Bryce Huebner: Macrocognition: A Theory of Distributed Minds and Collective Intentionality

Similar documents
Is integrated information theory viable as a theory of consciousness? George Deane

A Difference that Makes a Difference: Welfare and the Equality of Consideration

COMP329 Robotics and Autonomous Systems Lecture 15: Agents and Intentions. Dr Terry R. Payne Department of Computer Science

An Escalation Model of Consciousness

DYNAMICISM & ROBOTICS

The Standard Theory of Conscious Perception

Artificial Intelligence: Its Scope and Limits, by James Fetzer, Kluver Academic Publishers, Dordrecht, Boston, London. Artificial Intelligence (AI)

5.8 Departure from cognitivism: dynamical systems

Comments on David Rosenthal s Consciousness, Content, and Metacognitive Judgments

Brain Mechanisms Explain Emotion and Consciousness. Paul Thagard University of Waterloo

Intentionality. Phil 255

What role should heroes, saints and sages play within moral theory? While it would be unfair to

PSYCHOLOGICAL CONSCIOUSNESS AND PHENOMENAL CONSCIOUSNESS. Overview

AGENT-BASED SYSTEMS. What is an agent? ROBOTICS AND AUTONOMOUS SYSTEMS. Today. that environment in order to meet its delegated objectives.

Perception, Biology, Action, and Knowledge

Abstracts. An International Journal of Interdisciplinary Research. From Mentalizing Folk to Social Epistemology

Assignment 4: True or Quasi-Experiment

Cognitive Neuroscience History of Neural Networks in Artificial Intelligence The concept of neural network in artificial intelligence

LECTURE 5: REACTIVE AND HYBRID ARCHITECTURES

Eliminative materialism

1 What is an Agent? CHAPTER 2: INTELLIGENT AGENTS

A conversation with Professor David Chalmers, May 20, 2016 Participants

Physiological Function, Health and Medical Theory

CS148 - Building Intelligent Robots Lecture 5: Autonomus Control Architectures. Instructor: Chad Jenkins (cjenkins)

Intentional Horizons

Our previous accounts of perceptual experience accepted the phenomenal principle:

The Mind-Body Problem: Physicalism

Grounding Ontologies in the External World

M.Sc. in Cognitive Systems. Model Curriculum

CFSD 21 st Century Learning Rubric Skill: Critical & Creative Thinking

Subjective Consciousness: A Self-Representational Theory

Behavior Architectures

Neuroscience and Generalized Empirical Method Go Three Rounds

H.O.T. Theory, Concepts, and Synesthesia: A Reply to Adams and Shreve

Consider the following aspects of human intelligence: consciousness, memory, abstract reasoning

What is Morality? Paul Thagard University of Waterloo

Department of Psychological Sciences Learning Goals and Outcomes

Artificial Intelligence

Research Methodology in Social Sciences. by Dr. Rina Astini

ERA: Architectures for Inference

The scope of perceptual content, II: properties

Conclusion. The international conflicts related to identity issues are a contemporary concern of societies

Review of Tim Bayne s The Unity of Consciousness

Chapter 9 Motivation. Motivation. Motivation. Motivation. Need-Motive-Value Theories. Need-Motive-Value Theories. Trivia Question

ICS 606. Intelligent Autonomous Agents 1. Intelligent Autonomous Agents ICS 606 / EE 606 Fall Reactive Architectures

Durkheim. Durkheim s fundamental task in Rules of the Sociological Method is to lay out

Asking and answering research questions. What s it about?

On A Distinction Between Access and Phenomenal Consciousness

Materialism and the Mind and Body Problem:

Group Assignment #1: Concept Explication. For each concept, ask and answer the questions before your literature search.

Book Information Jakob Hohwy, The Predictive Mind, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013, ix+288, 60.00,

Whose psychological concepts?

Critical review (Newsletter for Center for Qualitative Methodology) concerning:

Personal Talent Skills Inventory

Robot Learning Letter of Intent

PLANNING THE RESEARCH PROJECT

Computational Explorations in Cognitive Neuroscience Chapter 7: Large-Scale Brain Area Functional Organization

Artificial Intelligence and Human Thinking. Robert Kowalski Imperial College London

Functionalism. (1) Machine Functionalism

CHAPTER TWO. The Philosophical Approach: Enduring Questions

Where No Interface Has Gone Before: What Can the Phaser Teach Us About Label Usage in HCI?

Assessing the Foundations of Conscious Computing: A Bayesian Exercise

On The Scope of Mechanistic Explanation in Cognitive Sciences

Artificial Neural Networks (Ref: Negnevitsky, M. Artificial Intelligence, Chapter 6)

In his essay The Truth in Psychological Egoism, Hugh Lafollette uses a modified version

"The Extended Mind" Extended. Joseph S. Fulda

Empty Thoughts: An Explanatory Problem for Higher-Order Theories of Consciousness

AFFECTS, MOODS, EMOTIONS, AND BELONGING

Agent-Based Systems. Agent-Based Systems. Michael Rovatsos. Lecture 5 Reactive and Hybrid Agent Architectures 1 / 19

Artificial Intelligence Lecture 7

Happiness, Pleasure, and Satisfaction

Sparse Coding in Sparse Winner Networks

Mapping A Pathway For Embedding A Strengths-Based Approach In Public Health. By Resiliency Initiatives and Ontario Public Health

Explaining an Explanatory Gap Gilbert Harman Princeton University

A Computational Framework for Concept Formation for a Situated Design Agent

CHAPTER 3 METHOD AND PROCEDURE

What is analytical sociology? And is it the future of sociology?

"Games and the Good" Strategy

Behaviorism: Laws of the Observable

Audio: In this lecture we are going to address psychology as a science. Slide #2

reward based power have ability to give you what you want. coercive have power to punish

Computational Cognitive Neuroscience

Existential Therapy scores GOALS!

REPORT ON EMOTIONAL INTELLIGENCE QUESTIONNAIRE: GENERAL

Answers to end of chapter questions

Evolutionary Programming

The Concept of Simulation in Control-Theoretic Accounts of Motor Control and Action Perception

Module 1. Introduction. Version 1 CSE IIT, Kharagpur

Research Ethics and Philosophies

AU B. Sc.(Hon's) (Fifth Semester) Esamination, Introduction to Artificial Neural Networks-IV. Paper : -PCSC-504

Commentary on Behavioral and Brain Sciences target article: Jones & Love, Bayesian Fundamentalism or Enlightenment?

Institute: Symbiosis School for Liberal Arts. Course Name : Psychology (Major/Minor) Introduction :

EMPATHY AND COMMUNICATION A MODEL OF EMPATHY DEVELOPMENT

Thinking Like a Researcher

COHERENCE: THE PRICE IS RIGHT

Review of Animals and the Economy. Steven McMullen Palgrave, pp., ebook and hardcover. Bob Fischer Texas State University

Generalization and Theory-Building in Software Engineering Research

Student Name: XXXXXXX XXXX. Professor Name: XXXXX XXXXXX. University/College: XXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXX

REVIEW OF ATTENTION, NOT SELF BY JONARDON GANERI

PSYCHOLOGISM VS. CONVENTIONAL VALUES by L.A. Boland

Transcription:

Minds & Machines DOI 10.1007/s11023-015-9355-0 BOOK REVIEW Bryce Huebner: Macrocognition: A Theory of Distributed Minds and Collective Intentionality Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2014, x+278, $65.00, ISBN 9780199926275 Matteo Colombo Ó Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015 Bryce Huebner s Macrocognition is a book with a double mission. The first and main mission is to show that there are cases of collective mentality in our world (p. 5). Cases of collective mentality are cases where groups, teams, mobs, firms, colonies or some other collectivities possess cognitive capacities or mental states in the same sense that we individually do. To accomplish this mission, Huebner develops an account of macrocognition, where the term macrocognition is intended as shorthand for the claim that system-level cognition is implemented by an integrated network of specialized computational mechanisms (p. 5). The second mission of Huebner s book is to elaborate an account of cognitive architecture that could set the groundwork for identifying under what conditions groups, and individuals indeed, are fruitfully and justifiably said to be minded. To this end, Huebner tackles several foundational issues in cognitive science, including traditional philosophical questions about the nature of representation, intentionality and consciousness. In order to substantiate the hypothesis that there are cases of collective mentality in our world, Huebner pursues a three-step strategy. The first step starts from Daniel Dennett s intentional system theory. The claim is that some types of behaviours of some kinds of groups are usefully and voluminously predictable from the intentional stance. If these types of behaviours are usefully and voluminously predictable from the intentional stance, then the kinds of groups exhibiting them are sometimes justifiably treated as if they were rational agents whose choices and actions are governed by beliefs, desires, perceptions and other types of mental states. However, while this step licenses claims about collective beliefs and desires, it falls short of M. Colombo (&) The Tilburg Center for Logic, General Ethics and Philosophy of Science, University of Tilburg, PO Box 90153, 5000 LE Tilburg, The Netherlands e-mail: m.colombo@uvt.nl

M. Colombo establishing that some types of collective behaviours are not better explained by reference to only individual mental states and processes. Closer attention should be paid to the causal and computational structures underlying putative cases of collective mentality in order to adequately evaluate to what extent positing collective mental states and processes bears explanatory value. The second step in Huebner s argument is an account of cognitive architecture. This account aims at picking out the types of representations and causal structures that are likely to be in place where collective mentality occurs. In fact Huebner offers a general theory of cognition. He identifies the kinds of representations, computational mechanisms, informational structures and transactions that a system should possess for it to count as a cognitive system. The claim is that cognition whether individual or collective should be posited only where interfaced networks of specialized computational mechanisms transform and consume representations in various formats, so as to produce flexible, skilful, goal-directed, system-level behaviour. If some group displays some type of behaviour that is underlain by this kind of distributed, integrated, parallel, network-like computational architecture, then there is reason to see the group as a genuine macrocognitive system. The third and final step in Huebner s argument consists in showing that some groups in our world display types of behaviours such that (i) the intentional stance is justifiably applicable to make sense of those behaviours, and (ii) the right kind of computational architecture for cognition underlies those behaviours. The satisfaction of these two conditions would provide us with good evidence that, although rare, there are some cases of collective mentality in our world. Macrocognition is divided into two parts. Part 1 includes four chapters (Chapters 1 4), where the bases for a theory of group minds are laid down. Part 2 includes the remaining six chapters of the book (Chapters 5 10), where some details are filled out, challenges are tackled, and some directions for future research on macrocognition highlighted. In Part 1, Chapter 1 motivates Macrocognition s overall project by first introducing ten possible real-world cases of collective mentality, and then by outlining the argument unpacked throughout the rest of the book. Chapter 2 canvasses a range of strategies that can be adopted to elaborate a theory of macrocognition. The chapter formulates, motivates and illustrates two constraints that must be respected by those who wish to argue that some collectivities are mindful. According to the first constraint, collective mental states or processes should not be posited where collective behavior results from an organizational structure set up to achieve the goals or realize the intentions of a few powerful and/or intelligent people (p. 21). In this case, the goals of few individuals are pursued; these individuals possess all relevant knowledge, make all relevant decisions, and have control over other individuals and informational structures, which are just instrumental in achieving their goals. Since information trickles down through the group from those in command, the cognitive architecture of a system can be exhaustively specified by reference to the psychological states of the individuals who make decisions, and the way that these decisions affect those who must conform to them (p. 21).

Macrocognition According to the second constraint, collective mental states or processes should not be posited where collective behavior bubbles up from simple rules governing the behavior of individuals (p. 23). This second constraint targets relevant literature in social epistemology, political science and economic modelling of collective behaviour, where collective mentality is typically explained in terms of individual mental states and of algorithms for their aggregation. In this case, the complex behaviour of the group bubbles up from individual behaviours aggregated according to some mechanical rule. The group as such need not represent any goal or rule in order to display the complex behaviour. No one in the group is in charge; and no one has control over all other individuals or over the informational transactions within the group. Individual states and processes, along with some rule of aggregation, exhaustively explain collective behaviour. Positing collective mental states here would open the door to worries of causal overdetermination and explanatory superfluity. Chapter 3 formulates a third and final constraint on accounts of macrocognition. According to this constraint, collective mental states or processes should not be posited where the capacities of the components belong to the same intentional kind as the capacity that is being ascribed to the collectivity and where the collective computations are no more sophisticated than the computations that are carried out by the individuals who compose the collectivity (p. 72). The idea is that, relative to the task at hand, the capacities and intelligence of the individuals constituting a macrocognitive system should be less sophisticated than the capacities and intelligence displayed at the system-level. In particular, the meaning of the representations of a macrocognitive system should not be fully derivable from the meaning of the representations of the individuals constituting the system. With these three constraints in place, Chapter 4 articulates an account of mentality so as to make some steps towards the accomplishment of Macrocognition s second mission. Huebner argues that the mind should be seen as an elegant kludge a computational system composed of a multi-layer network of distributed and integrated sub-mechanisms, each of which is specialized to solve some narrowly specified task. The organization of this network should allow for complex representational structures to be built out of simpler ones, and enable sophisticated, flexible, goal-directed behaviour. In the light of this foundation for macrocognition, three requirements should be satisfied by any appeal to collective mentality (p. 96): 1. A specification of the types of information that a collectivity is sensitive to; 2. A functional decomposition of the cognitive states that a collectivity is capable of being in and cognitive processes that it is capable of carrying out; and 3. An account of the computational procedures that implement these mental states and processes. With these requirements in place, collective mentality is likely to occur where a distributed network of individual minds with various degrees of sophistication and different cognitive capacities faces problems that can be broken down into

M. Colombo parallelizable sub-problems that demand the combination of many different cognitive capacities, whose solutions can be checked independently. While I agree on the general spirit of Huebner s diagnosis, I would have liked some more details. For I sometimes find the general theory of cognition on offer just a little too coarse-grained to assess properly. To be sure, the scope and readability of this, like of the other chapters of Macrocognition, are wonderful. Huebner s writing is accessible and engaging, and the range of evidential sources and arguments he weaves together is impressive. It is then no surprise that an account of cognitive architecture could be drawn only in broad strokes, since detailed information often trades off with scope and readability. However, a little more information about which kinds of algorithms and which kinds of network topologies are particularly suitable to sustain (macro)cognition would have been a bonus: it would have greatly added to the significance of Macrocognition s contribution more on this below. Part 2 begins with Chapter 5. After registering the resistance of commonsense psychology in attributing minds to collectivities, Huebner meticulously, and persuasively, I believe, parries several objections to collective mentality based on the idea that the marks of the mental are consciousness and intentionality, and collectivities cannot possess conscious or genuinely intentional mental states. Huebner s (counter)argumentative strategy treats psychological kinds like types of whiskey: Like whiskeys, psychological kinds must be classified by triangulating a variety of considerations including structural organization and history, as well as a variety of socially instituted facts that arise partially as a result of convention (p. ). Huebner shows that, once psychological kinds are picked out by relying on this type of triangulation, prominent objections to collective intentionality or consciousness lose much of their bite. Chapters 6 and 7 address the objection that collective mentality is explanatorily superfluous. The notion of collective representation is focal. The question is whether there are any kinds of collectivities that act on the basis of the way that they represent the world (p. 140). Chapter 6 sets the stage for answering this question affirmatively. It argues that many person-level mental representations derive their content from sub-personal structures that are themselves representational and intentional. If this is correct, then there is logical, and empirical space indeed, for maintaining that some types of collective representations possess a type of derived content that is genuinely cognitive. Do these representations guide flexible, goaldirected collective behaviour, at least in some cases? Chapter 7 provides an affirmative answer. While it is unlikely that collectivities have such representations as fully-fledged beliefs and desires, Huebner argues that, at least sometimes, collective systems possess genuine mental representations, including simple perception-action loops and states of the kind Ruth Millikan dubbed pushmipullyu representations, which are consumed by the system to both describe what is the case and direct what is to be done. If this is correct, then there are actually cases of macrocognitive systems that act on the basis of the way they represent the world, and collective mental states are not explanatorily superfluous. Here we find one of the central commitments of Macrocognition, viz. a rejection of the claim that there must be a semantically transparent mapping

Macrocognition between the kinds of states and processes that arise at the system level and the kinds that are operative in the production of those system-level states. (Huebner personal communication). In most of the plausible cases of group cognition, Huebner maintains that we find multiple semantically robust operations being conducted in parallel, and then being integrated into a system-level representation that makes use of its own semantic categories, which may partially overlap with the lower-level representations. Chapters 8 and 9 explore a host of intricate issues about collective personhood and collective responsibility. Huebner first delineates different kinds of collective minds. He maintains that having a mind is not an all-or-nothing property. Maximal mentality involves a rational self-conscious point of view, along with capacities for taking responsibility for one s behaviour, for committing oneself to norms of rationality and for negotiating these norms with other agents. Minimal minds lack these capacities. They traffic in representations that cannot be decoupled from their immediate environmental causes. According to Huebner, while plausible cases of macrocognition are most properly characterised as cases of minimal minds, only a defense of maximal-macrocognition could license familiar claims about collective intentionality and collective responsibility (p. 212). Although some large-scale scientific collaborations afford an intriguing and promising target for such a defense, Huebner acknowledges that a great deal more ethnographic, anthropological and computational work is required to justify the claim that there are maximally-minded collectivities that can be morally or epistemically responsible. Chapter 10 succinctly wraps things up, summarizing the argument developed in the previous chapters and the contribution of Macrocognition to current literature in philosophy and cognitive science. Macrocognition is fair-minded book. Its arguments intermingle careful, evenpaced, philosophical analysis with empirical evidence from several fields, including the cognitive, biological and social sciences. No sweeping claims are made, though the topic could invite them. Weak spots in the arguments are acknowledged; intuition pumps are always kept in check by concrete case-studies and scientific results; and different ways are emphasised in which macrocognition can bear on our practical engagements with the world. As I mentioned above, my main complaint concerns the level of detail at which Huebner s account of cognitive architecture is pitched. The account can be captured by the following twelve commitments: 1. Cognitive systems are computational systems. 2. Cognitive systems are parallel processing networks. 3. These networks are composed of semi-autonomous mechanisms. 4. These mechanisms are distributed. 5. Each of these mechanisms carries out some task-specific function. 6. Each of these mechanisms is largely encapsulated. 7. These mechanisms output representations. 8. These representations can be integrated, thereby producing more complex representations.

M. Colombo 9. Local interfaces between the mechanisms are responsible for integrating representations. 10. Each of these interfaces is implemented by a trading-language. 11. There need not be a semantically transparent mapping between system-level and subsystem-level representations. 12. The parallel processing networks constituting cognitive systems produce flexible system-level behaviour. In order to properly assess Huebner s account, I would have liked some more details about several of these ten claims filled out. Here are just a couple of examples. Following common usage in much of contemporary cognitive science, Huebner characterises computation in a liberal way, in terms of transformation of representations. But, in fact, the discussion of computing and cognitive architecture is cashed out in terms of parallel distributed processing and constraint satisfaction, which resonate many of the themes dear to connectionist cognitive science. In embracing a broadly connectionist view of computing, Huebner, it appears, assumes that a conservative approach to cognitive architecture should be privileged for developing an account of macrocognition (p. 167). Yet, this assumption looks unmotivated, and potentially unfruitful to me. It looks unmotivated because I believe that, currently, the most powerful tools and concepts that can be employed to understand (different aspects of) cognition come not only from the usual triad, viz. symbolicism, connectionism and dynamicism. Powerful tools and concepts can more easily be found in the toolboxes of rapidly expanding fields such as machine learning, control theory, information theory, graph and Bayesian decision theory. Given that there is a myriad of cognitive phenomena, it is very likely that different approaches and models will be the most explanatorily useful for some of these phenomena but not for others. If this is correct, then it may be unfruitful to look for the correct, general, computational architecture of cognition. If there is no single, general, correct account of cognitive architecture, then it could well turn out that there is no single general account of macrocognition. Rather, different approaches to the architecture of cognition may yield sharper insight, and be most useful, for some macrocognitive phenomena, but not for all. A second instance where I would have liked some more detail concerns the algorithms that would support macrocognition. In particular, Macrocognition could tell us something more about how exactly certain representations should be transformed and integrated to enable cognition. In several places, Huebner only hints at winner-take-all algorithms as a class of promising rules for at least transforming low-level representations into more complex ones. But how exactly would a winner-take-all mechanism transform low-level representations into more complex ones? And why does Huebner single this mechanism out? In a system that implements some (hard) winner-take-all rule, given some input data, units having the largest input activation achieve their maximum activation value while activation in all other units is suppressed. This is a class of schemes that contribute to promote unsupervised competitive learning in artificial recurrent neural networks, where different processing units compete for the right to respond to a subset of the input data. Winner-take-all competitive learning can efficiently

Macrocognition perform clustering on the input data contributing to support detection of visual features and selective attention. Nonetheless, it is not obvious why winner-take-all learning is particularly important or useful here. For there are many other machine learning algorithms that can tackle clustering and classification problems in a more efficient and biologically plausible fashion. For instance, Hierarchical Bayesian algorithms can be used flexibly to learn about the presence and importance of sensory features, to combine these features, and to learn structures of many different forms, by evaluating which form best explains a given dataset. While this kind of probabilistic approach to cognition provides fresh insight on several issues for example, about how cognitive systems come to perceive objects in the world, or about how abstract knowledge can guide learning and action from sparse, noisy data, or about how causal relations can be grasped it also promises to have traction on biological cognition. I believe it would be an intriguing project to build the case for collective mentality from the perspective of powerful machine learning schemes such as Hierarchical Bayesian algorithms. These couple of complaints do not detract from the value of Macrocognition. They just confirm that the road towards (macro)cognition is still long and full of excitement, as acknowledged by Huebner. Macrocognition has helped us take a couple of steps closer on this road. It is an original and thought-provoking book that advances the field of cognitive science in a number of theoretically and practically important directions.