Occurrent belief and dispositional belief. Jie Gao University of Edinburgh

Similar documents
Int ro du c t ion. James R. B e eb e

Effective Intentions: The Power of Conscious Will

Knowledge in and out of Contrast

Statistics and Full Belief

reward based power have ability to give you what you want. coercive have power to punish

On Our Experience of Ceasing to Exist

The Mystery of Stakes and Error in Ascriber Intuitions

Is it possible to gain new knowledge by deduction?

Step 2 Challenging negative thoughts "Weeding"

What is analytical sociology? And is it the future of sociology?

Comments on David Rosenthal s Consciousness, Content, and Metacognitive Judgments

Epistemic Motivation and Groups Reaction to Change: Effects of Need for Cognitive Closure on Norms Transmissions in a Laboratory Micro-Culture

Actionability Judgments Cause Knowledge Judgments

A Knobe Effect for Belief Ascriptions *

REVIEW OF ATTENTION, NOT SELF BY JONARDON GANERI

Existential Therapy scores GOALS!

Chapter 3: Perception and the Self in IPC 01/24/2012

2. Two paradigm cases of self-deception: the cuckold (wishful thinking) and the quarterback (willful self-deception).

Vagueness, Context Dependence and Interest Relativity

c) Redraw the model and place on it relevant attributions for each of the four boxes.

Gold and Hohwy, Rationality and Schizophrenic Delusion

Who Is Rational? Studies of Individual Differences in Reasoning

Human intuition is remarkably accurate and free from error.

Student Name: XXXXXXX XXXX. Professor Name: XXXXX XXXXXX. University/College: XXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXXX

Individual Determinants of Deception Detection Performance: Need for Closure, Attributional Complexity and Absorption

Abstracts. An International Journal of Interdisciplinary Research. From Mentalizing Folk to Social Epistemology

Eliminative materialism

A Difference that Makes a Difference: Welfare and the Equality of Consideration

Persuasive Speech. Persuasive Speaking: Reasoning with Your Audience

PSYCHOLOGICAL CONSCIOUSNESS AND PHENOMENAL CONSCIOUSNESS. Overview

Representational Content and Phenomenal Character

Learning Styles Questionnaire

"Games and the Good" Strategy

24.500/Phil253 topics in philosophy of mind/perceptual experience

Personal Talent Skills Inventory

Arguments for intentionalism


Intentionality. Phil 255

Groups, norms, and conformity. What s it about?

Emotional Intelligence

Intentional Action and Side Effects in Ordinary Language. The chairman of the board of a company has decided to implement

Research Ethics and Philosophies

The need for closure concept disclosed: Delineating motivation from ability in human decision-making

TTI Personal Talent Skills Inventory Coaching Report

The influence of (in)congruence of communicator expertise and trustworthiness on acceptance of CCS technologies

Perception, Biology, Action, and Knowledge

Kahneman, Daniel. Thinking Fast and Slow. New York: Farrar, Straus & Giroux, 2011.

Intentional Horizons

TROUBLES FOR BAYESIAN FORMAL EPISTEMOLOGY? A RESPONSE TO HORGAN

INTERVIEWS II: THEORIES AND TECHNIQUES 1. THE HUMANISTIC FRAMEWORK FOR INTERVIEWER SKILLS

Workshop on Dying Well Chinese University of Hong Kong Centre for Bioethics November 9-10, 2015

Belief Updating in Moral Dilemmas

INTERPERSONAL RELATIONSHIPS (IR)

Definitions of Nature of Science and Scientific Inquiry that Guide Project ICAN: A Cheat Sheet

EMOTIONAL INTELLIGENCE TEST-R

Causality and counterfactual analysis

Recognizing Ambiguity

Self-Handicapping Variables and Students' Performance

CSC2130: Empirical Research Methods for Software Engineering

UNCORRECTED PROOF. Daniel Steel / Across the Boundaries 01-DanielSteel-chap01 Page Proof page :48pm ACROSS THE BOUNDARIES

Behavioural Economics University of Oxford Vincent P. Crawford Michaelmas Term 2012

Module 2 Mentalizing

CONCEPTUAL FRAMEWORK, EPISTEMOLOGY, PARADIGM, &THEORETICAL FRAMEWORK

1.2. Husserlian Phenomenology And Phenomenological Method

Council on Licensure, Enforcement and Regulation 1

Chapter 2 Research Methodologies Related to Pharmacy Practice: An Overview

Chapter 3-Attitude Change - Objectives. Chapter 3 Outline -Attitude Change

Papineau on the Actualist HOT Theory of Consciousness

54 Emotional Intelligence Competencies

PHENOMENAL CONSCIUOSNESS: QUALIA & QUINNING QUALIA. Prof. Rajakishore Nath, Department of Humanities & Social Science, IIT Bombay

THE CUSTOMER SERVICE ATTRIBUTE INDEX

9/5/ Research Hazards Awareness Training

We Can Test the Experience Machine. Response to Basil SMITH Can We Test the Experience Machine? Ethical Perspectives 18 (2011):

FEEDBACK TUTORIAL LETTER

Bending it Like Beckham: Movement, Control and Deviant Causal Chains

The assumption of agency: a realist theory of the production of agency in everyday social life

I. Logical Argument (argument) appeals to reason and intellect.

Perception and Mind-Dependence: Lecture 4

Durkheim. Durkheim s fundamental task in Rules of the Sociological Method is to lay out

VALIDITY OF QUANTITATIVE RESEARCH

Realism and Qualitative Research. Joseph A. Maxwell George Mason University

Section 4 - Dealing with Anxious Thinking

This article, the last in a 4-part series on philosophical problems

Consciousness and Theory of Mind: a Common Theory?

JUNIOR SEMINAR 3: MYERS-BRIGGS TYPE INDICATOR MARC TUCKER

School of Psychology. Professor Richard Kemp. Cognitive Bias: Psychology and Forensic Science

Sociology 3308: Sociology of Emotions. Prof. J. S. Kenney. Overheads Class 5-6: The Psychology of Emotions:

Skepticism about perceptual content

The idea of an essentially contested concept is incoherent.

In his essay The Truth in Psychological Egoism, Hugh Lafollette uses a modified version

2015 NADTA Conference Pre-Education Committee Book Club Everyday Bias, Howard J. Ross, Suggested Group Discussion Questions

How do we procrastinate? Master's Dissertation: Addressing procrastination while doing your dissertation ( or how to overcome procrastination)

Chapter 3 Perceiving Ourselves and Others in Organizations

Communication & Assertiveness Training. Presented by Military & Family Life Counselors

Introduction to the Scientific Method. Knowledge and Methods. Methods for gathering knowledge. method of obstinacy

Chapter 11 Nonexperimental Quantitative Research Steps in Nonexperimental Research

Commentary on Constructing New Theory for Identifying Students with Emotional Disturbance

Project exam in Cognitive Psychology PSY1002. Autumn Course responsible: Kjellrun Englund

Chapter 1 Introduction to I/O Psychology

Materialism and the Mind and Body Problem:

Transcription:

Occurrent belief and dispositional belief Jie Gao University of Edinburgh EENM, Paris, July 4 th, 2016

Outline 1. Distinctions between dispositional belief and occurrent belief 2. Psychological effects on occurrent belief formation 3. Practical factors effects on occurrent belief formation 4. Two explanations of practical factors effects on occurrent belief formation 5. Relevant epistemic rationalities 6. Ramifications 1

Distinction: common ground Dispositional belief Information held in my memory and that could be manifested in certain circumstances Occurrent belief Thoughts are actively brought to mind whose contents vary depending on circumstances Relation with knowledge Dispositional belief but not occurrent belief is entailed by knowledge. 2

Traditional picture Occurrent belief and dispositional belief are different aspects of the same state. representationalism dispositionalism If a subject holds an occurrent belief that p, she also holds a dispositional belief that p. Once a belief is occurrently formed for the first time, it would automatically be added to the belief box and ready to be called into mind for future purposes. 3

Distinction: folk psychological Closure: The juncture at which a belief crystallizes and turns from hesitant conjecture to a subjectively firm fact (Kruglanski and Webster 1996: 266) A hypothesis: Occurrent belief requires closure, but dispositional belief does not. 4

Distinction folk psychological (continued) Unconfident Examinee (modified from Radford 1966) Kate is taking a history test. She had studied carefully and has been doing well on all the questions so far. She has now reached the final question, which reads What year did Queen Elizabeth die? As Kate reads this question she feels relief, since she had expected this question and memorized the answer. But before Kate can pause to recall the date, the teacher interrupts and announces that there is only one minute left. Now Kate panics. Her grip tightens around her pen. Her mind goes blank, and nothing comes to her. She feels that she can only guess. So, feeling shaken and dejected, she writes 1603 which is of course exactly the right answer. 5

Distinction folk psychological X-Phil on this case: (continued) Myers-Schulz and Schwitzgebel (2013): Did Kate believe that Queen Elizabeth died in 1603? - 63% deny belief to Kate. Rose and Schaffer (2013): Three probes eliciting the dispositional reading of belief. E.g. Did Kate still believe (in the sense that she still held the information in her mind even if she could not access it) that Queen Elizabeth died in 1603? - 74%, 58% and 71% ascribe belief to Kate. 6

Distinction folk psychological Analysis of the studies: (continued) There are reasons to think that Kate has dispositional belief but not closed-mindedness in the key proposition. Rose and Schaffer (2013) s study elicits the notion of dispositional belief held by folks. Participants in Myers-Schulz and Schwitzgebel (2013) s study deny the target belief to Kate in the occurrent sense. 7

Distinction folk psychological (continued) My assumption about the two types of belief: Occurrent belief that p necessarily involves: (i) closed-mindedness about whether p; (ii) (defeasible) dispositions to rely on p as a premise in reasoning and assert that p in the actual circumstances e.g., if asked whether p, the subject would answer affirmatively. Dispositional belief doesn t necessarily involve these conditions. At time t, a dispositional belief is triggered but it does not turn into its occurrent form. I will explore under what conditions this could happen. 8

Psychological effects As the previously mentioned empirical studies show, psychological factors such as panic and anxiety could block the proper activation of dispositional belief into occurrent forms. Furthermore, one s level of subjective confidence should be associated with occurrent belief and should be separated from whether one has dispositional belief. 9

Practical factors effects Need-for-closure: the desire of a definite answer to a question o Need for non-specific closure (henceforth NFC ) o Need for specific closure Need-to-avoid-closure (henceforth NTAC ): the desire of avoidance of closure Intrapersonal variations (i.e. variations within one person, depending on the circumstances) -Webster and Kruglanski 1994 Interpersonal variations (i.e. variations of NFC between different people) -Kruglanski and Webster 1999, Webster 1993, Kruglanski et al. 1993, and Webster et al. 1996 10

Practical factors effects (continued) Practical factors triggering high NFC: When a settled judgment is required An expected benefit of closure (e.g. when attaining closure brings others approval) Increased costs of continuing in ambiguity under conditions (e.g. time pressures) Conditions rendering information processing more difficult and laborious (e.g. tiredness, distracting background noise and making the task seem dull) 11

Practical factors effects (continued) Practical factors triggering high NTAC: Antecedent emphasis on accuracy of the judgment High costs of being wrong with the judgment Others esteem and appreciation for accuracy Making the task seem enjoyable and interesting When there is no special situational factor, one s NFC would be neutral (neutral NFC constitutes a baseline NFC that differs from one to another). 12

Practical factors effects (continued) The level of NFC or NTAC has significant effects on the amount of evidence necessary for occurrent belief formation. E.g. Mayseless and Kruglanski (1987, Study 2): The participants were asked to identify the digit very briefly shown on a tachistoscope. All subjects were able to repeat the stimulus presentation as many times as they wish. High NTAC condition - 18.28 times Neutral condition - 5.14 times High NFC condition - 3.24 times 13

Practical factors effects (continued) Practical sensitivity of occurrent belief formation: Effects of high NFC Feel uneasy with an absence of settled opinion Considerably cognitively impatient and hasty Generating less alternative hypotheses Effects of high NTAC Cherish uncertainty Cognitively cautious Generating more alternative hypotheses o Inhibiting a previously held dispositional belief turn into its occurrent form 14

Practical factors effects (continued) Consider a typical high NTAC situation a perceived high stakes case (e.g. the bank case) The doxastic attitudes of the high-stakes subject: Absence of occurrent belief that p Whether the subject has dispositional belief that p depends on her baseline NFC With high baseline NFC: probably maintain the dispositional belief (and hence also knowledge) With high baseline NTAC: probably lose the dispositional belief (and hence also knowledge) 15

Explanations of the practical sensitivity of occurrent belief formation Two possible explanations of the practical sensitivity of occurrent belief formation: 1. Doxastic pragmatism: practical sensitivity of the threshold for occurrent belief (derived from Bach 2005, 2008, 2010, Ganson 2008, Weatherson 2005 on practical sensitivity of belief) 2. Credal pragmatism: practical sensitivity of credence. The threshold for occurrent belief is stable. I will argue for credal pragmatism based on relevant empirical data and theoretical considerations. 16

Explanations of the practical sensitivity of occurrent belief formation Empirical data for practical sensitivity of credence: E.g. Mayseless and Kruglanski (1987, Study 2): High NTAC condition Neutral condition High NFC condition Confidence in the initial hypothesis (0-100) Shift of confidence after acquiring new evidence Final confidence (0-100) 27.43 13.46 90.8 34.78 20.44 57.98 50.84 38.49 78.03 unfounded confidence paradox (Kruglanski) 17

Explanations of the practical sensitivity of occurrent belief formation Practical sensitivity of credence: Under high NFC: Assign more importance to early information Readily give credibility to whatever early evidence Finish with a relatively high confidence in spite of having relatively less evidence. Under high NTAC: Assign less importance to early information Give less credibility to each piece of evidence Settle with a high confidence judgment only after exploring evidence thoroughly. 18

Explanations of the practical sensitivity of occurrent belief formation Empirical data concerning the practical sensitivity of the threshold: E.g. Mayseless and Kruglanski (1987, Study 2): Final confidence (0-100) High NTAC condition 90.8 Neutral condition 57.98 High NFC condition 78.03 Practical sensitivity of threshold alone cannot explain why final confidence in the high NFC condition is much higher than in the neutral condition, even though the evidence in the neutral condition is stronger than the high NFC condition. 19

Explanations of the practical sensitivity of occurrent belief formation Other consideration favouring credal pragmatism over doxastic pragmatism: - simplicity and ontological parsimony Assuming a variable threshold seems unnecessary and would require burdensome ontological and psychological commitments. In conclusion, credal pragmatism is better than doxastic pragmatism. 20

Dispositional belief Dispositional belief is more resistant to the effects of psychological and practical factors than occurrent belief. Dispositional belief depends on credence one would have in normal circumstances. -By normal circumstances I mean those circumstances in which there are no psychological factors that could temporarily block the access to one s possessed information or opinion and in which one s needfor-closure is neutral. 21

The rationality for practical sensitivity of occurrent belief formation and credence Three types of epistemic rationality: 1. Ideal epistemic rationality: relative to procedures leading to highly accurate epistemic achievements in ideal circumstances 2. Purist rationality: relative to epistemic achievements accessible to a human cognition exclusively affected by truth-relevant factors 3. Adaptive rationality: relative to the cognitive regulation for nonideal agents with limited cognitive abilities in real-life environments Practical sensitivity of occurrent belief formation and credence is adaptively rational, but not purist or ideally rational. 22

Ramifications Compatibility with moderate invariantism - Dispositional belief is the relevant type of belief required for knowledge and dispositional belief is governed by purist rationality standards (i.e., not influenced by conditions present in abnormal circumstances such as high stakes, urgency ). Credal pragmatism explains data concerning knowledge ascriptions in terms of the dispositional nature of occurrent belief - Intuitive judgments of all high stakes cases - Infallibilist intuition of knowledge - Concessive knowledge attributions and other related data 23

References Bach, K. (2005). The emperor s new knows. In G. Preyer & G. Peter (Eds.), Contextualism in philosophy: knowledge, meaning, and truth (pp. 51 89). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Bach, K. (2008). Applying pragmatics to epistemology. Philosophical Issues, 18(1), 68 88. Bach, K. (2010). Knowledge in and out of context. In J. K. Campbell, M. O Rourke, & H. S. Silverstein (Eds.), Knowledge and Skepticism (pp. 105 36). MA: MIT Press. Ganson, D. (2008). Evidentialism and pragmatic constraints on outright belief. Philosophical Studies, 139(3), 441 458. Kruglanski, A. W., & Webster, D. M. (1991). Group members reactions to opinion deviates and conformists at Varying degrees of Proximity to decision deadline and of environmental noise, 61(2), 212 225. Kruglanski, A. W., Webster, D. M., & Klem, A. (1993). Motivated resistance and openness to persuasion in the presence or absence of prior information. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 65(5), 861 876. Kruglanski, A. W., & Webster, D. M. (1996). Motivated closing of the mind: Seizing and freezing. Psychological review, 103(2), 263. 24

References (continued) Mayseless, O., & Kruglanski, A. W. (1987). What makes you so sure? Effects of epistemic motivations on judgmental confidence. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 39(2), 162 183. Myers-Schulz, B., & Schwitzgebel, E. (2013). Knowing that P without believing that P. Noûs, 47(2), 371 384. Nagel, J. (2008). Knowledge ascriptions and the psychological consequences of changing stakes. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 86(2), 279 294. Rose, D., & Schaffer, J. (2013). Knowledge entails dispositional belief. Philosophical Studies, 166(1), 19 50. Weatherson, B. (2005). Can we do without pragmatic encroachment? Philosophical Perspectives, 19(1), 417 443. Webster, Donna M. (1993). Motivated augmentation and reduction of the overattribution bias. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 65(2), 261 271. Webster, Donna M, & Kruglanski, A. W. (1994). Individual differences in need for cognitive closure. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 67(6), 1049 1062. Webster, D. M., Richter, L., & Kruglanski, A. W. (1996). On leaping to conclusions when feeling tired: Mental fatigue effects on impressional primacy. Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, 32(2), 181 195. 25

Thank you! 26