Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Similar documents
THE USE OF MULTIVARIATE ANALYSIS IN DEVELOPMENT THEORY: A CRITIQUE OF THE APPROACH ADOPTED BY ADELMAN AND MORRIS A. C. RAYNER

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

False Positives & False Negatives in Cancer Epidemiology

Further Properties of the Priority Rule

CRITICAL APPRAISAL OF CLINICAL PRACTICE GUIDELINE (CPG)

Review of Animals and the Economy. Steven McMullen Palgrave, pp., ebook and hardcover. Bob Fischer Texas State University

Special guidelines for preparation and quality approval of reviews in the form of reference documents in the field of occupational diseases

Revisiting Barriers to Trade: Do Foregone Health Benefits Matter?

A Classification Tree for Predicting Consumer Preferences for Risk Reduction

The activity. Suggested Answers

Running Head: ADVERSE IMPACT. Significance Tests and Confidence Intervals for the Adverse Impact Ratio. Scott B. Morris

University of Huddersfield Repository

Social Values and Health Priority Setting Case Study

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

QUESTIONING THE MENTAL HEALTH EXPERT S CUSTODY REPORT

Contribution to the European Commission s Public Consultation on. 15 January 2015

To evaluate a single epidemiological article we need to know and discuss the methods used in the underlying study.

Comparative Ignorance and the Ellsberg Paradox

Control of Confounding in the Assessment of Medical Technology

SUPPLEMENTARY INFORMATION

Evaluation Models STUDIES OF DIAGNOSTIC EFFICIENCY

Access to newly licensed medicines. Scottish Medicines Consortium

GENERAL COMMENTS. The Task Force Process Should be Fully Open, Balanced and Transparent

INTRODUCTION TO BAYESIAN REASONING

Chapter 1 Introduction to I/O Psychology

The Preservation of Minority Female Customs

Verbal and behavioural indicators of trust: How well are they associated? Nigel Harvey University College London. Harvey Toulouse October 2009

An Experimental Investigation of Self-Serving Biases in an Auditing Trust Game: The Effect of Group Affiliation: Discussion

UNIT 5 - Association Causation, Effect Modification and Validity

Highlight News. Health risks from mobile phone radiation why the experts disagree

ISC- GRADE XI HUMANITIES ( ) PSYCHOLOGY. Chapter 2- Methods of Psychology

IDA and the concept of essential drugs

Research in Education. Tenth Edition

CASE STUDY 2: VOCATIONAL TRAINING FOR DISADVANTAGED YOUTH

ISPOR Task Force Report: ITC & NMA Study Questionnaire

PLANNING THE RESEARCH PROJECT

Journal of Political Economy, Vol. 93, No. 2 (Apr., 1985)

Business Impact Analysis

INTERNATIONAL STANDARD ON AUDITING (NEW ZEALAND) 530

Successful results of clinical trials

Psychology, 2010, 1: doi: /psych Published Online August 2010 (

Rutgers Environmental Health and Safety (REHS)

A Brief Introduction to Bayesian Statistics

How to Regulate E-Cigarettes? Are we asking the right questions?

observational studies Descriptive studies

What are your rights if DTA won't give you benefits, or reduces or stops your benefits?

Information can kill

11 questions to help you make sense of a case control study

Term Paper Step-by-Step

FAQ: Heuristics, Biases, and Alternatives

OUTPATIENT SERVICES PSYCHOLOGICAL SERVICES CONTRACT

Scientific Minimalism and the Division of Moral Labor in Regulating Dual-Use Research Steven Dykstra

Chapter 11. Experimental Design: One-Way Independent Samples Design

How Does Analysis of Competing Hypotheses (ACH) Improve Intelligence Analysis?

Multiple Comparisons and the Known or Potential Error Rate

The Atomic Safety and Licensing Board Panel

A Review of the Scientific Literature As It Pertains to Gulf War Illnesses: Pyridostigmine Bromide

2) Ethical and scientific standards that guide the use of quarantine or other movement restrictions during public health emergencies.

Recent advances in non-experimental comparison group designs

Folland et al Chapter 4

HOW TO APPLY FOR SOCIAL SECURITY DISABILITY BENEFITS IF YOU HAVE CHRONIC FATIGUE SYNDROME (CFS/CFIDS) MYALGIC ENCEPHALOPATHY (ME) and FIBROMYALGIA

EXERCISE: HOW TO DO POWER CALCULATIONS IN OPTIMAL DESIGN SOFTWARE

Discussion. Re C (An Adult) 1994

Natural background Electromagnetic Field (EMF) Levels on Earth

ISA 540, Auditing Accounting Estimates, Including Fair Value Accounting Estimates, and Related Disclosures Issues and Task Force Recommendations

A Case Study: Two-sample categorical data

In Support of a No-exceptions Truth-telling Policy in Medicine

Addendum to the 12th Report on Carcinogens

107 If I have the proofs DTA wanted, should I still ask for a hearing?

Purpose: Policy: The Fair Hearing Plan is not applicable to mid-level providers. Grounds for a Hearing

Asking and answering research questions. What s it about?

APPENDICES. Appendix I Business Ethical Framework

Guidelines for Incorporating & Strengthening Perspective-Taking & Self-Authorship into Division of Student Life Programs

January 2, Overview

Addressing the rapid rate of change in the DOT-regulated world

Using the sociological perspective changes how we perceive the surrounding world and ourselves. Peter Berger

Psychological Visibility as a Source of Value in Friendship

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

DOING SOCIOLOGICAL RESEARCH C H A P T E R 3

Part 2. Chemical and physical aspects

Prepare for tobacco industry interference

good reputation, and less chance to be chosen as potential partners. Fourth, not everyone values a good reputation to the same extent.

The Bomb in the Brain. Part 4

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Democratizing Science: Processes for the involvement of the public in scientific. issues and their success

Complications of Proton Pump Inhibitor Therapy. Gastroenterology 2017; 153:35-48 발표자 ; F1 김선화

Summary A LOOK AT ANTIANDROGEN THERAPIES FOR NONMETASTATIC CASTRATION-RESISTANT PROSTATE CANCER CASTRATION-RESISTANT PROSTATE CANCER TREATMENT OPTIONS

How to Conduct an Unemployment Benefits Hearing

Are the likely benefits worth the potential harms and costs? From McMaster EBCP Workshop/Duke University Medical Center

Precaution and the Affirmation of Risk The EMF Case

Lecture Notes Module 2

Special Education Fact Sheet. Special Education Impartial Hearings in New York City

Gender specific attitudes towards risk and ambiguity an experimental investigation

Competency Rubric Bank for the Sciences (CRBS)

Guidelines in Breast Screening Mammography: Pros and Cons JOSLYN ALBRIGHT, MD SURGICAL ONCOLOGIST, ADVOCATE CHRIST MEDICAL CENTER OCTOBER 1, 2016

Beyond Controlling for Confounding: Design Strategies to Avoid Selection Bias and Improve Efficiency in Observational Studies

Research Prospectus. Your major writing assignment for the quarter is to prepare a twelve-page research prospectus.

Effects of Sequential Context on Judgments and Decisions in the Prisoner s Dilemma Game

Working Through The Haze: What Legal Marijuana Means For Nevada Employers

Transcription:

Decision-Making under Uncertainty in the Setting of Environmental Health Regulations Author(s): James M. Robins, Philip J. Landrigan, Thomas G. Robins, Lawrence J. Fine Source: Journal of Public Health Policy, Vol. 6, No. 3 (Sep., 1985), pp. 322-328 Published by: Palgrave Macmillan Journals Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3342398 Accessed: 23/10/2008 14:39 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showpublisher?publishercode=pal. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We work with the scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. Palgrave Macmillan Journals is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Journal of Public Health Policy. http://www.jstor.org

Decision-Making Under Uncertainty in the Setting of Environmental Health Regulations JAMES M. ROBINS, PHILIP J. LANDRIGAN, THOMAS G. ROBINS, and LAWRENCE J. FINE INTRODUCTION ca~(a 4Th IR Austin Bradford Hill promulgated guidelines (1) for determining the likelihood that an association observed i i1 2 in a non-experimental study is causal. These guidelines S _ are often used to weigh epidemiologic evidence in de- :r O cf'*) ciding whether or not to regulate exposures to chemical hazards. We argue that excessive reliance on his guidelines is inappropriate for many decisions bearing on the regulation of environmental exposures. We consider an alternative, explicitly Bayesian approach to regulatory decision-making, and we discuss the advantages and pitfalls of this approach. We conclude that a major advantage of the Bayesian approach is that it helps make explicit the non-scientific social and political determinants of public health decisions. BRADFORD HILL S GUIDELINES: STRENGTHS AND WEAKNESSES In regulatory decision-making, substantial weight is given to evidence obtained from epidemiologic studies of human populations. Unfortunately, statistical associations observed between exposures and diseases in such studies may be either causal or non-causal. An observed association may reflect causality, or it may be due to the confounding effects of unmeasured risk factors, to various forms of bias, or to sampling variability. Conversely, failure to find an association may reflect either true lack of causality, or may result from confounding, bias or chance. In an attempt to systematize assessment of these issues, Sir Austin Bradford Hill promulgated guidelines for determining the likelihood that an association observed in an epidemiologic study is causal in nature. In Bradford Hill's guidelines, the observed strength of an association between exposure and disease is the cardinal criterion of causality. When 322

ROBINS ET AL. * ENVIRONMENTAL HEALTH REGULATIONS assessing causality, the strength of the association is measured as the relative risk (the ratio of the rate of disease in an exposed group to that in an unexposed group). If a relative risk of 10 or greater is found in an epidemiologic study, it is difficulto imagine that unmeasured risk factors or unconsidered biases could account for such an extreme association. In such a case, scientificonsensus on causality will almost certainly be reached. On the other hand, if a relative risk is found to be only 1.5, it is easy to suppose that uncontrolled biases or unmeasured risk factors could explain the observed association, and experts can be expected to disagree in their interpretation of such a result. This latter situation would pertain even if the study population were of sufficient size to produce a narrow confidence interval for the relative risk [e.g.,(1.2, 1.4)] and an extreme p-value (e.g., p <.oi). The problem is not simply one of statistical power; but rather, a deeper problem associated with the inherent limits of nonexperimental research. In any epidemiologic study in which the observed relative risk is less than 3 to 4, one may expect that consensus will never be reached among scientific experts that the observed association is truly causal in nature. As we have implied, the application of Bradford Hill's guidelines is appropriate for determining whether or not scientific consensus can be reached. However, these same guidelines are often employed for a different purpose, i.e., to weigh the strength of epidemiologic evidence in establishing environmental regulations. We argue that these guidelines provide an inappropriate basis for such regulatory decisions. In general, the public health benefits of regulation are best measured in terms of the number of lives saved (or the amount of serious morbidity prevented) per thousand individuals exposed, i.e., in terms of attributable risk to each exposed individual rather than in terms of relative risk. (More precisely, if we assume (i) that the total funds available for preventing environmental disease are fixed; (2) that the costs of regulating any given chemical increase linearly with the number of individuals exposed; and (3) that the regulatory cost per individual is the same for all chemicals, then regulating the exposures associated with the largest attributable risk per individual will maximize the number of lives saved. If the regulatory costs per individual differ for different chemicals, these costs must enter into the decision process as follows. Chemical A should be regulated in preference to a Chemical B whenever the product of the reciprocal of the regulatory cost per individual times the attributable risk per individual for Chemical A exceeds that for Chemical B. Thus, the public health benefits of regulation can still be summarized in terms of the attributable risk per 323

324 JOURNAL OF PUBLIC HEALTH POLICY * SEPTEMBER 1985 individual. If the costs of regulation do not increase linearly with the number of individuals exposed, the health benefits of regulation can no longer be simply summarized in terms of the attributable risk per individual when weighing regulatory costs against health benefits.) Consider, for example, that the death rate from colorectal cancer is over 30 times that from soft tissue sarcoma (2). It is therefore more important (in terms of number of lives saved per thousand individuals exposed) to regulate an exposure associated with a true relative risk of 1.5 for colorectal cancer than to regulate an exposure associated with a true relative risk of 15 for soft tissue sarcoma [since 30 X (1.5-i) is greater than (15-1)]. Given that the true relative risk for colorectal cancer is 1.5, it is likely that the observed relative risk will be less than 2 in any epidemiologic study with sufficient power to be seriously considered in the regulatory process. In these circumstances, using Bradford Hill's guidelines, scientists would be unable to reach a consensus that the true relative risk was greater than 1 and that true causality existed. Thus, a regulatory decision based strictly on Bradford Hill's guidelines (i.e., based on scientificonsensus) would in this situation treathe true relative risk for colorectal cancer as no different from 1. In contrast, scientificonsensus would exist on the need to regulate the exposure associated with the 15-fold increased risk for soft tissue sarcoma. As a result, the exposure which in actuality threatens fewer lives would be preferentially regulated. Essentially, then, a regulatory policy which is based strictly on a requirement for scientificonsensus is equivalent to a policy not to regulate substances associated with true relative risks of roughly 3 or less, even when the associated attributable risks are quite large. A BAYESIAN APPROACH TO REGULATORY DECISION-MAKING We have argued for the need to conside regulating exposures for which the possibility of reaching scientificonsensus on causality is unlikely or even inherently infeasible. As an alternative to an approach based on scientificonsensus, we consider an approach to regulation which is based on Bayesian decision analysis. The use of the Bayesian approach to medical decision-making not new. For example, Pauker and Kassirer (3) have recommended that decision making in clinical practice be based on a Bayesian approach. A clinician cannot wait for scientificonsensus among experts regarding diagnosis before deciding whether or not ot operate on a suspected case of appendicitis. Similarly, environmental regulators cannot delay regulating a suspected harmful exposure until scientificonsensus

ROBINS ET AL. * ENVIRONMENTAL HEALTH REGULATIONS 325 exists. In both instances, decision-making under uncertainty is necessary. We describe briefly how a Bayesian approach to environmental regulation might operate. An expert hired by a regulatory agency would be asked to determine to the best of his ability (based on the available data) his subjective degree of belief (i.e., his personal probability) that the relative risk associated with an exposure E (at the dose in question) exceeds i. He then is asked to state explicitly his degree of belief that the relative risk is between 1 and 1.3, that it is between 1.3 and 1.6, and so on. Suppose that such an expert states with probability 60% (i.e., has a degree of belief of 60%) that the relative risk for colorectal cancer is 1.o with probability 30% that the relative risk is 1.5, and with probability lo% that it is 3.0. Using a Bayesian analysis, the expert would then calculate his expectation as to the number of excess deaths due to colorectal cancer per hundred thousand workers by multiplying 10% times the number of excess deaths that would occur if the true relative risk were 3.0 plus 30% times the number of excess deaths that would occur if the relative risk were 1.5. A simple calculation (Table 1) shows that from the perspective of this expert, more Colorectal Cancer Soft Tissue Sarcoma TABLE 1 Calculations Demonstrating Expected Excess Deaths for the Two Exposures Described in the Text Personal probability of given relative risk.6.3.1 Proportion of excess deaths above death rate X in the unexposed x (equals relative risk -1.o) x (.s - 1.0) x x (1.0-1.o) x x (3.0-1.0) x 1.0 X (io.o - i.o) x Annual death rate per 100,000 in the unexposed* 22.3 22.3 22.3 Expected annual excess per 100,000 among the exposed: = Contribution to annual excess deaths per 100,000 among the exposed 0.0 -- 33.4 = +4-4 7.8.74 = 6.7 * for ages 0-74, both sexes, all races, weighted by national population age distribution from reference 3.

326 JOURNAL OF PUBLIC HEALTH POLICY * SEPTEMBER 1985 lives would be expected to be saved by regulating such an exposure than by regulating an exposure (affecting an equal number of persons) that is known with 1oo% certainty to increase by 10 times the risk of death from a rare cancer such as soft tissue sarcoma. An agency regulator holding these same personal probabilities should act to regulate the exposure associated with colorectal cancer before the exposure associated with soft tissue sarcoma, even if he or she believes there is a 60% chance that such a regulatory effort would have no health benefits. This is so because over time this regulator and the agency must consideregulating hundreds or thousands of chemicals; and thus, over the long run, the regulator will expect that more lives will be saved by using a Bayesian approach to regulation than by using an approach based on scientificonsensus. The advantages of this Bayesian approach appear twofold: i) it incorporates the attributable risk into decision making; 2) it requires the rationale for a regulatory decision to be stated explicitly. PITFALLS OF THE BAYESIAN APPROACH In principle the Bayesian approach to decision-making makes excellent public health sense. Nonetheless, advocating this approach may be quite dangerous in a society, such as ours, in which political and economic power is unevenly distributed. We provide examples of the possible dangers. Using our Bayesian calculus, if economicosts are equal, it may be more beneficial in terms of total lives saved to control exposures associated with a small increase risk to many individuals than to control exposures associated with quite a high risk for relatively few individuals. Clearly, however, this calculus is unfair to relatively small groups of workers performing dangerous jobs. The problem is that in advocating the Bayesian approach, we have acted as though the costs and benefits of regulation were applied to the same individuals. In fact, however, this is frequently not the case. Small groups of individuals are asked in our society to bear disproportionate risks. Attempts at resolution of this dilemma through offering incentivesuch as hazard pay for high-risk jobs is ethically and politically suspect, particularly when only the poor need consider such trade-offs. Thus, considerations of fairness must be integrated into any Bayesian approach. Explicit consideration of whose costs and whose benefits are at stake is a necessity. Another potential pitfall of the Bayesian approach is its susceptibility to influence by the unstated prior beliefs of experts and regulators. For example, under the Toxic Substances Control Act, industrial epidemiolo-

ROBINS ET AL. * ENVIRONMENTAL HEALTH REGULATIONS 327 gists are required to report to the EPA those chemicals found to be suspect in epidemiologic studies. If, however, industry selectively hires epidemiologists who have strong prior beliefs that most chemicals are not hazardous, such experts will, using a Bayesian approach, tend to discount observed relative risks of 2 to 3 as being due to bias or to confounding. As a consequence, they might be less likely to report a potentially dangerous chemical to EPA than would other members of the scientificommunity. Similarly, when the influence of the business lobby is strong in the Federal Government, individuals hired as regulators will tend to be persons who have demonstrated strong prior beliefs that most chemicals are safe. When these regulators combine uncertain positive evidence of hazard with their strong prior beliefs of safety, they may fail to regulate under circumstances in which other members of the scientific community would have taken action. Of course, the same considerations could apply in a reverse fashion to "pro-labor" epidemiologists or regulators with strong prior beliefs that many chemicals are hazardous. We expect that the distribution of political power among contending parties in the regulatory process will determine the relative influence of variously held prior beliefs. CONCLUSIONS Despite these potential pitfalls, we see two reasons for popularizing a Bayesian approach to regulatory decision-making. First, in the aftermath of the Supreme Court decision on benzene, there is a widespread feeling that the Federal Government should not and need not regulat exposures in the absence of scientificonsensus. In this setting, relatively pro-industry experts will argue the position that the presently available data on a given substance are not sufficiento form any scientifi consensus concerning causality; acceptance of this argument can effectively preclude regulation. Our argument, that the ability to reach scientifi consensushould have little to do with regulatory decision-making, may help to counter such a position. A second argument in favor of the adoption of a Bayesian approach is that it may persuade the scientifi community to require that experts report explicitly the distribution of their subjective probabilities. Thus, experts would be put in the position of having to say explicitly whether or not they believe, for example, that there is a 5% chance that a particular chemical exposure will cause 500 excess deaths. Requiring experts to report explicitly their probability distributions will insure that their willingness to accept a substantial amount of risk to the public cannot be hidden behind

328 JOURNAL OF PUBLIC HEALTH POLICY? SEPTEMBER 1985 a cloak of apparent "scientific objectivity." The public may be much less willing than the expert to accept such a level of risk. Further, when the public has the opportunity to see the wide range of expert opinion as to the number of excess deaths to be expected from a particular exposure, it will become apparent that in many cases the available scientific data are open to quite conflicting interpretations. The Bayesian approach provides a means for rational decision making in the face of such uncertainty. Additionally, it provides a means for the systematic examination of the subjective beliefs of the experts and regulators chosen by those who hold political power. REFERENCES 1. Hill, A. B. Principles of Medical Statistics, 9th Ed. New York: Oxford University Press, 1971. 2. National Cancer Institute Monograph 57. Surveillance, Epidemiology and End Result: Incidence and Mortality Data, 1973-77; pp. 10, 84, 150. National Institutes of Health Publication No. 81-2330, Bethesda, Maryland, June, 1981. 3. Pauker, S. G., and S. P. Kassirer. "The Threshold Approach to Clinical Decision Making," N EngJ Med 302 (1980): 1108-17.