Asymmetric dominance and phantom decoy effects in games q

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Asymmetric dominance and phantom decoy effects in games q"

Transcription

1 Available online at Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 104 (2007) Asymmetric dominance and phantom decoy effects in games q Andrew M. Colman a, *, Briony D. Pulford a, Fergus Bolger b a School of Psychology, University of Leicester, Leicester LE1 7RH, UK b Durham Business School, Durham University, Mill Hill Lane, Durham DH1 3LB, UK Received 28 July 2006 Available online 4 May 2007 Accepted by Robyn Dawes Abstract In individual choices between alternatives x and y, the availability of a third alternative z, judged inferior to x but not to y, tends to increase preferences for x. Two experiments investigated corresponding strategic asymmetric dominance effects in games. In Experiment 1, 72 players chose strategies in six symmetric 3 3 games, each having one strategy dominating just one other, or in reduced 2 2 games constructed by deleting the dominated strategies. Asymmetrically dominated strategies, even when unavailable (phantom decoy), increased choices of the strategies that dominated them and bolstered decision confidence. In Experiment 2, 81 participants played 12 similar but asymmetric games with or without dominated strategies, and similar asymmetric dominance, phantom decoy, and confidence effects were found. Ó 2007 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved. Keywords: Asymmetric dominance; Confidence; Focal point; Game theory; Property alpha; Reason-based choice; Strategic dominance When choosing between alternatives x and y, the availability of a third alternative z, to which the decision maker strictly prefers x but not y, tends to increase the decision maker s preference for x (Huber, Payne, & Puto, 1982). For example, a shopper may feel indifferent between one cell phone x, costing $120 with call charges of 15c per minute, and another y, costing $100 with call charges of 25c per minute, but the availability of a third option z, costing $140 with call charges of 20c per minute, may cause the shopper to prefer x to y, because x is cheaper than z on both relevant product attributes, whereas y is not. This asymmetric dominance effect is q This project was supported by Grant RES from the Economic and Social Research Council of the UK. The authors thank Clare Davies for help with data collection, Eldar Shafir, Robert Sugden, Ali al-nowaihi, Sanjit Dhami, Karl Teigen, and other participants who provided useful comments on this research at the ESRC symposium on Confidence in Interactive Decisions, 1 July 2005, and anonymous referees for suggesting significant further improvements. * Corresponding author. Fax: +44 (0) address: amc@le.ac.uk (A.M. Colman). large and robust, occurring not only under experimental conditions but also in real in-store purchases, and it has been reported even when the dominated alternative z was presented as an unavailable phantom decoy option, like an item on a menu or catalogue that cannot be ordered because it is out of stock or unavailable (Ariely & Wallsten, 1995; Doyle, O Connor, Reynolds, & Bottomley, 1999; Mishra, Umesh, & Stem, 1993). The implications of this phenomenon for interactive decisions in games have not previously been empirically investigated or apparently even discussed. The phenomenon of strategic dominance in games suggests a natural method of modeling a game-theoretic counterpart of asymmetric dominance. 1 In a dyadic (two-player) game, 1 The term dominance has subtly different though related denotations in decision theory and game theory. In this article, we are concerned only with strict dominance. In individual decision making, an alternative x (strictly) dominates another y for a decision maker for whom x is better than y on all relevant attribute dimensions. In game theory, a strategy x (strictly) dominates another y for a player who receives a better payoff from choosing x than y irrespective of the strategy or strategies chosen by the other player(s) /$ - see front matter Ó 2007 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved. doi: /j.obhdp

2 194 A.M. Colman et al. / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 104 (2007) one strategy dominates another for a particular player if it yields a higher payoff to that player irrespective of the strategy chosen by the co-player. Strategic asymmetric dominance is a feature of any game in which a player has one strategy that strictly dominates just one of two or more other strategies. A strategic asymmetric dominance effect may be said to occur if the presence of an asymmetrically dominated Strategy z causes the player s preference for the dominating Strategy x to increase relative to another Strategy y in the game. A phantom decoy effect may be said to occur if an asymmetrically dominated Strategy z, shown but not available for choice, increases the player s preference for the dominating Strategy x. This article reports the results of two experiments designed to investigate whether strategic asymmetric dominance and phantom decoy effects occur in dyadic games with dominant strategies. We examined dyadic games in which each player had three strategies, one of which strictly dominated just one other, and there were no other dominance relations between strategies. In one treatment condition, the asymmetrically dominated strategies were phantom decoys, visible but unavailable for choice, and in another they were available for choice, though inadmissible for rational (payoff-maximizing) players because they were strictly dominated, a generally accepted prediction of game theory being that if a game has a dominated strategy, then a rational player will not choose it. We compared strategy choices in these 3 3 games with choices in reduced 2 2 versions of the games formed by deleting the dominated strategies. The theoretical basis for our hypotheses, stated formally at the end of this introduction, is reason-based choice (Shafir, Simonson, & Tversky, 1993; Shafir & Tversky, 1992; Tversky & Shafir, 1992). The key assumption is that, in decisions under uncertainty, when outcomes depend on unpredictable factors and there are no obvious rules to guide decisions, people tend to seize on any reason that may present itself for choosing one particular alternative rather than another. Our 2 2 control games afforded players no obvious reasons for choosing either strategy, and we assumed that players would therefore tend to lack confidence in their strategy choices. The expanded 3 3 versions, in contrast, each had one strategy strictly dominating one other, and this provided players with an obvious reason for choosing the dominant strategy. The reason for preferring a dominant strategy is that it is unconditionally better than the strategy that it dominates irrespective of the co-player s choice and this remains true even if the dominated strategy is a phantom decoy that is not available to be chosen, because an option that is unconditionally better than something else has at least something to recommend it. Property a and Savage s first postulate The asymmetric dominance effect seems obviously irrational, but it is not immediately obvious why this should be so. In Appendix A we show formally that it violates the basic contraction property of rational choice, Sen s (1969) Property alpha (a), and we prove that this property is implied by the first postulate of Savage s (1954/1972) theory of subjective expected utility (SEU), arguably the most fundamental axiom of rational choice. Informally, Property a asserts that if a decision maker considers a particular member of a set of alternatives to be the best, then that decision maker must also consider it to be best in any subset drawn from that set (for a critical discussion, see Sugden, 1985). Sen (1970) offered the following intuitive example of Property a: If the world champion in some game is a Pakistani, then he must also be the champion in Pakistan (p. 17). This example is flawed, because a chess player (for example) could win the world championship but lose the national championship of Pakistan. We suggest the following tidied-up example: If the oldest man in the world is in Pakistan, then he must also be the oldest man in Pakistan. Property a is sometimes called regularity (Doyle et al., 1999; Huber et al., 1982; Luce, 1959; Tversky & Simonson, 1993). A probabilistic version of it is assumed by Tversky s (1972) theory of elimination by aspects (see also Tversky & Sattah, 1979) and by Luce s (1959) theory of individual choice. It is a special case of the independence of irrelevant alternatives (Chernoff, 1954; Fishburn, 1973; Nash, 1950). Luce and Raiffa (1957, p. 288) offered the following illustration of this more general principle. Suppose a customer in a restaurant, having studied a menu, considers ordering either salmon or steak and eventually decides on salmon. The waiter then informs the customer that fried snails are also available. The customer, who detests fried snails, responds to the waiter: Splendid, I ll change my order to steak. This behavior seems manifestly irrational, because the addition of the fried snails option should be irrelevant to the customer s preference for salmon over steak. It turns out that any violation of Property a is also a violation of Savage s first postulate. This twofold postulate asserts, first, that for any pair of alternatives x and y, a decision maker must consider either x to be at least as good as y, ory at least as good as x, or both, in other words the decision maker s preference relation must be complete; and second, that for any three alternatives x, y, and z, if a decision maker considers x to be at least as good as y, andy at least as good as z, then this decision maker must also consider x to be at least as good as z, ensuring that the preference relation is transitive (Savage, 1954/1972, p. 18). See Appendix A for a for-

3 A.M. Colman et al. / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 104 (2007) malization of this postulate and a mathematical proof that Property a is implied by it. Most authorities consider Property a to be a fundamental characteristic of rational individual choice (see, e.g., Chernoff, 1954; Fishburn, 1973; Kreps, 1988; Luce & Raiffa, 1957; Nash, 1950; Sen, 2002; Tversky & Simonson, 1993), although it is not necessarily a characteristic of collective choice or of individual choice based on rationality criteria other than expected utility maximization (Sugden, 1985). Asymmetric dominance in games In strategic games, various contextual factors that might explain apparent violations of Property a are filtered out by the abstract representation of games. Because the payoffs represent utilities, any violation of Property a must necessarily represent a departure from the rationality assumptions of game theory. Summarizing experimental evidence on individual decision making accumulated over two decades, Luce (1977) commented that the only property of general choice probabilities that has not been empirically disconfirmed is regularity [Property a] (p. 229). The more recently discovered asymmetric dominance effect violates it, however, and the version of it that we have defined for strategic games may also violate it. A strategic asymmetric dominance effect may be shown to occur in games if players choose y from the strategy set {x,y} and x from an expanded strategy set {x, y, z} that includes an additional Strategy z, strictly dominated by x but not by y. At an aggregate level, any significant increase in the relative frequency of choosing x in the three-strategy case may be interpreted as evidence for a strategic asymmetric dominance effect. The frequencies in the two- and three-strategy versions of the games can differ significantly from each other only if a significant proportion of players violate Property a. A more powerful test could capitalize on the fact that the effect has been found to occur even when dominated alternatives are presented as unavailable phantom decoys that cannot be chosen (Doyle et al., 1999). There is persuasive evidence that irrelevant alternatives can influence decisions significantly (e.g., Bastardi & Shafir, 1998; Carpenter, Glazer, & Nakamoto, 1994; Shafir et al., 1993). Preferences for dominant strategies have, of course, been extensively documented in experimental games. In particular, Cooper, DeJong, Forsythe, and Ross (1990) studied choices in several 3 3 games based on a fixed 2 2 game to each of which a third strategy, dominated by one or more of the original 2 2 strategies, was appended for each player. The embedded 2 2 game had two symmetric Nash equilibria, and the dominated third strategy varied from one 3 3 game to the next. The results showed that different dominated strategies, though they were seldom chosen, caused the players to prefer different Nash equilibria in the larger games. Cooper et al. s study focused on factors affecting Nash equilibrium selection and not on asymmetric dominance or phantom decoy effects. Furthermore, it did not include a dominance-free control condition and therefore provided no evidence to show that the presence of a dominated strategy increases players preferences for the strategy that dominates it, relative to the 2 2 game without the dominated strategy. According to the standard assumptions of game theory, rational (payoff-maximizing) players always avoid choosing dominated strategies and expect their co-players to avoid them also. On this basis, we formulated the following hypotheses. Hypothesis 1: The inclusion of asymmetrically dominated strategies will lead players to choose the strategies that dominate them significantly more frequently than in the 2 2 control condition. Hypothesis 2: The inclusion of phantom decoy dominated strategies that are visible but not available for choice will also lead players to choose the strategies that dominate them significantly more frequently than in the 2 2 control condition. In both cases, strategic dominance provides players with a reason for choice, although in the second case the reason rests on a strategically irrelevant context effect only. The experiments described below were designed to test both hypotheses. To facilitate the interpretation of the results, the experiments also examine the possible role of confidence in choices involving dominant strategies. Experiment 1 Participants The participants in Experiment 1 were 72 undergraduate students at the University of Leicester, most of them studying economics, mathematics, or computer sciences, recruited through an online experimental participant volunteer panel on the School of Psychology s web pages. They volunteered to take part in what was described as a decision making experiment, earning an average of 6.20 (about $12) each, range 4.80 to 8.40, depending on the points that they scored in 12 games, six of which were excluded from analysis for reasons explained in the Results section below. The sample included 36 men and 36 women, with ages ranging from 18 to 31 years and a mean of (SD = 2.16) years. Design A randomized-groups experimental design was used, with players assigned to the following three treatment conditions. In the first (phantom decoy) condition, players made one-off decisions in six symmetric 3 3 games in which each player invariably had one strategy strictly dominating just one other, in the sense of yielding a

4 196 A.M. Colman et al. / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 104 (2007) strictly higher payoff irrespective of the co-player s choice, but the dominated strategies were phantom decoys, visible but unavailable for choice. A second (dominated-available) condition was similar to the phantom decoy condition, except that the asymmetrically dominated strategies were available for choice. In a third (control) condition, players made one-off decisions in six 2 2 games constructed by deleting the asymmetrically dominated row and column from each of the 3 3 games. From a strategic point of view, the phantom decoy and control conditions were identical, apart from the strategically irrelevant context provided by the unavailable third strategy in the phantom decoy condition, and any difference in choice behavior between these two conditions must be interpreted as a context effect. In a meaningful sense, the dominated-available condition was also strategically equivalent to the phantom decoy and control conditions, for players who are fully rational in the game-theoretic sense and have common knowledge of this rationality, because strictly dominated strategies are inadmissible for rational players, who never choose them and know that their co-players never choose them. Materials The six 3 3 games used in Experiment 1 (shown in Appendix B) were based on symmetric 2 2 games, all but two of which (Games 1 and 4) lacked dominant strategies. An example of a game used in Experiment 1 is shown in Fig. 1: this game elicited the largest asymmetric dominance effect. The dominant strategies are shown in row and column C and the dominated strategies in row and column E, although in the experiment, to control for positioning and labeling effects, strategies were rotated systematically so that they appeared equally frequently in all three rows and columns. We refer to the asymmetrically dominant strategy as C and the dominated strategy as E, although they were not invariably labeled as such in the payoff matrices seen by the players. To aid comprehension, the games were presented to the players with labeling and payoffs in Fig. 1. One of the games used in Experiment 1. Player I chooses between rows C, D, and E, Player II chooses between the columns, and the payoffs to Players I and II are shown in that order in the cell corresponding to the players choices. Strategy C strictly dominates Strategy E, because it yields a strictly higher payoff whichever strategy the co-player chooses. red for Player I and in blue for Player II, and each cell was divided diagonally from top left to bottom right to make the payoff matrices easier to read. The payoffs represented cash in units of pence sterling, ranging from 0 to 80 pence in each game. The main dependent variable was the relative frequency of C strategy choices choices of asymmetrically dominant strategies or their counterparts in the 2 2 versions of the games, not necessarily labeled C in the versions presented to the players. A secondary dependent variable was the players self-rated confidence in their decisions. Players indicated their strategy choices by circling C, D, or E on answer sheets in the dominated-available treatment condition, or by circling C or D in the control condition from which E was omitted. In the phantom decoy condition, players were shown 3 3 matrices, as in the dominated-available condition, but after studying each matrix, when they came to make their choices, they found that only two options were available on the answer sheet, because E was always unavailable, as it was the phantom decoy (sometimes labeled C or D on the players materials). The answer sheets also included small spaces in which players could briefly summarize the reasons for their choices. Finally, for each choice, players responded to a Likert scale ranging from 0 to 10, anchored by the phrases not at all confident and totally confident, respectively, indicating how confident they felt that the choice they made was the best one available. Procedure Pairs of participants were allocated quasi-randomly to treatment conditions, maintaining equal numbers of male male, female female, and male female pairs in each treatment condition to control for gender effects. However, no significant gender effects emerged, and we shall say nothing more about this variable. Between one and four pairs were tested in each experimental session. Players were seated so that they could not see their co-players, and communication between players was forbidden. After they had finished reading a page of instructions and filling in demographic information on their answer sheets, the experimenters conducted question-and-answer sessions, using three sample payoff matrices similar to those used in the appropriate treatment condition to clarify the players understanding of the matrices. It was explained to players at that point that they and their co-players would be looking at exactly the same payoff matrix on each trial. In the phantom decoy treatment condition, in which each payoff matrix included a strategy that could not be chosen, players were told: One of the rows and one of the columns is not available and can t be chosen by either person. You will not

5 A.M. Colman et al. / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 104 (2007) know which one is unavailable until you turn over the answer sheet for that problem. If, for example, you decide to choose row C and have found that this option is unavailable on the answer sheet, please go back to the payoff diagrams and make another choice. The unavailable strategies were always the strictly dominated E strategies (though not always labeled as such in the materials), and we did not expect players to choose them, except by mistake or through misunderstanding. The players recorded their choices, reasons, and confidence ratings for all six matrices during experimental sessions lasting approximately 35 min. They were not provided with any feedback until they had completed all of the games. At the end of each session, the experimenters added up the players scores, taking into account their choices and those of their co-players, and paid them whatever they had earned. Results In the dominated-available treatment condition, in which the dominated Strategy E was available for choice, only two players ever chose it. One chose it once out of six games and another chose it twice. The relative frequency of dominated strategy choices was thus 0.69 percent, suggesting that, in the main, the players understood the payoff matrices and the dominance relation that was crucial to the experiment. This was corroborated by their stated reasons for their choices. These comments were generally reasonable and thoughtful, and when a dominant strategy was present, they often alluded to the fact that a particular option was better (or worse) than another whatever the other player might choose. C choices. The main dependent variable was the relative frequency with which players chose the asymmetrically dominant strategies and their counterparts in the 2 2 versions of the games from which the dominated strategies were deleted. The mean numbers of C choices across treatment conditions are shown in Table 1. The mean relative frequency of C choices in the control condition, without asymmetric dominance, was 1.50 times out of six, or percent, compared to percent in the phantom decoy condition and percent in the dominated-available condition. The differences between these three means are highly significant: F(2, 69) = , p <.0001, partial g 2 =.26, suggesting that a substantial proportion of the variance in C choices is explained by differences between treatment conditions. Post hoc multiple comparisons using the Tukey HSD procedure revealed that the phantom decoy and dominated-available means do not differ significantly from each other, but that the phantom decoy mean is significantly higher than the control group mean (p <.008), and the dominated-available mean is also significantly higher than the control group mean (p <.0001). 2 These findings corroborate Hypotheses 1 and 2. Game-by-game analysis. Table 2 shows the relative frequencies of C choices across treatment conditions, separately for each game, with v 2 values, associated probability levels, and values of the effect size statistic w. According to Cohen (1992), an effect is small if w P.10, medium if w P.30, and large if w P.50. The figures in the columns labeled PD (phantom decoy), DA (dominated-available), and ND (control) are shown as percentages, although the v 2 values were calculated from raw frequencies. Four of the six games exhibited the strategic asymmetric dominance effect significantly, the exceptions being Games 2 and 5. In the control condition, the percentages of C choices were quite low in both of these games (29 percent and 25 percent, respectively), so that there was no ceiling to prevent the effect from occurring. Probable explanations for these anomalies will be addressed in the discussion section below. Confidence ratings. A 2 (treatment condition) 2 (dominant or non-dominant strategy chosen) ANOVA 3 revealed that players self-rated confidence in their decisions, on a scale from 0 to 10, differed significantly across treatment conditions. In the phantom decoy condition, the mean was M = 7.34, SD = 1.22; in the dominated-available condition, M = 6.76, SD = 1.60; and in the 2 2 control condition, M = 6.03, SD = These means differ significantly, F(2, 58) = 5.98, p =.004, partial g 2 =.17. Post hoc Tukey HSD multiple comparisons revealed that the first two means do not differ significantly from each other (p =.27), but confidence was significantly higher in the presence of an asymmetrically dominated strategy in the phantom decoy than in the control condition (p =.003). The dominatedavailable and control condition did not significantly differ (p =.14). 2 We originally included 12 games in this experiment, but in six of them large majorities of players preferred the C strategies in the control condition, creating a ceiling effect and leaving little room for any increase in preferences for C strategies when they became asymmetrically dominant in the other treatment conditions. An anonymous referee recommended relegating these games to a footnote. For the record, when all 12 games were included in the analysis, the differences between these three means were in the predicted direction but were not significant, F(2,69) = 2.06, p =.14, effect size partial g 2 =.06; but planned comparisons showed that the difference between the dominated-available and control conditions was significant, t(46) = 2.07, p <.05 (two-tailed), and that the difference between the phantom decoy and control conditions was non-significant, t (46) = 1.06, p =.29 (two-tailed). 3 When analyzing confidence ratings the confidence in C choices were compared with the confidence in not-c choices, thus incorporating the few E choices made by participants in the dominated-available condition in with the D choices.

6 198 A.M. Colman et al. / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 104 (2007) Table 1 Experiment 1: Mean numbers of C choices across treatment conditions N Mean SD Phantom decoy Dominated-available Control Total Table 2 Experiment 1: Percentages of C choices across phantom decoy (PD), dominated-available (DA), and control (ND) treatment conditions in each of six games, with v 2 test results and effect sizes w Game PD DA ND v 2 p w Overall, participants were less confident when choosing C (M = 6.36, SD = 1.77) than when choosing the D strategy (M = 7.10, SD = 1.44), F(1, 58) = 10.11, p =.002, partial g 2 =.15. The explanation for this can be found by considering the interaction of treatment condition and chosen strategy, F(2, 58) = 2.65, p =.08, partial g 2 =.08, and the game-by-game confidence ratings, broken down by treatment condition and choice of strategy in Table 3. Participants tended to choose D in the control condition and were more confident in that strategy (M = 6.80, SD = 1.14) than when choosing the C strategy (M = 5.25, SD = 2.15). Introducing the dominated strategy caused both an increase in choosing C (as previously discussed) and a significant increase in the confidence felt in the C strategy in both the phantom decoy condition (M = 7.17, SD = 1.12) and in the dominated-available condition (M = 6.56, SD = 1.46) compared with the control condition (M = 5.25, SD = 2.15), F(2, 58) = 7.39, p =.001, partial g 2 =.20, (post hoc Tukey HSD tests reveal that the first two conditions do not differ from each other p =.44, but both are higher than the control, p =.001 and p =.033, respectively). There was no significant increase in confidence when choosing the D strategy in any treatment condition (see Table 3), F(2, 58) = 1.36, p =.26, ns, partial g 2 =.05, presumably because participants were not choosing the strategy that dominated E, and thus their confidence did not increase. Discussion The results of Experiment 1 corroborate our main Hypotheses 1 and 2. Dominant C strategies were chosen significantly more frequently in the 3 3 versions of the games, and this effect was significant even when the dominated strategies were phantom decoys, replicating a finding on asymmetric dominance in individual choice (Doyle et al., 1999). The game-by-game analysis in Table 2 sheds more light on the results of Experiment 1. Most of the games exhibited the asymmetric dominance effect, the frequencies of C choices being significantly higher in the phantom decoy and dominated-available conditions than in the no-dominance control condition. The exceptions were Games 2 and 5, and it is not difficult to explain why these games did not follow the predicted pattern. A property that they share in common is the payoff dominance of the (D, D) Nash equilibrium. Although neither player has a dominant strategy in either of the 2 2 versions of the games, both 2 2 games have Nash equilibria at (D,D) and (C,C), and payoffs are higher for both players in the (D, D) than the (C, C) equilibrium. Selection of payoff-dominant equilibria is natural and compelling (Bacharach, 1999; Colman, 2003; Colman & Bacharach, 1997; Colman & Stirk, 1998; Cooper et al., 1990; Harsanyi & Selten, 1988; Sugden, 1993). In Games 2 and 5, the payoff dominance of the (D,D) outcome may have counteracted the influence of the strategic dominance of C over E to some extent in the 3 3 versions of these games by providing players with a persuasive reason for choosing D. None of the other games had payoff-dominant equilibria. These findings are consistent with the interpretation that payoff-dominant outcomes function as focal points (in the sense of Schelling, 1960; see also Janssen, 2006; Sugden & Zamarrón, 2006) for coordinating actions and expectations. The asymmetric dominance effect seems most likely to emerge when the control version of a game lacks a focal point on which players might expect to coordinate, presumably because asymmetric dominance provides a reason for choice, but it can be overwhelmed by a strong focal point such as a payoffdominant equilibrium that offers an alternative reason for choice. Game 3 also merits comment, because it elicited the largest and most highly significant asymmetric dominance effect. The reason was almost certainly the exceptionally low relative frequency of C choices in the 2 2 control condition. This low base of 8 percent C choices considerably lower than any other game used in the experiment left more scope than other games for increased C choices in the phantom decoy and dominated-available conditions, in which the C strategies dominated E strategies. Self-rated decision confidence was significantly higher when asymmetrically dominant strategies were present than in the control condition, and this effect was significant even in the phantom decoy condition, in which the dominated strategies could not be chosen. We shall comment in the General Discussion on a possible explanation for this confidence-bolstering effect.

7 A.M. Colman et al. / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 104 (2007) Table 3 Experiment 1: Mean confidence ratings in C and D choices across phantom decoy (PD), dominated-available (DA), and control (ND) treatment conditions in each of the six games Game C choices D choices PD DA ND PD DA ND Mean Experiment 2 The results of Experiment 1 provide some evidence for asymmetric dominance and phantom decoy effects in games, but the results, though significant, rest on a relatively small number of symmetric games. A new set of 12 games based on asymmetric 2 2 games was therefore devised for Experiment 2, partly to provide a broader-based test of the main hypotheses, and partly because suitable strategic structures for symmetric 2 2 games had been exhausted in Experiment 1. Method participants The participants were 81 undergraduate students recruited through the same online participant panel as was used in Experiment 1 but excluding anyone who had participated in that experiment. The sample comprised 30 men and 51 women, with ages ranging from 17 to 50 years and a mean of (SD = 5.83) years. In this experiment, participants earned an average of 7.20 (about $14) each, range 5.00 to 9.40, depending on the points scored in the games. Design and materials A randomized-groups experimental design was used, similar to the design used in Experiment 1. The 12 games used in Experiment 2 (shown in Appendix B) were based on 2 2 games chosen from the taxonomy of Rapoport, Guyer, and Gordon (1976). We selected 2 2 mixedmotive games without dominant strategies and without unique or payoff-dominant Nash equilibria (ignoring mixed strategies involving randomization). A Nash equilibrium is a combination of players strategies in which each player makes a best reply to the co-player s strategy, a best reply being a strategy yielding the highest payoff given the co-player s strategy choice. If a game has a unique Nash equilibrium, then rational players are bound to choose it, according to the assumptions of game theory. If a game has more than one Nash equilibrium, but one is payoff-dominant in the sense that it yields both players a higher payoff than the other, then that is the natural outcome of the game and, once again, we should expect rational players to choose it (Harsanyi & Selten, 1988). Our selection of 12 games without unique or payoff-dominant pure-strategy equilibria was intended to maximize the scope for asymmetric dominance effects. We constructed 3 3 versions of these games by first identifying the strategies that were predominantly dispreferred by players in an unpublished empirical study of single plays in 2 2 games carried out by Frenkel and reported in Rapoport et al. (1976, pp ). We labeled these strategies C and then added third strategies, asymmetrically dominated by them, which we labeled E, to the games. An example of one of the games used in Experiment 2 the one that yielded the largest asymmetric dominance effect is shown in Fig. 2. This game has Nash equilibria at (C,C) and(d,d), but neither of these is payoff dominant, because nether yields a higher payoff to both players than the other. Strategy C dominates Strategy E for both players and, as in all our games, there are no other dominance relations between strategies. The payoff matrices were presented to the participants as in Experiment 1, color-coded as an aid to comprehension, and once again the payoffs represented cash values in units of pence sterling, ranging from 0 pence to 80 pence. Rows and columns were systematically rotated to control for positioning and labeling effects although, once again for convenience, we refer to the dominant strategy as C and the dominated strategy as E. The Fig. 2. An asymmetric game used in Experiment 2, with no dominance relation between Strategies C and D. Strategy C strictly dominates Strategy E, because it yields a higher payoff irrespective of the coplayer s strategy choice.

8 200 A.M. Colman et al. / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 104 (2007) dependent variables were the relative frequencies of C choices (not necessarily labeled C in the versions presented to the players) and the players self-rated confidence in their decisions. In this experiment, to control for extraneous sources of variance arising from the fact that the games were asymmetric, participants were all assigned to the role of Player I, and one additional participant served as Player II to enable meaningful payoffs to be calculated (this player s choices were not included in the analysis below). Participants were told truthfully that they would each be paired with another player but, in fact, there was only one Player II. 4 Procedure The procedure was similar to Experiment 1, apart from the use of asymmetric games. The instructions given to the participants were essentially the same, but players were randomly assigned to treatment conditions without regard to gender. In light of the absence of gender differences in Experiment 1, we did not examine this variable again in Experiment 2. Players made one-off strategy choices in all 12 games during experimental testing sessions that lasted approximately 40 min. No feedback was given until they had completed all 12 games. Results In the dominated-available treatment condition, in which the dominated Strategy E was available for choice, players chose it rarely. One participant chose E eight times, one chose it six times, one chose it four times, two chose it twice, and two chose it once, yielding an overall relative frequency of dominated strategy choice of 2.47 per cent. Although dominated strategy choices were slightly more frequent than in Experiment 1, presumably because the asymmetric payoff matrices were more complex and harder to analyze, these data suggest that most players understood the games, including the crucial dominance property. 4 An anonymous referee has suggested that this involved deception, but we respectfully disagree. Each Player I was indeed paired with another participant in the role of Player II, and the fact that this Player II was the same for every Player I did not affect the dyadic task that each player faced. Player II was also paired with another (randomly chosen) participant to calculate her payoffs. C choices. The relative frequencies with which players chose the asymmetrically dominant C strategies and their counterparts in the 2 2 versions of the games are shown in Table 4. Differences between these three means are significant, F(2, 78) = 6.44, p =.01, partial g 2 =.14. Post hoc multiple comparisons using the Tukey HSD procedure reveal that the means for the phantom decoy and dominated-available treatment conditions are not significantly different from each other but that both are significantly larger than the mean for the control condition (p <.05), confirming the major experimental hypotheses that players would choose C significantly more frequently when it was asymmetrically dominant, both when the E strategy that it dominated was available for choice (Hypothesis 1) and when it was a phantom decoy (Hypothesis 2). Game-by-game analysis. In Table 5, the relative frequencies of C choices across treatment conditions are shown separately for each game, together with v 2 values, significance levels and values of the effect size statistic w. The asymmetric dominance effect is significant in the hypothesized direction (that is, with the smallest mean in the no-dominance control condition) in six of the games. In addition, in Game 9, the percentages differ in the hypothesized direction and there is a medium effect size, but the effect is only marginally significant. In two of the games in which the effect was not found, a ceiling effect is evident. In Game 5, for example, 89 percent of players chose C in the 2 2 control condition, and in Game 12, 70 percent of them chose it in the control condition. These were the two games with the highest frequencies of C choices in the control condition, and in both cases, relatively little headroom was left to increase the frequency of C choices when a dominated E strategy was appended in the phantom decoy and dominated-available conditions. Confidence ratings. The same analyses as for Experiment 1 were carried out on confidence ratings. Mean confidence ratings on a scale from 0 to 10 were highest in the phantom decoy condition (M = 6.57, SD = 1.53). The means in the dominated-available condition (M = 5.65, SD = 1.80) and the control condition (M = 5.90, SD = 1.09) were slightly lower. The three means differ significantly, F(2,78) = 3.18, p =.05, partial g 2 =.08, and post hoc Tukey HSD multiple comparisons confirm that confidence was significantly higher in the phantom decoy condition than in the dominated-available condition (p =.05) and that other differences were non-significant. Furthermore, confidence was higher when choosing dominant C strategies (M = 6.27, SD = 1.46) than non-dominant D strategies (M = 5.81, SD = 1.61), and this difference is significant, F(1,78) = 13.70, p <.001, partial g 2 =.15, providing further support for the suggestion that asymmetric dominance bolsters decision confidence. Game-by-game confidence ratings, broken down by treatment condition and choice of strategy, are shown in Table 6. The overall means hide the pattern of results somewhat, but by examining Table 6 with the results shown in Table 5 in mind it is clear that in the six games in

9 A.M. Colman et al. / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 104 (2007) Table 4 Experiment 2: Mean numbers of C choices (out of 12) across treatment conditions N Mean SD Phantom decoy Dominated-available Control Total which asymmetric dominance occurred (1, 2, 3, 4, 7, and 8), confidence when choosing the dominating Strategy C was higher in the phantom decoy and dominated-available conditions than in the control condition, following the same pattern as shown in Experiment 1. General discussion We capitalized on the game-theoretic concept of strategic dominance to define a form of asymmetric dominance applicable to interactive decisions and to investigate asymmetric dominance and phantom decoy effects in experimental games. Strategic dominance is a feature of any game in which a player has one strategy that dominates another, and a strategic asymmetric dominance effect may be said to occur if the addition of a dominated strategy to a game without dominance relations increases players preferences for the dominating strategy relative to a strategy that is neither dominant nor dominated. We proved that the asymmetric dominance effect violates Sen s (1969) Property a and hence also the first postulate in Savage s (1954/ 1972) subjective expected utility (SEU) theory, his most fundamental axiom of rational choice. The principal aim of the experiments reported in this article was to seek empirical evidence for the occurrence of strategic asymmetric dominance and phantom decoy effects in games. In Experiment 1, C strategies were chosen more frequently in the treatment condition in which they asymmetrically dominated third strategies than in the control condition without dominated strategies (see Tables 1 and 2). Dominant C strategies were chosen significantly more frequently in the 3 3 versions of the games, even when the dominated strategies were phantom decoys. These findings corroborate our main experimental Hypotheses 1 and 2. The effects were highly significant, with substantial effect sizes. Compared to the control condition, the effect occurred not only in the dominated-available condition but also in the phantom decoy condition in which the dominated strategy was visible but unavailable for choice. It is worth noting that in the phantom decoy condition, the games were strategically identical to those in the 2 2 control condition, from which the dominated strategies were deleted, differing only in extraneous context provided by the unavailable dominated strategies, yet for these games the effect was only slightly smaller than in the dominated-available condition. This corroborates and extends the findings of Doyle et al. (1999) and others regarding asymmetrically dominated phantom decoys in individual decision making. In the dominated-available condition, the 3 3 versions were strategically equivalent to their 2 2 counterparts for game-theoretically rational players for whom strictly dominated strategies are inadmissible, assuming that the players rationality is common knowledge in the game each player knows it, knows that the co-player knows it, and so on. In Experiment 2, we used asymmetric games without unique or payoff-dominant pure-strategy equilibria. Significantly more players chose the C strategy when it dominated a third E strategy, both in the phantom decoy condition, where E was visible but unavailable for choice, and in the dominated-available condition, where E could be chosen. These findings provide further corroboration of Hypotheses 1 and 2. When data from Table 5 Experiment 2: Percentages of C choices across phantom decoy (PD), dominated-available (DA), and control (ND) treatment conditions in each of 12 games, with v 2 test results and effect sizes w Game PD DA ND v 2 p w

10 202 A.M. Colman et al. / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 104 (2007) Table 6 Experiment 2: Mean confidence ratings in C and D choices across phantom decoy (PD), dominated-available (DA), and control (ND) treatment conditions in each of the 12 games Game C choices D choices PD DA ND PD DA ND Mean the 12 games used in Experiment 2 were analyzed separately (Table 5), this asymmetric dominance effect turned out to be statistically significant in six of the games. In a seventh (Game 9) the C strategy was chosen less frequently in the control condition than in the dominated-available or phantom decoy conditions, in line with Hypotheses 1 and 2, respectively, but the effect was only marginally significant. Two games that failed to elicit the effect (Games 5 and 12) were the two with the highest frequencies of C choices in the 2 2 control condition, and this is strongly suggestive of ceiling effects limiting the possibility of increasing C choices when they became dominant in the phantom decoy and dominated-available conditions. In all of the games used in Experiment 2, the C strategies were the ones that were predominantly dispreferred by players in Frenkel s study (reported in Rapport et al., 1976, pp ) of single plays in 2 2 games. We deliberately chose these strategies to avoid ceiling effects when their attractiveness was increased by making them dominate third strategies. In a few cases, the C strategies were nonetheless preferred by our players in the 2 2 control condition versions. The reasons for the differences between preferences in our Experiment 2 and in Frenkel s study are conjectural, but there are at least three possibilities. First, the players in Experiment 2 were male and female British undergraduate students, whereas Frenkel s players were all male Canadian undergraduates, and there is evidence (reviewed in Colman, 1995 and elsewhere) to show that both sex and nationality often influence choices in mixed-motive games, although it is worth recalling that no sex differences were found in Experiment 1. Second, the payoffs in each of the games used in Experiment 2 were 0, 20, 40, 60, or 80 and represented monetary payoffs in pence sterling, whereas in Frankel s study they were 10, 1, 1, or 10 and did not represent money: prizes of $15, $10, and $5 were offered to the three participants among 96 who accumulated the largest total points over all the games. Third, the players in Experiment 2 made 12 individual decisions in a single 40-min session, whereas Frenkel s players made 320 decisions (78 different games, each repeated at least twice) in their own time over a period of 48 h and were told that they could consult with others if they wished. Analysis of players self-rated confidence in their decisions in Experiment 1 revealed evidence of significantly higher confidence in the chosen strategy when it dominated an inferior strategy, even if that strategy was not available for choice. This tends to suggest that the asymmetric dominance and phantom decoy effects may be due to a bolstering of confidence in strategies when they have other strategies to dominate. In any individual or interactive choice, an alternative tends to appear more attractive when juxtaposed with something manifestly less attractive on all relevant attributes or dimensions, and our evidence suggests that this increases decision makers confidence to choose it, in line with reason-based choice theory. In Experiment 2, self-rated decision confidence was significantly higher in the phantom decoy condition than in the dominated-available condition. This suggests that the presence of phantom decoy strategies bolstered players decision confidence more than asymmetrically dominated strategies that were available for choice. The most obvious reason is that players had only two available strategies from which to choose in the phantom decoy condition, and are therefore likely, other things being equal, to have more confidence in their choices than in the dominated-available condition, in which they chose from three available strategies. It is

The Game Prisoners Really Play: Preference Elicitation and the Impact of Communication

The Game Prisoners Really Play: Preference Elicitation and the Impact of Communication The Game Prisoners Really Play: Preference Elicitation and the Impact of Communication Michael Kosfeld University of Zurich Ernst Fehr University of Zurich October 10, 2003 Unfinished version: Please do

More information

Appendix: Instructions for Treatment Index B (Human Opponents, With Recommendations)

Appendix: Instructions for Treatment Index B (Human Opponents, With Recommendations) Appendix: Instructions for Treatment Index B (Human Opponents, With Recommendations) This is an experiment in the economics of strategic decision making. Various agencies have provided funds for this research.

More information

Disjunction Effect in Prisoners Dilemma: Evidences from an Eye-tracking Study

Disjunction Effect in Prisoners Dilemma: Evidences from an Eye-tracking Study Disjunction Effect in Prisoners Dilemma: Evidences from an Eye-tracking Study Evgenia Hristova (ehristova@cogs.nbu.bg) Maurice Grinberg (mgrinberg@nbu.bg) Central and Eastern European Center for Cognitive

More information

Some Thoughts on the Principle of Revealed Preference 1

Some Thoughts on the Principle of Revealed Preference 1 Some Thoughts on the Principle of Revealed Preference 1 Ariel Rubinstein School of Economics, Tel Aviv University and Department of Economics, New York University and Yuval Salant Graduate School of Business,

More information

Effects of Sequential Context on Judgments and Decisions in the Prisoner s Dilemma Game

Effects of Sequential Context on Judgments and Decisions in the Prisoner s Dilemma Game Effects of Sequential Context on Judgments and Decisions in the Prisoner s Dilemma Game Ivaylo Vlaev (ivaylo.vlaev@psy.ox.ac.uk) Department of Experimental Psychology, University of Oxford, Oxford, OX1

More information

A Comment on the Absent-Minded Driver Paradox*

A Comment on the Absent-Minded Driver Paradox* Ž. GAMES AND ECONOMIC BEHAVIOR 20, 25 30 1997 ARTICLE NO. GA970508 A Comment on the Absent-Minded Driver Paradox* Itzhak Gilboa MEDS KGSM, Northwestern Uni ersity, E anston, Illinois 60201 Piccione and

More information

Team Reasoning and a Rank-Based Function of Team s Interests

Team Reasoning and a Rank-Based Function of Team s Interests Team Reasoning and a Rank-Based Function of Team s Interests Jurgis Karpus Mantas Radzvilas April 2015 Abstract Orthodox game theory is sometimes criticized for its failure to single out intuitively compelling

More information

Equilibrium Selection In Coordination Games

Equilibrium Selection In Coordination Games Equilibrium Selection In Coordination Games Presenter: Yijia Zhao (yz4k@virginia.edu) September 7, 2005 Overview of Coordination Games A class of symmetric, simultaneous move, complete information games

More information

Koji Kotani International University of Japan. Abstract

Koji Kotani International University of Japan. Abstract Further investigations of framing effects on cooperative choices in a provision point mechanism Koji Kotani International University of Japan Shunsuke Managi Yokohama National University Kenta Tanaka Yokohama

More information

Volume 30, Issue 3. Boundary and interior equilibria: what drives convergence in a beauty contest'?

Volume 30, Issue 3. Boundary and interior equilibria: what drives convergence in a beauty contest'? Volume 30, Issue 3 Boundary and interior equilibria: what drives convergence in a beauty contest'? Andrea Morone University of Bari & University of Girona Piergiuseppe Morone University of Foggia Abstract

More information

Introduction to Game Theory Autonomous Agents and MultiAgent Systems 2015/2016

Introduction to Game Theory Autonomous Agents and MultiAgent Systems 2015/2016 Introduction to Game Theory Autonomous Agents and MultiAgent Systems 2015/2016 Ana Paiva * These slides are based on the book by Prof. M. Woodridge An Introduction to Multiagent Systems and the online

More information

Emanuela Carbonara. 31 January University of Bologna - Department of Economics

Emanuela Carbonara. 31 January University of Bologna - Department of Economics Game Theory, Behavior and The Law - I A brief introduction to game theory. Rules of the game and equilibrium concepts. Behavioral Games: Ultimatum and Dictator Games. Entitlement and Framing effects. Emanuela

More information

In this paper we intend to explore the manner in which decision-making. Equivalence and Stooge Strategies. in Zero-Sum Games

In this paper we intend to explore the manner in which decision-making. Equivalence and Stooge Strategies. in Zero-Sum Games Equivalence and Stooge Strategies in Zero-Sum Games JOHN FOX MELVIN GUYER Mental Health Research Institute University of Michigan Classes of two-person zero-sum games termed "equivalent games" are defined.

More information

Rational Choice Theory I: The Foundations of the Theory

Rational Choice Theory I: The Foundations of the Theory Rational Choice Theory I: The Foundations of the Theory Benjamin Ferguson Administrative Keep in mind that your second papers are due this coming Friday at midnight. They should be emailed to me, roughly

More information

Comparative Ignorance and the Ellsberg Paradox

Comparative Ignorance and the Ellsberg Paradox The Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 22:2; 129 139, 2001 2001 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Manufactured in The Netherlands. Comparative Ignorance and the Ellsberg Paradox CLARE CHUA CHOW National University

More information

Choice set options affect the valuation of risky prospects

Choice set options affect the valuation of risky prospects Choice set options affect the valuation of risky prospects Stian Reimers (stian.reimers@warwick.ac.uk) Neil Stewart (neil.stewart@warwick.ac.uk) Nick Chater (nick.chater@warwick.ac.uk) Department of Psychology,

More information

Answers to Midterm Exam

Answers to Midterm Exam Answers to Midterm Exam Econ 159a/MGT522a Ben Polak Fall 2007 The answers below are more complete than required to get the points. In general, more concise explanations are better. Question 1. [15 total

More information

Gamble Evaluation and Evoked Reference Sets: Why Adding a Small Loss to a Gamble Increases Its Attractiveness. Draft of August 20, 2016

Gamble Evaluation and Evoked Reference Sets: Why Adding a Small Loss to a Gamble Increases Its Attractiveness. Draft of August 20, 2016 Evoked Reference Sets -- 1 Gamble Evaluation and Evoked Reference Sets: Why Adding a Small Loss to a Gamble Increases Its Attractiveness Craig R. M. McKenzie UC San Diego Shlomi Sher Pomona College Draft

More information

Behavioral Game Theory

Behavioral Game Theory School of Computer Science, McGill University March 4, 2011 1 2 3 4 5 Outline Nash equilibria One-shot games 1 2 3 4 5 I Nash equilibria One-shot games Definition: A study of actual individual s behaviors

More information

Towards a Justification the Principle of Coordination

Towards a Justification the Principle of Coordination TI 2000-017/1 Tinbergen Institute Discussion Paper Towards a Justification the Principle of Coordination Maarten C.W. Janssen Tinbergen Institute The Tinbergen Institute is the institute for economic research

More information

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send to:

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send  to: COPYRIGHT NOTICE: Ariel Rubinstein: Lecture Notes in Microeconomic Theory is published by Princeton University Press and copyrighted, c 2006, by Princeton University Press. All rights reserved. No part

More information

HOT VS. COLD: SEQUENTIAL RESPONSES AND PREFERENCE STABILITY IN EXPERIMENTAL GAMES * August 1998

HOT VS. COLD: SEQUENTIAL RESPONSES AND PREFERENCE STABILITY IN EXPERIMENTAL GAMES * August 1998 HOT VS. COLD: SEQUENTIAL RESPONSES AND PREFERENCE STABILITY IN EXPERIMENTAL GAMES * August 1998 Jordi Brandts Instituto de Análisis Económico (CSIC) Barcelona and University of California Berkeley (jbrandts@econ.berkeley.edu)

More information

7 Action. 7.1 Choice. Todd Davies, Decision Behavior: Theory and Evidence (Spring 2010) Version: June 4, 2010, 2:40 pm

7 Action. 7.1 Choice. Todd Davies, Decision Behavior: Theory and Evidence (Spring 2010) Version: June 4, 2010, 2:40 pm 7 Action Todd Davies, Decision Behavior: Theory and Evidence (Spring 2010) We can now apply beliefs, preferences, and confidence to choices between different possible actions or options. 7.1 Choice DEFINITION

More information

It is Whether You Win or Lose: The Importance of the Overall Probabilities of Winning or Losing in Risky Choice

It is Whether You Win or Lose: The Importance of the Overall Probabilities of Winning or Losing in Risky Choice The Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 30:1; 5 19, 2005 c 2005 Springer Science + Business Media, Inc. Manufactured in The Netherlands. It is Whether You Win or Lose: The Importance of the Overall Probabilities

More information

The effect of decision frame and decision justification on risky choice

The effect of decision frame and decision justification on risky choice Japanese Psychological Research 1993, Vol.35, No.1, 36-40 Short Report The effect of decision frame and decision justification on risky choice KAZUHISA TAKEMURA1 Institute of Socio-Economic Planning, University

More information

Veronika Grimm, Friederike Mengel. Let me sleep on it: Delay reduces rejection rates in Ultimatum Games RM/10/017

Veronika Grimm, Friederike Mengel. Let me sleep on it: Delay reduces rejection rates in Ultimatum Games RM/10/017 Veronika Grimm, Friederike Mengel Let me sleep on it: Delay reduces rejection rates in Ultimatum Games RM/10/017 Let me sleep on it: Delay reduces rejection rates in Ultimatum Games Veronika Grimm Friederike

More information

Risky Choice Decisions from a Tri-Reference Point Perspective

Risky Choice Decisions from a Tri-Reference Point Perspective Academic Leadership Journal in Student Research Volume 4 Spring 2016 Article 4 2016 Risky Choice Decisions from a Tri-Reference Point Perspective Kevin L. Kenney Fort Hays State University Follow this

More information

The Disjunction Effect and Reason-Based Choice in Games

The Disjunction Effect and Reason-Based Choice in Games Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes Vol. 80, No. 2, November, pp. 118 133, 1999 Article ID obhd.1999.2846, available online at http://www.idealibrary.com on The Disjunction Effect and

More information

An Experiment to Evaluate Bayesian Learning of Nash Equilibrium Play

An Experiment to Evaluate Bayesian Learning of Nash Equilibrium Play . An Experiment to Evaluate Bayesian Learning of Nash Equilibrium Play James C. Cox 1, Jason Shachat 2, and Mark Walker 1 1. Department of Economics, University of Arizona 2. Department of Economics, University

More information

Comments on Plott and on Kahneman, Knetsch, and Thaler

Comments on Plott and on Kahneman, Knetsch, and Thaler R. Duncan Luce Harvard Universio Comments on Plott and on Kahneman, Knetsch, and Thaler Commenting on papers by top researchers (Kahneman, Knetsch, and Thaler, in this issue; and Plott, in this issue)

More information

On the diversity principle and local falsifiability

On the diversity principle and local falsifiability On the diversity principle and local falsifiability Uriel Feige October 22, 2012 1 Introduction This manuscript concerns the methodology of evaluating one particular aspect of TCS (theoretical computer

More information

Lecture 2: Learning and Equilibrium Extensive-Form Games

Lecture 2: Learning and Equilibrium Extensive-Form Games Lecture 2: Learning and Equilibrium Extensive-Form Games III. Nash Equilibrium in Extensive Form Games IV. Self-Confirming Equilibrium and Passive Learning V. Learning Off-path Play D. Fudenberg Marshall

More information

PREFERENCE REVERSAL: AN EXPERIMENTAL INVESTIGATION OF ECONOMIC AND PSYCHOLOGICAL HYPOTHESES*

PREFERENCE REVERSAL: AN EXPERIMENTAL INVESTIGATION OF ECONOMIC AND PSYCHOLOGICAL HYPOTHESES* PREFERENCE REVERSAL: AN EXPERIMENTAL INVESTIGATION OF ECONOMIC AND PSYCHOLOGICAL HYPOTHESES* by Robin Cubitt** Alistair Munro** Chris Starmer*** * Research for this paper was funded by the Economic and

More information

Introduction to Behavioral Economics Like the subject matter of behavioral economics, this course is divided into two parts:

Introduction to Behavioral Economics Like the subject matter of behavioral economics, this course is divided into two parts: Economics 142: Behavioral Economics Spring 2008 Vincent Crawford (with very large debts to Colin Camerer of Caltech, David Laibson of Harvard, and especially Botond Koszegi and Matthew Rabin of UC Berkeley)

More information

Irrationality in Game Theory

Irrationality in Game Theory Irrationality in Game Theory Yamin Htun Dec 9, 2005 Abstract The concepts in game theory have been evolving in such a way that existing theories are recasted to apply to problems that previously appeared

More information

Supporting Information

Supporting Information Supporting Information Burton-Chellew and West 10.1073/pnas.1210960110 SI Results Fig. S4 A and B shows the percentage of free riders and cooperators over time for each treatment. Although Fig. S4A shows

More information

The Role of Modeling and Feedback in. Task Performance and the Development of Self-Efficacy. Skidmore College

The Role of Modeling and Feedback in. Task Performance and the Development of Self-Efficacy. Skidmore College Self-Efficacy 1 Running Head: THE DEVELOPMENT OF SELF-EFFICACY The Role of Modeling and Feedback in Task Performance and the Development of Self-Efficacy Skidmore College Self-Efficacy 2 Abstract Participants

More information

HYPOTHETICAL AND REAL INCENTIVES IN THE ULTIMATUM GAME AND ANDREONI S PUBLIC GOODS GAME: AN EXPERIMENTAL STUDY

HYPOTHETICAL AND REAL INCENTIVES IN THE ULTIMATUM GAME AND ANDREONI S PUBLIC GOODS GAME: AN EXPERIMENTAL STUDY HYPOTHETICAL AND REAL INCENTIVES IN THE ULTIMATUM GAME AND ANDREONI S PUBLIC GOODS GAME: INTRODUCTION AN EXPERIMENTAL STUDY Mark T. Gillis West Virginia University and Paul L. Hettler, Ph.D. California

More information

So You Want to do a Survey?

So You Want to do a Survey? Institute of Nuclear Power Operations So You Want to do a Survey? G. Kenneth Koves Ph.D. NAECP Conference, Austin TX 2015 September 29 1 Who am I? Ph.D. in Industrial/Organizational Psychology from Georgia

More information

What Solution-Focused Coaches Do: An Empirical Test of an Operationalization of Solution-Focused Coach Behaviors

What Solution-Focused Coaches Do: An Empirical Test of an Operationalization of Solution-Focused Coach Behaviors www.solutionfocusedchange.com February, 2012 What Solution-Focused Coaches Do: An Empirical Test of an Operationalization of Solution-Focused Coach Behaviors Coert F. Visser In an attempt to operationalize

More information

Thoughts on Social Design

Thoughts on Social Design 577 Center for Mathematical Economics Working Papers September 2017 Thoughts on Social Design Walter Trockel and Claus-Jochen Haake Center for Mathematical Economics(IMW) Bielefeld University Universitätsstraße

More information

Team Reasoning and a Measure of Mutual Advantage in Games

Team Reasoning and a Measure of Mutual Advantage in Games Team Reasoning and a Measure of Mutual Advantage in Games Jurgis Karpus Mantas Radzvilas August 2016 Abstract The game theoretic notion of best-response reasoning is sometimes criticized when its application

More information

The Effect of Guessing on Item Reliability

The Effect of Guessing on Item Reliability The Effect of Guessing on Item Reliability under Answer-Until-Correct Scoring Michael Kane National League for Nursing, Inc. James Moloney State University of New York at Brockport The answer-until-correct

More information

Paradoxes and Violations of Normative Decision Theory. Jay Simon Defense Resources Management Institute, Naval Postgraduate School

Paradoxes and Violations of Normative Decision Theory. Jay Simon Defense Resources Management Institute, Naval Postgraduate School Paradoxes and Violations of Normative Decision Theory Jay Simon Defense Resources Management Institute, Naval Postgraduate School Yitong Wang University of California, Irvine L. Robin Keller University

More information

COOPERATION 1. How Economic Rewards Affect Cooperation Reconsidered. Dan R. Schley and John H. Kagel. The Ohio State University

COOPERATION 1. How Economic Rewards Affect Cooperation Reconsidered. Dan R. Schley and John H. Kagel. The Ohio State University COOPERATION 1 Running Head: COOPERATION How Economic Rewards Affect Cooperation Reconsidered Dan R. Schley and John H. Kagel The Ohio State University In Preparation Do Not Cite Address correspondence

More information

Effect of Choice Set on Valuation of Risky Prospects

Effect of Choice Set on Valuation of Risky Prospects Effect of Choice Set on Valuation of Risky Prospects Neil Stewart (neil.stewart@warwick.ac.uk) Nick Chater (nick.chater@warwick.ac.uk) Henry P. Stott (hstott@owc.com) Department of Psychology, University

More information

' ( j _ A COMPARISON OF GAME THEORY AND LEARNING THEORY HERBERT A. SIMON!. _ CARNEGIE INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY

' ( j _ A COMPARISON OF GAME THEORY AND LEARNING THEORY HERBERT A. SIMON!. _ CARNEGIE INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY f ' ( 21, MO. 8 SBFFEMBKB, 1056 j _ A COMPARISON OF GAME THEORY AND LEARNING THEORY HERBERT A. SIMON!. _ CARNEGIE INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY.; ' It is shown that Estes'formula for the asymptotic behavior

More information

Limitations of Additive Conjoint Scaling Procedures: Detecting Nonadditivity When Additivity Is Known to Be Violated

Limitations of Additive Conjoint Scaling Procedures: Detecting Nonadditivity When Additivity Is Known to Be Violated _ -- ~---- ~-- ~-- - -- - ----- Limitations of Additive Conjoint Scaling Procedures: Detecting Nonadditivity When Additivity Is Known to Be Violated Thomas E. Nygren Ohio State University Two sets of three-outcome

More information

Recognizing Ambiguity

Recognizing Ambiguity Recognizing Ambiguity How Lack of Information Scares Us Mark Clements Columbia University I. Abstract In this paper, I will examine two different approaches to an experimental decision problem posed by

More information

Online Appendix A. A1 Ability

Online Appendix A. A1 Ability Online Appendix A A1 Ability To exclude the possibility of a gender difference in ability in our sample, we conducted a betweenparticipants test in which we measured ability by asking participants to engage

More information

On the Evolution of Choice Principles

On the Evolution of Choice Principles On the Evolution of Choice Principles Michael Franke 1 and Paolo Galeazzi 2 1 Department of Linguistics, University of Tübingen 2 Institute for Logic, Language and Computation, Universiteit van Amsterdam

More information

The Common Priors Assumption: A comment on Bargaining and the Nature of War

The Common Priors Assumption: A comment on Bargaining and the Nature of War The Common Priors Assumption: A comment on Bargaining and the Nature of War Mark Fey Kristopher W. Ramsay June 10, 2005 Abstract In a recent article in the JCR, Smith and Stam (2004) call into question

More information

Sawtooth Software. The Number of Levels Effect in Conjoint: Where Does It Come From and Can It Be Eliminated? RESEARCH PAPER SERIES

Sawtooth Software. The Number of Levels Effect in Conjoint: Where Does It Come From and Can It Be Eliminated? RESEARCH PAPER SERIES Sawtooth Software RESEARCH PAPER SERIES The Number of Levels Effect in Conjoint: Where Does It Come From and Can It Be Eliminated? Dick Wittink, Yale University Joel Huber, Duke University Peter Zandan,

More information

Decisions based on verbal probabilities: Decision bias or decision by belief sampling?

Decisions based on verbal probabilities: Decision bias or decision by belief sampling? Decisions based on verbal probabilities: Decision bias or decision by belief sampling? Hidehito Honda (hitohonda.02@gmail.com) Graduate School of Arts and Sciences, The University of Tokyo 3-8-1, Komaba,

More information

Games With Incomplete Information: Bayesian Nash Equilibrium

Games With Incomplete Information: Bayesian Nash Equilibrium Games With Incomplete Information: Bayesian Nash Equilibrium Carlos Hurtado Department of Economics University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign hrtdmrt2@illinois.edu June 29th, 2016 C. Hurtado (UIUC - Economics)

More information

Handout on Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium

Handout on Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium Handout on Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium Fudong Zhang April 19, 2013 Understanding the concept Motivation In general, the Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium (PBE) is the concept we are using when solving dynamic

More information

Network Architecture, Salience and Coordination

Network Architecture, Salience and Coordination Network Architecture, Salience and Coordination Syngjoo Choi, Douglas Gale, Shachar Kariv, and Thomas Palfrey January 5, 2011 Abstract This paper reports the results of an experimental investigation of

More information

SHSU ECONOMICS WORKING PAPER

SHSU ECONOMICS WORKING PAPER Sam Houston State University Department of Economics and International Business Working Paper Series Choice, internal consistency, and rationality Aditi Bhattacharyya Sam Houston State University Prasanta

More information

Unlike standard economics, BE is (most of the time) not based on rst principles, but on observed behavior of real people.

Unlike standard economics, BE is (most of the time) not based on rst principles, but on observed behavior of real people. Behavioral Economics Lecture 1. Introduction and the Methodology of Experimental Economics 1. Introduction Characteristica of Behavioral Economics (BE) Unlike standard economics, BE is (most of the time)

More information

Ambiguous Data Result in Ambiguous Conclusions: A Reply to Charles T. Tart

Ambiguous Data Result in Ambiguous Conclusions: A Reply to Charles T. Tart Other Methodology Articles Ambiguous Data Result in Ambiguous Conclusions: A Reply to Charles T. Tart J. E. KENNEDY 1 (Original publication and copyright: Journal of the American Society for Psychical

More information

The effects of payout and probability magnitude on the Allais paradox

The effects of payout and probability magnitude on the Allais paradox Memory & Cognition 2008, 36 (5), 1013-1023 doi: 10.3758/MC.36.5.1013 The effects of payout and probability magnitude on the Allais paradox BETHANY Y J. WEBER Rutgers University, New Brunswick, New Jersey

More information

Contingent Weighing of Past and Future Decision Outcomes

Contingent Weighing of Past and Future Decision Outcomes No. 5:31,1 Contingent Weighing of Past and Future Decision Outcomes Ásgeir Juliusson, Niklas Karlsson, and Tommy Gärling Department of Psychology Göteborg University Juliusson, Á, Karlsson, N., and Gärling,

More information

Cooperation in Prisoner s Dilemma Game: Influence of Social Relations

Cooperation in Prisoner s Dilemma Game: Influence of Social Relations Cooperation in Prisoner s Dilemma Game: Influence of Social Relations Maurice Grinberg (mgrinberg@nbu.bg) Evgenia Hristova (ehristova@cogs.nbu.bg) Milena Borisova (borisova_milena@abv.bg) Department of

More information

ULTIMATUM GAME. An Empirical Evidence. Presented By: SHAHID RAZZAQUE

ULTIMATUM GAME. An Empirical Evidence. Presented By: SHAHID RAZZAQUE 1 ULTIMATUM GAME An Empirical Evidence Presented By: SHAHID RAZZAQUE 2 Difference Between Self-Interest, Preference & Social Preference Preference refers to the choices people make & particularly to tradeoffs

More information

Personal involvement, task complexity, and the decision making process: An information search analysis'

Personal involvement, task complexity, and the decision making process: An information search analysis' Japanese Psychological Rescarch 1994, Vol.36, No. 1. 41-48 Special lssue: Decision Making Personal involvement, task complexity, and the decision making process: An information search analysis' KAZUHISA

More information

1 The conceptual underpinnings of statistical power

1 The conceptual underpinnings of statistical power 1 The conceptual underpinnings of statistical power The importance of statistical power As currently practiced in the social and health sciences, inferential statistics rest solidly upon two pillars: statistical

More information

UNIT 5 - Association Causation, Effect Modification and Validity

UNIT 5 - Association Causation, Effect Modification and Validity 5 UNIT 5 - Association Causation, Effect Modification and Validity Introduction In Unit 1 we introduced the concept of causality in epidemiology and presented different ways in which causes can be understood

More information

Tilburg University. Burning money and (pseudo) first-mover advantages Huck, S.; Müller, Wieland. Published in: Games and Economic Behavior

Tilburg University. Burning money and (pseudo) first-mover advantages Huck, S.; Müller, Wieland. Published in: Games and Economic Behavior Tilburg University Burning money and (pseudo) first-mover advantages Huck, S.; Müller, Wieland Published in: Games and Economic Behavior Document version: Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record

More information

Information Acquisition in the Iterated Prisoner s Dilemma Game: An Eye-Tracking Study

Information Acquisition in the Iterated Prisoner s Dilemma Game: An Eye-Tracking Study Information Acquisition in the Iterated Prisoner s Dilemma Game: An Eye-Tracking Study Evgenia Hristova (ehristova@cogs.nbu.bg ) Central and Eastern European Center for Cognitive Science, New Bulgarian

More information

Reinforcement Learning : Theory and Practice - Programming Assignment 1

Reinforcement Learning : Theory and Practice - Programming Assignment 1 Reinforcement Learning : Theory and Practice - Programming Assignment 1 August 2016 Background It is well known in Game Theory that the game of Rock, Paper, Scissors has one and only one Nash Equilibrium.

More information

Cooperation in a Prisoners Dilemma with Losses. Results from an Experimental Study.

Cooperation in a Prisoners Dilemma with Losses. Results from an Experimental Study. Cooperation in a Prisoners Dilemma with Losses. Results from an Experimental Study. Roger Berger Institute for Sociology, University of Leipzig and SNF Venice International University 2006 Rational Choice

More information

Nash Equilibrium and Dynamics

Nash Equilibrium and Dynamics Nash Equilibrium and Dynamics Sergiu Hart September 12, 2008 John F. Nash, Jr., submitted his Ph.D. dissertation entitled Non-Cooperative Games to Princeton University in 1950. Read it 58 years later,

More information

Clicker quiz: Should the cocaine trade be legalized? (either answer will tell us if you are here or not) 1. yes 2. no

Clicker quiz: Should the cocaine trade be legalized? (either answer will tell us if you are here or not) 1. yes 2. no Clicker quiz: Should the cocaine trade be legalized? (either answer will tell us if you are here or not) 1. yes 2. no Economic Liberalism Summary: Assumptions: self-interest, rationality, individual freedom

More information

Behavioral Game Theory

Behavioral Game Theory Outline (September 3, 2007) Outline (September 3, 2007) Introduction Outline (September 3, 2007) Introduction Examples of laboratory experiments Outline (September 3, 2007) Introduction Examples of laboratory

More information

Choose an approach for your research problem

Choose an approach for your research problem Choose an approach for your research problem This course is about doing empirical research with experiments, so your general approach to research has already been chosen by your professor. It s important

More information

Value Function Elicitation: A Comment on Craig R. Fox & Amos Tversky, "A Belief-Based Account of Decision under Uncertainty"

Value Function Elicitation: A Comment on Craig R. Fox & Amos Tversky, A Belief-Based Account of Decision under Uncertainty Value Function Elicitation: A Comment on Craig R. Fox & Amos Tversky, "A Belief-Based Account of Decision under Uncertainty" Craig R. Fox Peter P. Wakker Fuqua School of Business, Duke University Box 90120,

More information

DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS AND FINANCE COLLEGE OF BUSINESS AND ECONOMICS UNIVERSITY OF CANTERBURY CHRISTCHURCH, NEW ZEALAND

DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS AND FINANCE COLLEGE OF BUSINESS AND ECONOMICS UNIVERSITY OF CANTERBURY CHRISTCHURCH, NEW ZEALAND DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS AND FINANCE COLLEGE OF BUSINESS AND ECONOMICS UNIVERSITY OF CANTERBURY CHRISTCHURCH, NEW ZEALAND Comment on Promises and Partnership Cary Deck, Maroš Servátka, and Steven Tucker

More information

CHAPTER VI RESEARCH METHODOLOGY

CHAPTER VI RESEARCH METHODOLOGY CHAPTER VI RESEARCH METHODOLOGY 6.1 Research Design Research is an organized, systematic, data based, critical, objective, scientific inquiry or investigation into a specific problem, undertaken with the

More information

Teorie prospektu a teorie očekávaného užitku: Aplikace na podmínky České republiky

Teorie prospektu a teorie očekávaného užitku: Aplikace na podmínky České republiky Teorie prospektu a teorie očekávaného užitku: Aplikace na podmínky České republiky Prospect Theory and Expect Utility Theory: Application to Conditions of the Czech Republic Kateřina Fojtů, Stanislav Škapa

More information

Multiple Equilibria in Tullock Contests *

Multiple Equilibria in Tullock Contests * Multiple Equilibria in Tullock Contests * Subhasish M. Chowdhury a and Roman M. Sheremeta b a School of Economics, Centre for Competition Policy, and Centre for Behavioral and Experimental Social Science,

More information

Risk attitude in decision making: A clash of three approaches

Risk attitude in decision making: A clash of three approaches Risk attitude in decision making: A clash of three approaches Eldad Yechiam (yeldad@tx.technion.ac.il) Faculty of Industrial Engineering and Management, Technion Israel Institute of Technology Haifa, 32000

More information

A POPPERIAN TEST OF LEVEL-K THEORY

A POPPERIAN TEST OF LEVEL-K THEORY CBESS Discussion Paper 12-06 A POPPERIAN TEST OF LEVEL-K THEORY By Shaun Hargreaves Heap*, David Rojo Arjona** and Robert Sugden* * School of Economics, University of East Anglia **Economic Science Institute,

More information

Effects of causal relatedness and uncertainty on integration of outcomes of concurrent decisions

Effects of causal relatedness and uncertainty on integration of outcomes of concurrent decisions Available online at www.sciencedirect.com ScienceDirect Procedia - Social and Behavioral Sciences 190 ( 2015 ) 113 119 2nd GLOBAL CONFERENCE on PSYCHOLOGY RESEARCHES, 28-29, November 2014 Effects of causal

More information

The Distracted Teenage Brain Scientists discover that teens are easily distracted by behaviors that were once but are no longer rewarding

The Distracted Teenage Brain Scientists discover that teens are easily distracted by behaviors that were once but are no longer rewarding Name: Class: The Distracted Teenage Brain Scientists discover that teens are easily distracted by behaviors that were once but are no longer rewarding By Alison Pearce Stevens From Societyforscience.Org

More information

Experimental Testing of Intrinsic Preferences for NonInstrumental Information

Experimental Testing of Intrinsic Preferences for NonInstrumental Information Experimental Testing of Intrinsic Preferences for NonInstrumental Information By Kfir Eliaz and Andrew Schotter* The classical model of decision making under uncertainty assumes that decision makers care

More information

Sleeping Beauty is told the following:

Sleeping Beauty is told the following: Sleeping beauty Sleeping Beauty is told the following: You are going to sleep for three days, during which time you will be woken up either once Now suppose that you are sleeping beauty, and you are woken

More information

The Logic of Data Analysis Using Statistical Techniques M. E. Swisher, 2016

The Logic of Data Analysis Using Statistical Techniques M. E. Swisher, 2016 The Logic of Data Analysis Using Statistical Techniques M. E. Swisher, 2016 This course does not cover how to perform statistical tests on SPSS or any other computer program. There are several courses

More information

Evolving Strategic Behaviors through Competitive Interaction in the Large

Evolving Strategic Behaviors through Competitive Interaction in the Large Evolving Strategic Behaviors through Competitive Interaction in the Large Kimitaka Uno & Akira Namatame Dept. of Computer Science National Defense Academy Yokosuka, 239-8686, JAPAN E-mail: {kimi, nama}@cc.nda.ac.jp

More information

This self-archived version is provided for scholarly purposes only. The correct reference for this article is as follows:

This self-archived version is provided for scholarly purposes only. The correct reference for this article is as follows: SOCIAL AFFILIATION CUES PRIME HELP-SEEKING INTENTIONS 1 This self-archived version is provided for scholarly purposes only. The correct reference for this article is as follows: Rubin, M. (2011). Social

More information

Fairness and Reciprocity in the Hawk-Dove game

Fairness and Reciprocity in the Hawk-Dove game Fairness and Reciprocity in the Hawk-Dove game Tibor Neugebauer*, Anders Poulsen**, and Arthur Schram*** Abstract We study fairness and reciprocity in a Hawk-Dove game. This allows us to test various models

More information

Nash Equilibrium and Dynamics

Nash Equilibrium and Dynamics Nash Equilibrium and Dynamics Sergiu Hart June 2008 Conference in Honor of John Nash s 80th Birthday Opening Panel SERGIU HART c 2008 p. 1 NASH EQUILIBRIUM AND DYNAMICS Sergiu Hart Center for the Study

More information

THE USE OF MULTIVARIATE ANALYSIS IN DEVELOPMENT THEORY: A CRITIQUE OF THE APPROACH ADOPTED BY ADELMAN AND MORRIS A. C. RAYNER

THE USE OF MULTIVARIATE ANALYSIS IN DEVELOPMENT THEORY: A CRITIQUE OF THE APPROACH ADOPTED BY ADELMAN AND MORRIS A. C. RAYNER THE USE OF MULTIVARIATE ANALYSIS IN DEVELOPMENT THEORY: A CRITIQUE OF THE APPROACH ADOPTED BY ADELMAN AND MORRIS A. C. RAYNER Introduction, 639. Factor analysis, 639. Discriminant analysis, 644. INTRODUCTION

More information

WILL HOMO ECONOMICUS SURVIVE?

WILL HOMO ECONOMICUS SURVIVE? WILL HOMO ECONOMICUS SURVIVE? PHILIPP DOERRENBERG Erasmus Student In this essay, Philipp Doerrenberg highlights recent experimental work that has proven the shaky foundations of the concept of the rational,

More information

Examples of Feedback Comments: How to use them to improve your report writing. Example 1: Compare and contrast

Examples of Feedback Comments: How to use them to improve your report writing. Example 1: Compare and contrast Examples of Feedback Comments: How to use them to improve your report writing This document contains 4 examples of writing and feedback comments from Level 2A lab reports, and 4 steps to help you apply

More information

Ambiguity Aversion in Game Theory: Experimental Evidence

Ambiguity Aversion in Game Theory: Experimental Evidence Ambiguity Aversion in Game Theory: Experimental Evidence Evan Calford August 6, 2015 PRELIMINARY Comments welcome. Abstract This paper studies games with ambiguity averse agents, focusing on the relationship

More information

Size of Ellsberg Urn. Emel Filiz-Ozbay, Huseyin Gulen, Yusufcan Masatlioglu, Erkut Ozbay. University of Maryland

Size of Ellsberg Urn. Emel Filiz-Ozbay, Huseyin Gulen, Yusufcan Masatlioglu, Erkut Ozbay. University of Maryland Size of Ellsberg Urn Emel Filiz-Ozbay, Huseyin Gulen, Yusufcan Masatlioglu, Erkut Ozbay University of Maryland behavior fundamentally changes when the uncertainty is explicitly specified and vaguely described

More information

SUPPLEMENTARY INFORMATION

SUPPLEMENTARY INFORMATION Supplementary Statistics and Results This file contains supplementary statistical information and a discussion of the interpretation of the belief effect on the basis of additional data. We also present

More information

Belief Formation in a Signalling Game without Common Prior: An Experiment

Belief Formation in a Signalling Game without Common Prior: An Experiment Belief Formation in a Signalling Game without Common Prior: An Experiment Alex Possajennikov University of Nottingham February 2012 Abstract Using belief elicitation, the paper investigates the formation

More information

Binary Diagnostic Tests Paired Samples

Binary Diagnostic Tests Paired Samples Chapter 536 Binary Diagnostic Tests Paired Samples Introduction An important task in diagnostic medicine is to measure the accuracy of two diagnostic tests. This can be done by comparing summary measures

More information

Equilibrium Cooperation in Three-Person, Choice-of-Partner Games

Equilibrium Cooperation in Three-Person, Choice-of-Partner Games Equilibrium Cooperation in Three-Person, Choice-of-Partner Games Douglas D. Davis and Charles A. Holt * Abstract The experiment involves three-person games in which one player can choose which of two others

More information