to Vranas. Cognition, 81, 93±103. HaÂjek, A. (in press). Conditional probability is the guide to life. In H. E. Kyburg Jr., & M. Thalos (Eds.), Probability as a guide to life. Open Court. Hertwig, R., & Gigerenzer, G. (1999). The `conjunction fallacy' revisited: how intelligent inferences look like reasoning errors. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 12, 275±305. Humphreys, P. (1985). Why propensities cannot be probabilities. Philosophical Review, 94, 557±570. Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1996). On the reality of cognitive illusions. Psychological Review, 103, 582±591. Koehler, J. J. (1996). The base rate fallacy reconsidered: descriptive, normative, and methodological challenges. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 19, 1±17.

P.B.M. Vranas / Cognition 81 (2001) 105±111 111 Kyburg Jr., H. E., & Smokler, H. E. (Eds.) (1980). Studies in subjective probability (2nd ed.). Huntington, NY: Krieger. Lewis, D. K. (1986). A subjectivist's guide to objective chance. In D. K. Lewis, Philosophical papers (Vol. 2, pp. 83±132). New York: Oxford University Press. (Original work published 1980) Mackie, J. L. (1973). Truth, probability and paradox: studies in philosophical logic. Oxford: Clarendon. Popper, K. R. (1959). The propensity interpretation of probability. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 10, 25±42. Slovic, P., Monahan, J., & MacGregor, D. G. (2000). Violence risk assessment and risk communication: the effects of using actual cases, providing instruction, and employing probability versus frequency formats. Law and Human Behavior, 24, 271±296. Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1983). Extensional versus intuitive reasoning: the conjunction fallacy in probability judgment. Psychological Review, 90, 293±315. Vranas, P. B. M. (2000). Gigerenzer's normative critique of Kahneman and Tversky. Cognition, 76, 179± 193.