Germ-line gene editing: What are the social and moral risks?

Similar documents
Genome Editing and Human Reproduction October 26, 2016

STEM CELL RESEARCH: MEDICAL PROGRESS WITH RESPONSIBILITY

Parents may one day be morally obligated to edit their baby s genes

Human Gene Editing for Reproduction:

First Part: Anthropological, Theological, and Ethical Aspects of Human Life and Procreation

A Kantian Ethical Analysis of Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis

B1 Revision You and Your Genes. You and Your Genes (B1) Revision for Exam

Reprogenetics and Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis (PGD)

Should we allow 'genetic vaccination' with Crispr Opinion Chemistry World

Ethical Standards for Catholic Health and Aged Care Services in Australia

Regulating mitochondrial donation: seeking expert views. Background document

Your consent to disclosing identifying information

Genetic condition decisionmaking and slippery slopes DAVE ARCHARD PHILOSOPHY, QUB

Who we should be as Catholic health care Identity In light of this, what we do as Catholic health care Integrity

Would genome editing harm or benefit the person born as a result? Prof. Rob Sparrow Philosophy, Monash University.

[Act on Artificial Fertilisation and use of Human Gametes and Embryos for Stem-Cell Research] 1) No. 55/1996 1) Act No. 27/2008, Article 9

Sperm Donation - Information for Donors

WHAT YOU NEED TO KNOW ABOUT DONATING SPERM, EGGS OR EMBRYOS

Embryo Experimentation

THE PUBLIC AND GENETIC EDITING, TESTING, AND THERAPY

Information For Egg Recipients

Blackpool CCG. Policies for the Commissioning of Healthcare. Assisted Conception

The Ethical Implications of Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis (PGD)

15/12/2011. You and your genes (OCR)

Reproductive Technology, Genetic Testing, and Gene Therapy

Haringey CCG Fertility Policy April 2014

D D M M Y Y D D M M Y Y. For clinic use only (optional) MD PNT only (gender-neutral): version 1; 3 April 2017

Women s consent to the use and storage of eggs or embryos for surrogacy

HALTON CLINICAL COMMISSIONING GROUP NHS FUNDED TREATMENT FOR SUBFERTILITY. CONTENTS Page

INTRODUCTION BREAST CANCER CARE

Q1 Do you think creating embryos by cell nuclear replacement (CNR) into animal eggs will be beneficial to research?

ASSISTED CONCEPTION NHS FUNDED TREATMENT FOR SUBFERTILITY ELIGIBILITY CRITERIA & POLICY GUIDANCE

Human Molecular Genetics Prof. S. Ganesh Department of Biological Sciences and Bioengineering Indian Institute of Technology, Kanpur

Your consent to the use of your sperm in artificial insemination

The British Medical Association Report on. Although this report was prepared for, and concerns. problem, By A. M. McCUTCHEON, M.B., Ch.B., F.R.F.P.S.

Deriving Sperm and Eggs from Human Skin Cells: Facilitating Community Discussion

A Stepwise Approach to Embryo Selection and Implantation Success

Fill in this form if you are donating eggs and/or embryos created with your eggs for use in another person s mitochondrial donation

St Helens CCG NHS Funded Treatment for Subfertility Policy 2015/16

NHS FUNDED TREATMENT FOR SUBFERTILITY. ELIGIBILITY CRITERIA POLICY GUIDANCE/OPTIONS FOR CCGs

The Regulation of Gene Editing in the UK

Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis (PGD) in Western Australia

Guide to Good Practice in fertility cases

Access to IVF. Help us decide Discussion paper. South Central Specialised Commissioning Group C - 1

Jesus said to him, I am the way and the truth and the life John 14:6

Men s consent to the use and storage of sperm or embryos for surrogacy

When Genomes Get Cheap

Policy updated: November 2018 (approved by Haringey and Islington s Executive Management Team on 5 December 2018)

Fertility treatment in trends and figures

Submission to the Commission on Assisted Human Reproduction December 2001

SOCIAL, ETHICS, RELIGION AND SCIENCE IN REPRODUCTIVE TECHNOLOGIES. Marie-Noel Bruné

Weight Management Clinic

COMMISSIONING POLICY FOR IN VITRO FERTILISATION (IVF)/ INTRACYTOPLASMIC SPERM INJECTION (ICSI) WITHIN TERTIARY INFERTILITY SERVICES V2.

Not Unsafe Does Not Equal Safe An Evaluation of the HFEA s report on MST and PNT

Your consent to donating your eggs

Approved January Waltham Forest CCG Fertility policy

INTRACYTOPLASMIC SPERM INJECTION

SEX-SELECTION, GENOME SELECTION, AND DESIGNER BABIES

Fertility treatment in trends and figures

Women s consent to treatment and storage form (IVF and ICSI)

Bonnie Steinbock University at Albany (emerita) Distinguished Visiting Professor, CUHK Centre for Bioethics 12th December, 2015

ETHICAL ISSUES IN REPRODUCTIVE MEDICINE

MST and PNT allow eggs or embryos to be created for you containing your and your partner s nuclear genetic material D D M M Y Y D D M M Y Y

The Genetics and Public Policy Center is an independent and objective source of information

Talking about Mental Health A Narrative Approach Marla Lipscomb, MSW, LCSW Saint Alphonsus CARE Maternal Child Health Program Boise, Idaho

A meeting in the PGD Lab

Couples Information Leaflet

Fertility Policy. December Introduction

Assisted Reproductive Technologies

Integrating and strengthening the European research area *

Recommended Interim Policy Statement 150: Assisted Conception Services

Genetic screening. Martin Delatycki

THE USE OF MEDICAL TECHNOLOGY

commandment. The second is like it: Love your neighbor as yourself. All the Law and the Prophets hang on these two commandments.

WOLFSON FERTILITY CENTRE. Wolfson Fertility Centre

Note: This updated policy supersedes all previous fertility policies and reflects changes agreed by BHR CCGs governing bodies in June 2017.

Information leaflet for Patients and Families. Cystic Fibrosis

Public consultation: Seeking your views on IVF

Opinion no. 67 of 12 September 2016 on the reception of eggs harvested from the partner within lesbian couples with a view to in vitro fertilisation

Introduction 4. Important information about consent to legal parenthood 7. Women s consent to treatment and storage form (IVF and ICSI) (WT form) 9

Genetics Review and Reproductive Options in Kennedy Disease

Unit B2, B2.7. Cell division and inheritance. Stage 1. Ovary. Cell Q. Cell P. Cell R. Cell S. 7 Embryo A B C

The Zika Virus. What Is Our Catholic Response?

How to Select an Egg Donor

What Are Genes And Chromosomes?

Friday, 25 August 2017 HFEA, 10 Spring Gardens, London SW1A 2BU

Commissioning Policy For In Vitro Fertilisation (IVF) / Intracytoplasmic Sperm Injection (ICSI) within Tertiary Infertility Services

GENA2. Source Booklet. General Studies (Specification A) General Certificate of Education Advanced Subsidiary Examination June 2011

Your consent to your sperm and embryos being used in treatment and/or stored (IVF and ICSI)

NEW YORK STATE MODEL FOR REGULATORY OVERSIGHT OF ART AND GENETIC TESTING.

17. Storage of gametes and embryos

University of Huddersfield Repository

Biology of fertility control. Higher Human Biology

WHO ARE THE DONORS? - An HFEA Analysis of donor registrations and use of donor gametes over the last 10 years

Semi-Meiotic hypothesis: Producing new species

Egg sharing (Donor) Information for Patients and Partners

European IVF Monitoring (EIM) Year: 2013

FACT SHEET. Failure of Ovulation Blocked or Damaged Fallopian TubesHostile Cervical Mucus Endometriosis Fibroids

What is the relationship between genes and chromosomes? Is twinning genetic or can a person choose to have twins?

West Hampshire Clinical Commissioning Group Board

Transcription:

This is an accepted manuscript of the article published in Medicina e Morale: Rivista internazionale di Bioetica, 65.2 (2016), 123-130 http://dx.doi.org/10.4081/mem.2016.435 Germ-line gene editing: What are the social and moral risks? From: Dr Agneta Sutton, Visiting Lecturer, Department of Pastoral Theology, Heythrop College, University of London, Kensington Square, London W8 5HN, UK a.sutton@heythrop.ac.uk agneta.sutton@gmail.com Key words: gene editing, embryo, germ-line, negative eugenics, positive eugenics. ABSTRACT Should we welcome all developments in gene editing? Somatic cell gene editing would be on a par with conventional therapies aimed at treating particular conditions or alleviating symptoms. It would solely affect the individual patient treated. It could thus serve as a welcome new kind of treatment for cancers and blood diseases such as ß-thalassaemia. Germ-line gene editing, on the other hand, would have hereditary effects. This raises special concerns about medical mishaps. Medical risks are, however, not the only kinds of risks in the case of germ-line gene editing. Discussed here are not the medical risks, but the social and moral risks of germ-line-gene editing. Introduction Scientists at the Francis Crick Institute in London have been granted permission to edit the genomes of human embryos for research purposes. The permission was given on 1 February 2016 by the UK s fertility treatment and embryo research regulator, the Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority (HFEA). The permission makes the UK the first country in the world to officially sanction gene editing of human embryos. 1 While being the first country in the world to give a legal green light to the creation of gene-edited embryos, UK scientists are, however, not the first scientists in the world to embark on the creation of gene-edited human embryos. Chinese scientists beat them in this race. In a paper published online in Protein &Cell, on 18 April 2015, Chinese scientists explained how, with the use of the recently developed gene editing technique called CRISPR-Cas9, they had managed to modify the gene responsible for ß-thalassaemia, a potentially lethal blood disorder. 2 Not surprisingly, the paper sparked an intense debate among scientists and ethicists about the ethics and social risks of germ- 1 The HFEA announced the news about the licence on its website on 01.02.2016 (accessed on 09.02.2016 at: http://guide.hfea.gov.uk/guide/showpdf.aspx?id=5966). The Francis Crick Institute published the news on its website on 02.02.2016 (accessed on 09.02.2016 at: https://www.crick.ac.uk/news/science-news/2016/02/01/hfea-decision/). See also, Ewen Callaway, UK scientists gain licence to edit genes in human embryos, Nature News, 01.02.2016 (accessed on 08/02/2016 at: http://www.nature.com/news/uk-scientists-gain-licence-to-edit-genes-inhuman-embryos-1.19270?wt.mc_id=sfb_nnews_1508_rhbox). 2 Puping Liang, et.al., CRISPR/Cas9-mediated gene editing in human tripronuclear zygotes, Protein and Cell, 2015, 6 (5), pp. 363-372.

line gene editing, that is, the ethics and social risks of genetic modification of human eggs, sperm and embryos. Using abnormal embryos obtained from local fertility clinics, the Chinese scientists found that out of 86 gene edited one-cell embryos only 28 were successfully spliced, and that only a fraction of these 28 contained the intended genetic material. As the Chinese team pointed out, this shows that the CRISPR-cas9 technique is far from being fine-tuned enough for clinical use in humans. The medical risks of physical mishaps are too great. This is especially because in the case of germ-line gene editing, if the genetic modification went wrong, the adverse effects would be hereditary. That said, besides the medical risks of germ-line gene editing there are also significant social and moral risks. In this paper I am concentrating on the social and moral risks of germ-line gene editing. In the last century we witnessed draconian eugenic policies. This was not only in Nazi Germany. In North America and Scandinavia, people with a various conditions, including for example epilepsy, were forced to be sterilized. That is, policies of sterilizing people with certain conditions were imposed by the state. Today such practices would be considered shameful. This does not mean that eugenics is a thing of the past. Presently, many or most healthcare systems promote a practice of soft eugenics. I am referring to pre-implantation (PGD) and prenatal diagnosis with a view to avoiding births of children with certain adverse conditions. In many countries diagnostic prenatal tests are recommended if blood tests or ultrasound screening point to a foetal problem, or if the pregnant mother is in her late thirties or older and therefore at increased risk of having a child with a chromosomal abnormality, such as Down syndrome. Likewise, PGD may be recommended in connection with IVF when a woman or her male partner is affected by a particular hereditary condition. These practices constitute a soft form of negative eugenics. I say soft eugenics, because nobody is being coerced to have such tests. Nor is anyone forced to undergo an abortion on grounds of foetal abnormality. The tests are only performed on a voluntary basis. If germ-line gene editing were to be practised, it too would undoubtedly be practised on a voluntary basis. So practised, it would constitute a form of soft positive eugenics. Some governments, health authorities and many pregnant women or couples might welcome the development of germ-line gene editing for the purpose of practising a policy of soft positive eugenics. But there are good reasons for voicing warnings about this development. The Francis Crick Institute research The aim of the embryo gene editing, to which the HFEA has granted a licence, is not that of curing human embryos by editing faulty genes. It is solely that of undertaking research. Dr Kathy Niakan, who approached the HFEA for an embryo gene editing licence in September 2015, and who will be undertaking the research at the Francis Crick Institute, has told the media that she only wants to undertake basic research studying embryological development. Unlike the Chinese scientists who, to justify their destruction of human embryos, said they were working with non-viable embryos, Dr Niakan who specialises in embryo development will be working with healthy embryos, so-called left-over embryos. In other words, she will be working with embryos that have been donated by couples who have undergone IVF treatment. Interested in why so many embryos fail to develop, she hopes that her research will improve IVF success rates. She is particularly interested in the genes involved in early cell differentiation. That is, she is studying the formation of cells destined to develop into the embryo proper and of cells destined to develop into intra-uterine supportive tissue, such as the placenta, umbilical cord and amniotic sac. 3 3 The Francis Crick Institute published a statement about the research on its website of 02.02. 2016 (accessed on 07.02.2016 at: https://www.crick.ac.uk/news/science-news/2016/02/01/hfea-decision/).

Since the present aim of embryo gene editing at the Francis Crick Institute is that of undertaking basic research, it might seem innocuous enough. It might seem so, unless you recognize the human embryo as a nascent member of the human family and therefore worthy of respect and protection. That is to say, the destruction of human embryos used in research is one reason why the research at the Francis Crick Institute is morally controversial. However, this is not the only controversial aspect of this research. While the present aim of embryo gene editing at the Francis Crick institute is that of undertaking basic research, the longer-term aim of this research looks different, as witness the talks and discussions about the science and ethics of gene editing at the conference of the Progress Educational Trust, in London, on 9 December 2015. Among the speakers was Professor Robin Lovell- Badge of the Francis Crick Institute, who expressed the view that once the CRISPR- Cas9 technique of gene editing has been perfected, germ-line gene editing might prove a superior alternative to somatic gene editing for therapeutic purposes. He said germ-line gene editing might eventually prove to be a safer way of eliminating faulty genes than somatic gene editing. Explaining why, he said that gene editing of a one-cell embryo, sperm or egg would entail less risk of off-target effects compared with somatic gene editing in which millions of cells are genetically modified. 4 It should be added that he was not the only speaker at the conference who expressed hopes about the benefits of germ-line gene editing. International Summit on Gene Editing While CRISPR-Cas9 has raised many hopes and expectations within medical and scientific communities, it is clear that germ-line gene editing is controversial. This is the very reason why scientists from all over the world convened at the International Summit on Gene Editing, jointly organized by the US National Academies of Sciences, the UK Royal Society and the Chinese Academy of Science in Washington D.C., on 3-5 December 2015. 5 Not surprisingly, clinical use of gene editing of somatic cells was welcomed by the participants. Used for somatic gene editing, gene editing techniques, such as the much celebrated CRISPR-Cas 9 technique, would serve the purpose of curing the individual patient of a particular medical condition. Such treatment would, in principle, be no different from more conventional therapies inasmuch as the effects would only affect the individual person and thus would not be hereditary. In other words, somatic gene editing would constitute a new therapy complementing already existing treatments to heal a sick patient of a particular disease. The committee, therefore, supported further research into genetic modification of, for example, blood cells in search of cures for cancers and conditions such as sickle-cell anaemia. Several concerns were, however, voiced about embryo gene editing, though the experts at the meeting did not say categorically no to it. On the contrary, they were clearly expecting germ-line gene editing to be used for clinical purposes in the future. Thus they only said no to the use of this technology for the time being. And it was decided that the debate about genetic modification of See also, Ewen Callaway, UK scientists gain licence to edit genes in human embryos, Nature News, 01.02.2016 (accessed on 07.02.2016se at: http://www.nature.com/news/uk-scientists-gain-licence-to-edit-genes-inhuman-embryos-1.19270?wt.mc_id=sfb_nnews_1508_rhbox). 4 See, Dr Jess Buxton, Genome editing and CRISPR: the science of engineering the embryo, BioNews, 18.01.2016 (accessed on 21.032016 at: http://www.bionews.org.uk/page_606553.asp). 5 The National Academies of Sciences, Engineering and Medicine, International Summit on Gene Editing, On human gene editing international summit statement, 03.12. 2015 (accessed on 06.02.2016 at: http://www8.nationalacademies.org/onpinews/newsitem.aspx?recordid=12032015a).

eggs, sperm and embryos for clinical purposes should be reopened periodically in the wake of further developments of gene editing techniques. That said, the concerns raised by the assembled scientists pointed to a number of social and moral issues raised by embryo gene editing, be it for the sake of eliminating diseases or in other ways altering the human embryo. For a start, discussing the medical risks linked to the clinical use of germ-line gene editing, the participants noted that, not only could things go wrong in the sense of adversely affecting the physical health of individual subjects, but since the effects would be hereditary any gene-editing mishaps could be passed on to subsequent generations. And so it was agreed that until gene editing techniques have been perfected their use would be immoral. At present the medical risks are too great. More important, it was also recognized that the risks linked to germ-line gene editing are not only medical. It was noted that there are social and medical risks as well. This, as observed, was because germ-line gene editing might in the future be used not only for therapeutic purposes but also for the sake of enhancement, that is, for the creation of so-called designer babies. Pointing to the possibility of adverse social consequences of embryo gene editing for enhancement purposes, the participants at the summit quite rightly said that hereditary genetic changes aimed at enhancing certain characteristics or abilities could exacerbate social inequalities. In other words, it could lead to a genetically modified over-class and social discrimination. And pointing to the possibility of unethical practices, they noted that germ-line gene editing for the sake of enhancement could even come to be used coercively. In other words, they acknowledged the risk of germ-line gene editing being imposed as a mandatory procedure and thus used for eugenic purposes in the future. And so they expressed special concern about the possibility of purposefully altering human evolution using the technology. They also expressed the fear that public reactions to germ-line gene editing, such as objections to creation of designer babies and to scientists playing God, could have the unfortunate effect of adversely affecting public attitudes towards somatic gene editing. Reflections on social and moral risks As noted, embryo gene editing, such as that undertaken purely for research purposes at the Francis Crick Institute, could prove to be a preamble to the perfection of genetic modification of eggs, sperm and embryos for clinical purposes. If the aim of clinical use of germ-line gene modification was purely that of correcting faulty genes, then one could admittedly see a good in it inasmuch as it could spare future individuals from being affected by a particular hereditary disease. Indeed, used for purely therapeutic purposes, germ-line gene editing serving as a tool for eliminating hereditary diseases that have been afflicting previous generations of particular families might be cautiously welcomed. I say, cautiously, because it would have to be strictly regulated. Why? Because, once permitted and used germ-line gene editing would almost certainly set in motion a slippery slope. While it might be argued that strict regulation could be put in place to avoid this, once the technology has been perfected and is in use, it might with time come to be used not only in order to avoid a variety of severe genetic conditions. Instead the technique could also come to be used in order to avoid less severe diseases. And eventually it could come to be used to promote or enhance certain genetic traits considered social desirable. In other words, the major concerns about germ-line gene editing are not related to the medical or physical risks. These risks might be overcome. The major concerns relate to the risks of adverse ethical and social consequences. Scientific progress made in this century has promoted an emphasis on children having good genes. Applicable is the warning given in the Vatican document Donum

Vitae, of 1987, that while our new technologies might constitute progress in the service of man, they may also expose him to the temptation to go beyond the limits of reasonable domination over nature. 6 What is at issue is the risk that the use of germ-line gene editing could lead to an increasing failure on the part of society to give the child an unconditional welcome. There is the risk that use of germ-line gene editing, like use of pre-implantation genetic diagnosis (PGD) and prenatal diagnosis with a view to embryo selection and selective abortion, could come to be widely used - at least in societies with sufficient financial resources. If used for enhancement purposes there is the risk, as suggested at the International Summit on Gene Editing, of adverse social consequences such as the creation of a genetic over-class and a genetic under-class. There is even the risk that zealous use of germ-line gene editing for the purely therapeutic purpose of producing perfectly healthy children could come to serve as a complement to PGD and prenatal testing with a view to embryo selection and selective abortion to avoid births of children with particular conditions. Today most countries in the world allow soft negative eugenics policies by way of weeding out embryos and foetuses viewed as less than perfect. Tomorrow zealous use of therapeutic germ-line gene editing could serve as a positive eugenic complement to these negative eugenic policies. The result would then be a widespread policy of soft negative-cum-positive eugenics of selective breeding. As such, germ-line gene therapy, like prenatal testing with a view to selective abortion, would come to serve as a eugenic tool. This would represent a failure to respect and treat the child-to-be as our equal in human dignity. The child would be treated as a product of human selection and making; it would be treated as a commodity. Indeed, if germ-line gene editing were to become widely used, the list of genes to be modified would most probably become longer and longer. Of course, as I have said, one could see some good in the use of germ-line gene editing in order to eliminate clear cases of burdensome genetic disease such as cystic fibrosis and thalassaemia. However, there is the fear that the technology could come to be used to overcome any kind of genetic trait viewed as a weakness or as an imperfection. And if this happened, the technique would in the end come to be used in the same spirit as genetic enhancement. Indeed, there is no sharp line between healing and enhancement. To use germ-line gene therapy to produce perfectly able and healthy children would mean fabricating babies that live up to certain standards of health perfection decided by parents or society. Effectively, going down the path of seeking to rid children of ever more and more bad genes is not very different from, but in reality it is the much the same as, making sure they have good genes, genes linked to physical traits and mental abilities deemed desirable by parents and society. There is no Rubicon separating germline gene editing for therapeutic purposes from germ-line gene editing for the sake of enhancement. In other words, I am saying that while therapeutic use of germ-line gene editing might be welcomed, we should be aware of the risk of immoral use of germ-line gene editing in order to avoid any condition that might be viewed as a weakness. So used the technology would be used for eugenic purposes. Today it is sometimes said that it is irresponsible to bring a Down syndrome child into the world. It is argued that children with Down syndrome pose a burden on families and on society. And it is pointed out that given the possibility of prenatal testing the birth of the child with this condition could have been avoided. Tomorrow failure to avail of germ-line gene editing therapy might similarly be denounced as irresponsible. This would reflect inherently eugenic attitudes. And such attitudes are cause for concern inasmuch as they reflect discrimination and a failure to unconditionally accept and welcome the child. Fuelled by hubris, eugenics is blind to the giftedness of life. Accepting children as gifts means not treating embryos and foetuses as replaceable goods, goods to be discarded and replaced by better products if found imperfect. Accepting children as gifts means not 6 CDF, Donum Vitae, 1987, Introduction. 1.

making their welcome depend on whether they satisfy our demands for beauty, ability or perfect health. Eugenics, whatever form it takes, means usurping powers over the lives and deaths--of others, while failing to recognize our creaturely limitations and the fact that true perfection is not of this world. Not content unconditionally to accept the child-to-be as a gift, it would seem that we are increasingly on a quest for the perfect child. But the attempt to create the perfect child, or the perfectly healthy child, is indeed an attempt to play God. As such it is an attempt at unreasonable domination over nature. Speaking in Christian terms, it represents a failure to recognize the image of God in each and every human being irrespective of his or her skills, looks or health. In sum, there is the risk that the use of germ-line gene editing could lead to regrettable parental and social attitudes and aspirations. It could lead to a society which is intolerant of difference and one in which one generation assumes undue powers over the next. Voicing his fears in his famous work The Abolition of Man, C.S. Lewis wrote: if any age attains, by eugenics and scientific education, the power to make its descendants what it pleases, all men who live after it are the patients of that power. 7 What he feared was the power of some humans to make future humans helpless products of their design. 7 S. Lewis, The Abolition of Man, in C.S. Lewis, The Abolition of Man (New York; HarperSanFrancisco, 2001), p. 57.