Different developmental patterns of simple deductive and probabilistic inferential reasoning

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Different developmental patterns of simple deductive and probabilistic inferential reasoning"

Transcription

1 Memory & Cognition 2008, 36 (6), doi: /MC Different developmental patterns of simple deductive and probabilistic inferential reasoning Henry Markovits Université du Québec à Montréal, Montréal, Québec, Canada and Valerie Thompson University of Saskatchewan, Saskatoon, Saskatchewan, Canada In three studies, we examined simple counterexample-based and probabilistic reasoning in children 6, 7, and 9 years of age. In the first study, participants were asked to make conditional (if then) inferences under both categorical (certain or uncertain) and probabilistic instructions. Results showed that 6-year-olds respond to both forms of inference in similar ways, but whereas probabilistic conditional inferences showed little development over this period, categorical inferences clearly improved between 6 and 7 years of age. An analysis of the children s justifications indicated that performance under categorical instructions was strongly related to counterexample generation at all ages, whereas this was true only for the younger children for inferences under probabilistic instructions. These findings were replicated in a second study, using problems that referred to concrete stimuli with varying probabilities of inference. A third study tested the hypothesis that children confused probability judgments with judgments of confidence and demonstrated a clear dissociation between these two constructs. Overall, these results show that children are capable of accurate conditional inferences under probabilistic instructions at a very early age and that the differentiation between categorical and probabilistic conditional reasoning is clear by at least 9 years of age. These results are globally consistent with dual-process theories but suggest some difficulties for the way that the analytic heuristic distinction underlying these theories has been conceptualized. The capacity to make deductive inferences from premises that are assumed to be true is one of the more important abilities characterizing the human cognitive system. A great deal of research has examined the kinds of inferences that are made under standard deductive instructions, which require a dichotomous evaluation of the certainty of a putative conclusion. Studies in which both children and adults have been looked at (e.g., Cummins, 1995; Janveau-Brennan & Markovits, 1999; Thompson, 1994, 2000) have consistently shown a great deal of variation, due to both content and context, in this kind of reasoning. At least two kinds of processes have been posited to explain the observed variation. The first relies on explicit use of counterexamples to judge conclusions as certain or not (Johnson-Laird & Byrne, 1991; Markovits & Barrouillet, 2002; Verschueren, Schaeken, & d Ydewalle, 2005). Such models assume that retrieval and use of at least one potential counterexample are sufficient to deny a conclusion. The second entails a more probabilistic approach (e.g., Evans, Handley, & Over, 2003; Oaksford, Chater, & Larkin, 2000), which requires an evaluation of the probability of a putative conclusion. This involves some process by which the relative frequency of a potential conclusion is compared with the relative frequency of potential counterexamples. The goal of the present article is to examine the development of these two types of inferential reasoning in young children. Our basic hypothesis is that inferences using judgments of probability emerge early in childhood; explicit inferential reasoning based on explicit use of counterexamples, however, is posited to develop later. Studies with adults support the hypothesis that when inferences are made on the basis of conditional statements that are familiar to reasoners, counterexample-based inferential reasoning is more demanding than inferential reasoning based on the assessment of probabilities. Verschueren et al. (2005) recently suggested that there are two distinct forms of inferential reasoning, corresponding to two ways of determining whether a putative conclusion is valid. The first relies on likelihood judgments about conclusion plausibility that are fairly intuitive and do not require many cognitive resources. Thus, if the premises suggest that a conclusion is highly likely when compared with potential alternatives that are consistent with the premises (i.e., counter examples), this conclusion will be judged to be valid. The second form of reasoning requires explicit use of counterexamples in order to determine whether a conclusion is valid or not. A conclusion will be judged to be valid if a reasoner cannot generate at least one counterexample that is consistent with the premises. Verschueren et al. presented evidence that reasoners with higher working memory capacity show a greater de- H. Markovits, markovits.henry@uqam.ca Copyright 2008 Psychonomic Society, Inc. 1066

2 Deductive and Probabilistic Inference 1067 clearest index of developmental change in conditional reasoning is thus the increasing tendency to reject the invited inferences in the AC and DA forms. In the following study, we will specifically focus on the AC inference. Although the same general patterns are found for the DA inference, the use of a negation in the formulation of this inference makes its use in young children more difficult, particularly in the present context, and we have not examined it here. A great many empirical studies have examined this kind of reasoning and have made possible some clear understanding of the factors that influence the kinds of AC inferences that are made by both children and adults under standard deductive instructions. These studies have focused on the fact that reasoners apply background knowledge about the conditional relationship to the evaluation of inferences. Thompson (1994, 2000) suggested that the dimension most relevant to evaluating the AC and DA inferences is the extent to which the antecedent of the conditional is perceived to be a necessary condition for the consequent. Specifically, when reasoners believe that P must happen in order for Q to happen (e.g., if a figure has four sides, it is a square), correct responses to the AC and DA inferences are low; in contrast, when P is not believed to be a necessary condition for Q (e.g., if a figure has four sides, it is a polygon), the rate of correct responses is high. In fact, there is a great deal of evidence that when making an inference with concrete content, both children and adults may attempt to access their knowledge about the premises; the nature of the retrieved information affects the kind of inferences they will then make. Several studies have shown that the relative number of alternative antecedents that can be readily accessed for any given if then premise with familiar content will affect the kinds of inferences that are made to the AC (and DA) forms (Bucci, 1978; Cummins, 1995; Cummins, Lubart, Alksnis, & Rist, 1991; Janveau-Brennan & Markovits, 1999; Markovits & Vachon, 1990; Thompson, 1994, 2000). For example, take the following AC inference: If a brick is thrown at a window, then the window will break. A window is broken. Has a brick been thrown at the window? This inference will lead to a relatively high rate of rejecting the conclusion that a brick has been thrown at the window, since there are many ways of breaking a window other than throwing a brick at it. In comparison, the AC inference If a tree is cut down, then the tree will fall. A tree has fallen. Has the tree been cut down? will lead to a relatively low rate of rejecting the conclusion that the tree has been cut down, since there are few ways of making a tree fall other than cutting it down (Bucci, 1978; Cummins, 1995; Markovits & Vachon, 1990). Similarly, the strength of association between the consequent of the major premise (Q) and the most strongly associated alternative antecedent (Barrouillet, Markovits, & Quinn, 2002; Markovits, Fleury, Quinn, & Venet, 1998; Quinn & Markovits, 1998) also affects responses to the AC inference. That is, reasoners are less likely to draw the AC inference when there is a strongly associated, as opposed to a weakly associated, antecedent available. This idea is reinforced by studies that have shown a correlation between efficiency of information retrieval (as meagree of explicit counterexample use while making deductive judgments, whereas low working memory capacity reasoners tend to use likelihood judgments about conclusion plausibility. In other words, a deliberate, analytic strategy based on counterexample use, so that a single counterexample was explicitly considered sufficient to invalidate a conclusion, was associated with high working memory capacity, whereas reliance on a presumably more automatic, heuristic process that generated the likelihood of a conclusion was associated with low working memory capacity. The major goal of this study was to test the hypothesis that children also exhibit two separate modes of reasoning that parallel the ones observed in adults, in the context of conditional reasoning, and that these two modes of reasoning show different developmental trajectories. Specifically, the less-resource-demanding probabilistic form of reasoning is hypothesized to develop earlier than resource-intensive counterexample reasoning. Conditional reasoning is a cornerstone of thinking and is probably one of the most extensively studied forms of logical reasoning, in both the adult and the developmental literatures. Conditional reasoning involves making inferences on the basis of a given if then relation. Most studies of conditional reasoning have examined children s abilities to make inferences on the four basic argument forms. Modus ponens (MP) is the logical principle that involves reasoning with the premises P implies Q, P is true and leads to the logically correct conclusion Q is true. Modus tollens (MT) involves reasoning with the premises P implies Q, Q is false and leads to the logically correct conclusion P is false. These two are valid forms, since both of them lead to a single, logically necessary conclusion. Affirmation of the consequent (AC) involves reasoning with the premises P implies Q, Q is true. Denial of the antecedent (DA) involves reasoning with the premises P implies Q, P is false. For the latter forms, there is more than one conclusion that is logically consistent with the premises; we will subsequently refer to these as uncertain argument forms. In these cases, the logically correct response is to deny a putative conclusion. Developmental studies of conditional reasoning show some very clear patterns that can be summarized in the following way: Young children tend to make the MP and MT inferences very reliably when reasoning with familiar premises (Markovits, 2000; Markovits et al., 1996; but see Barrouillet & Lecas, 1999, for evidence that the MT inference is not made when reasoning with premises for which the relation between the terms is arbitrary), but there is a well-documented tendency for them to also accept the invited AC and DA inferences (e.g., in the case of the AC inference, reasoners will often claim that P implies Q, Q is true allows the conclusion that P is true). Developmental change is characterized mainly by a decrease in the rate of accepting the AC and DA inferences (e.g., Janveau- Brennan & Markovits, 1999; Markovits & Vachon, 1990; O Brien & Overton, 1980). There are some less clear-cut patterns that suggest possible developmental trends toward refusing the MP and MT inferences, at least in some cases (e.g., Janveau-Brennan & Markovits, 1999; O Brien & Overton, 1980; Rumain, Connell, & Braine, 1983), but these are inconsistent and more difficult to interpret. The

3 1068 Markovits and Thompson refer to these types of inferences as categorical, since they result in a binary response. However, a reasoner might also use a probabilistic approach to evaluating the inference. A probabilistic inference will require a reasoner to estimate what the probability would be that a rock was thrown at the window. This would require some evaluation of the relative frequency of windows being broken by rocks that is, the conditional probability that if a window is broken, a rock was thrown at it leading to reasoning of the sort, it s fairly likely that if the window is broken, a rock was thrown. Available evidence indicates that this generally involves a rapid judgment based on simple activation of things related to breaking windows and an intuitive estimation of the relative weights of rocks and other things. It is this form of judgment that is assumed to underlie current models of probabilistic reasoning, and frequent use of such a process is implied by the results of Verschueren et al. (2005). We will refer to this as probabilistic reasoning in the following. The dissociation between categorical inferences based on a search for, and the explicit representation of, counterexamples and probabilistic inferences that are based on a more intuitive assessment of likelihood is consistent with the broader outlines of dual-process theories (Verschueren et al., 2005). Although there are differences between various formulations (e.g., Evans, 2007; Evans & Over, 1996; Klaczynski, 2001; Stanovich & West, 2000), these theories agree that making inferences can be guided by very direct associative processes that exploit people s experience and knowledge of the world in order to allow them to make inferences rapidly and automatically. In contrast to this, a second, analytic system is postulated that requires conscious effort and an explicit use of information, such as that required for counterexample generation and use. The latter kind of processing may ultimately allow the making of inferences that are abstract and decontextualized; however, in the present study, we were more concerned with the development of the underlying processes. Common to these theories is the idea that associative processes are present at a very early age, whereas the more explicit, and working-memory-intensive processes develop later. In other words, if dual-process theories are true, young children should find it easier, when reasoning with familiar premises, to make probabilistic inferences, using some form of likelihood evaluation, than to make explicit categorical inferences based on counterexample generation and use. There are, in fact, some recent results that are consistent with the idea that cognitive development in adolescence can be understood by the interplay between an early-developing associative system and a later developing analytic system (e.g., Klaczynski, 2001; Kokis, Macpherson, Toplak, West, & Stanovich, 2002). More specifically, developmental studies in which children s conditional reasoning with familiar premises under standard deductive instructions has been looked at have suggested that children s ability to use an explicit counterexample to deny the AC inference is very limited at 6 or 7 years of age and undergoes rapid change subsequently (Janveau-Brennan & Markovits, 1999; Markovits, 2000). Although there are no known direct studies of probabilissured by the quantity and speed of retrieval of information from long-term memory) and responding to the AC (and DA) forms in both children (Janveau-Brennan & Markovits, 1999) and adults (Markovits & Quinn, 2002) and also have shown differential latencies for AC inferences made with premises of differing degrees of associative strength (Grosset, Barrouillet, & Markovits, 2005). Recent studies in which patterns of responses to other inferential forms have been looked at have come to similar conclusions (e.g., De Neys, Schaeken, & d Ydewalle, 2002). There are at least two types of processes that can explain these patterns. One entails a process of retrieval and the use of counterexamples, such that a single counterexample is sufficient to invalidate a putative conclusion. One recent instantiation of such a process was presented by Markovits and Barrouillet (2002), who proposed that if at least a single alternative antecedent is retrieved and can be incorporated into an explicit mental model of the premises, the AC (and DA) inferences will be denied. A second type of process involves a less cognitively demanding assessment of likelihood, as suggested by Verschueren et al. (2005) and by Thompson (2000). Although some forms of probabilistic reasoning certainly involve complex, working-memory-intensive processes, this hypothesis suggests that making probabilistic inferences on the basis of familiar conditional premises is often the result of a likelihood judgment that capitalizes on a reasoner s intuitive knowledge. Note that there are other models of probabilistic reasoning (e.g., Evans et al., 2003; Oaksford et al., 2000) that differ in their details but retain the same basic notion. Specifically, a conclusion will be evaluated as more or less valid if the likelihood that the conclusion is true, assuming the truth of some part of the premises (depending on the specific model), is high. This process is generally conceived of as a fairly effortless evaluation that relies on the associative structure of stored knowledge about the premises and the conclusion. In other words, when evaluating the likelihood of a conclusion, a reasoner can simply activate a network of consequences related to the premises, including potential counterexamples, and estimate the relative weights of the conclusion, as compared with the counterexamples. At this point, it is useful to examine this distinction in the context of a specific example. Consider the following premises: If a rock is thrown at a window, then the window will break. Suppose that a window is broken. Suppose that a reasoner is asked to judge the validity of the putative conclusion a rock was thrown at the window. According to Markovits and Barrouillet s (2002) model, counterexample-based reasoning involves two processes. First, the reasoner must retrieve one or more alternative antecedents that is, things that can break a window that are not rocks. Then the reasoner must add an explicit representation of this alternative to the initial representation of the major premise. If such a representation is indeed generated, the conclusion will be judged to be invalid. This corresponds to reasoning of the sort, it is not certain that a rock was thrown at the window, since maybe a storm broke the window. If such a representation is not generated, the conclusion will be judged to be valid. We will

4 Deductive and Probabilistic Inference 1069 tic conditional inferences, there is evidence that children as young as 6 years of age understand the basic notion of probabilistic uncertainty with familiar content (e.g., Acredolo, O Connor, Banks, & Horobin, 1989; Brainerd, 1981). In fact, even infants have basic probabilistic intuitions (Téglás, Girotto, Gonzalez, & Bonatti, 2007). A recent study by Girotto and Gonzalez (2008) has shown that children this young can also understand the more complex notion of posterior probability, which involves updating judgments in uncertain situations on the basis of new evidence, an ability that must be a key component in the making of probabilistic inferences. These results indicate that very young children (around 6 years of age) possess the kind of understanding of probabilities that is required to understand the task demands involved in making a probabilistic conditional inference. There is, however, no study that we know of that has directly tested the hypothesis that 6-year-old children can adequately make probabilistic conditional inferences and later develop inferential strategies based on the deliberate use of counterexamples. This was the purpose of the following studies. Study 1 In this first study, we decided to look specifically at the way that young children make conditional inferences with simple verbal propositions, corresponding to the MP and AC forms on two different tasks. The first used standard deductive instructions and requested categorical inferences (we will refer to these as categorical instructions). These instructions were chosen to promote use of counterexample-based reasoning. We hypothesized that younger children would show relatively more difficulty on this task than would older children and, conversely, that older children would be more likely to make explicit use of counterexamples than would younger children on this task. The second task asked children to assess the degree to which a putative conclusion is likely (these will be referred to as probabilistic instructions). This was designed to elicit probabilistic inferences. Under the hypothesis that probabilistic reasoning is relatively well developed in young children, when compared with counterexample-based categorical reasoning, we expected relatively little developmental change on the probabilistic task, as compared with developmental change with the categorical inferences. Finally, under the hypothesis that counterexample-based reasoning develops later than probabilistic reasoning, we should observe that younger children tend to treat the probabilistic and categorical problems similarly; however, as children grow older, they should differentiate more clearly between the two. To test these hypotheses, we examined the inferences that the children drew for MP and AC problems, and we also asked them to provide justifications for those inferences. There is very good evidence that young children s justifications are good indicators of the kinds of information that are used to make an inference (Janveau-Brennan & Markovits, 1999; Markovits, 2000). By asking for justifications in addition to inferential judgments, we could then examine patterns of variation in both categorical and probabilistic inferences as a function of information use. The specific premises used here were chosen to provide relatively easy access to potential alternative antecedents for children of the age examined (Markovits et al., 1998). We can then make some specific predictions about children s inferential performance. First, we know from developmental studies that even young children can respond correctly to the MP inference under standard deductive instructions with the kinds of plausible premises used in this study (Markovits, 2000; Markovits et al., 1996). Adults appear to reason similarly on MP with both standard deductive and probabilistic instructions, and there was no reason to suppose that probabilistic evaluation of MP inferences in children would be difficult. Thus, we predicted that children of all the age groups should accept the MP inference under both probabilistic and deductive instructions. It should be noted that when premises allow potential retrieval of disabling conditions, performance on the MP inference is more difficult (these are conditions that allow the antecedent to be true but suggest that the consequent may not be true e.g., if a rock is thrown at a window, the window will certainly break, unless the window is made of Plexiglas; see Cummins et al., 1991). Available evidence suggests that retrieval of disabling conditions during reasoning will lead to rejection of the MP inference (e.g., Cummins et al., 1991), unless the reasoner manages to inhibit these (De Neys, Schaeken, & d Ydewalle, 2005b; Markovits & Doyon, 2004). In the present context, we did not wish to examine the effects of disabling conditions and, thus, chose premises for which few disabling conditions were available. We thus expected that all the children in the present study would show high levels of acceptance of the MP inference under categorical instructions and high ratings of the MP inference under probabilistic instructions, irrespective of the underlying processes. In the case of the AC inference, however, probabilistic and categorical instructions should produce different patterns. Although younger children may not show a clear distinction between the forms of reasoning used with the two instructions, as reasoning by counterexample develops, the two forms should diverge. In particular, the reasoningby-counterexample model supposes that production of at least one alternative antecedent (of any kind) should be strongly correlated with rejection of the AC inference. In contrast, when probabilistic inference is made, the relation between alternatives and ratings of the likelihood of a putative conclusion is weaker (see Markovits & Handley, 2005, for evidence of this difference in adults). A simple example of this is a situation in which the alternative antecedent that is retrieved is one whose real probability of occurrence is low; in this situation, the likelihood of the invited conclusion will remain high. For instance, suppose that a reasoner is asked to evaluate the following AC inference: If an animal is a duck, then it has wings. An animal has wings. It is a duck. Suppose that Reasoner A retrieves the example of a sparrow, as an alternative counterexample, whereas Reasoner B does not do so. If these reasoners are given standard deductive instructions and are capable of reasoning by counterexample, Reasoner A would deny the invited conclusion it

5 1070 Markovits and Thompson Results We first examined the mean responses to inferences under the categorical and probabilistic instructions. Since an initial analysis showed that there were no order effects, subsequent analyses did not take this factor into consideration. We also compared AC performance with the car and hedgehog premises. No significant differences were found between these two AC inferences, under either catis a duck, and Reasoner B would accept this conclusion. If these two reasoners are given probabilistic instructions, they would have to evaluate the probability that something that has wings is a duck. Reasoner B would rate this as quite low, given general knowledge about things having wings. Reasoner A would add to general knowledge the specific example of a sparrow. However, this would not appreciably change A s initial evaluation, since the probability that something having wings is a duck is low even when sparrows are considered. Thus, we would predict that the relation between alternative antecedent use and inferential performance would be strong with categorical instructions and weak with probabilistic instructions, if the processes used to make these two forms of inference were clearly differentiated, as is the case with adults. In sum, we hypothesized that counterexample-based categorical reasoning develops later than probabilistic reasoning. Thus, we expected a stronger developmental trend in the tendency to reject AC inferences under categorical instructions than under probabilistic instructions. We expected older children to generate more counterexamples than would younger children. We expected the relation between counterexample generation and AC reasoning to be stronger under categorical instructions than under probabilistic instructions among the older children, but not among the younger children. Moreover, whereas older children should be better than younger ones at using counterexamples to make categorical inferences, this trend was not expected for probabilistic inferences. Method Participants. A total of 56 elementary school children participated in the study. Of these, 17 were in Level 1 (average age: 6 years 5 months; 2 girls, 15 boys), 13 were in Level 2 (average age: 7 years 1 month; 5 girls, 8 boys), and 26 were in Level 4 (average age: 8 years 7 months; 13 girls, 13 boys). The children attended various rural state schools in southwest England. Materials. A set of four videotaped sequences were prepared. The first showed a cartoon character with a black background. The character greeted the child (although not by name!) and then said that he would have some questions to ask the child. Then the following instructions were presented for the categorical condition: I will first read to you a short sentence which you must suppose to be true. Then I will ask you to use the first sentence to decide whether or not you can say that something must be certainly true or not. The child was then presented with an example of an MP inference, using the premise If an animal is a duck, then it has wings. After this, the following series of inferences were presented: Inference 1 (MP): Suppose that it is true that: If something is a car, then it has a motor. Now, suppose that you see a car. Is it certain that it has a motor? Inference 2 (AC): Now, suppose that you see something that has a motor. Is it certain that it is a car? Inference 3 (MP): Suppose that it is true that: If an animal is a hedgehog then it has four legs. Now, suppose that you see an animal that is a hedgehog. Is it certain that it has four legs? Inference 4 (AC): Now, suppose that you see an animal with four legs. Is it certain that it is a hedgehog? For each of these inferences, the children were asked to justify their responses by answering the question, Why do you think this? In all cases, the MP inference preceded the AC inference for the same premise. The MP inference was given first in order to allow the participants to establish the basic premise clearly before being given the more complex AC inference. It should also be noted that there is no evidence of the existence of order effects between the MP and the AC inferences. Finally, pretesting showed that even 5-year-old children were able to reliably generate counterexamples required by the two AC inferences (i.e., animals who are not hedgehogs that have four legs, things that are not cars that have motors) when explicitly asked to do so. Following this first set of questions, the participants were shown the certainty scale by the experimenter. This consisted of a sequence of five vertical red bars on a white sheet of cardboard, with the bar on the left being close to 0 cm. Each successive bar was longer than the one to the left of it, making an ascending sequence. Each child was told that the extreme points represented totally likely and totally unlikely possibilities, with intermediate points representing variable degrees of likelihood. The exact formulation used the notion of how sure it is. The points on the scale were indicated by the following sequence: (1) not sure, (2) a little sure, (3) medium sure, (4) very sure, (5) very, very sure. These categories were converted to a 5-point scale for the purpose of analysis, with 1 used to denote not sure and 5 used to denote very, very sure. The children were then shown three situations, using a set of green and red trees. In the first, there was one red tree and nine green trees; in the second, five red and five green trees; and in the third, nine red and one green tree. For each of these, the participants were asked to show on the scale the likelihood of choosing a red tree from among all the trees. Specifically, they were asked, How sure is it that if you chose 1 tree from among all these trees, the tree would be red? If the child had problems understanding how to use the scale appropriately, the experimenter repeated the explanation. Most children had no difficulty in understanding how to use the scale in these conditions. The exact formulation used was derived after pretesting the children in the youngest age group examined here. Following this explanation, the children were asked the same inferential questions as in the categorical condition, in the same order. This time, however, they were asked how likely the presented conclusion was. For example, the MP inference was presented in the following way: Suppose that it is true that: If something is a car, then it has a motor. Now, suppose that you see a car. How sure is it that it has a motor? A second version of this videotaped sequence was constructed by starting with Inferences 3 and 4 and then presenting Inferences 1 and 2. Finally, for each of these two sequences, a second set was constructed by asking the probabilistic inferences first, followed by the categorical inferences, thus giving a total of four sequences. Procedure. The children were tested individually in sessions lasting about 10 min. The children were introduced to an experimenter, who told them that they would watch a single videotape and that, during the tape, they would be asked some questions. They were asked to listen to the tape attentively. After that, the experimenter started the tape. The tape was paused after each question. The children s responses were recorded and analyzed subsequently. The four videotaped sequences were varied systematically from one child to the next.

6 Deductive and Probabilistic Inference 1071 egorical or probabilistic instructions, so we combined scores across these two contents. Acceptance of the MP and AC inferences. The children s response was yes, no, or not sure. The first was classed as accepting the inference, whereas no and not sure responses were classed as not accepting the inference (Markovits et al., 1998). Table 1 gives the mean percentages of acceptance of the MP and AC inferences under categorical instructions (out of two) and the mean probability ratings for the MP and AC inferences (on a scale from 1 to 5) under probabilistic instructions. As can be seen from this table, performance on the MP inference showed very high levels of acceptance under categorical instructions and correspondingly high levels of the evaluated probability of this inference. This indicated that even the youngest children had no real difficulty in understanding the instructions to suppose that the premise was true, with both forms of instruction. We initially examined the way that inferential performance under probabilistic instructions varied as a function of age. An ANOVA with mean conclusion ratings on the MP and AC inferences as dependent variables, with argument form as a repeated measure, and with grade level as the independent variable was performed. This showed only an effect of argument form [F(1,53) , p,.001]. No other effects were significant. Mean ratings on the AC inference were lower than mean ratings on the MP inference at all grade levels. This shows that the participants were generally able to differentiate the AC from the MP inference in the probabilistic condition. More important, consistent with our hypothesis, there was little developmental change in how either the AC or the MP inferences were evaluated under probabilistic instructions. We also examined how the probabilistic scale was used. At each grade level, we calculated the proportion of responses that were at either extreme of the probability scale. These represented 80%, 62%, and 50% of all the responses among the 6-year-olds, the 7-year-olds, and the 9-year-olds, respectively. This shows that the 6-yearolds did sometimes employ the intermediate points on the probability scale but had, nonetheless, a strong tendency to dichotomize their responses. Use of an intermediate response clearly increased with age. We subsequently looked at inferential performance under categorical instructions. We first looked at whether these children were able to distinguish between the MP and the AC inferences. In order to do this, we calculated Table 1 Mean Percentages of Acceptance of the Invited Inference in the Categorical Condition and Mean Ratings of the Probability of the Invited Inference (on a Scale From 1 to 5) in the Probabilistic Condition for the Modus Parens (MP) and Affirmation of the Consequent (AC) Forms Combined Over the Two Premises Categorical Inference Probabilistic Inference Grade Level n MP AC MP AC the number of times that each participant accepted the MP and AC inferences (this gave scores varying between 0 and 2 for each inference type). We then compared these, using a Wilcoxon signed-rank test for each grade level. This showed that acceptance of the MP inference was significantly higher than acceptance of the AC inference for the 6-year-olds [T(17) 5 12, p,.05], the 7-year-olds [T(13) 5 39, p,.001], and the 9-year-olds [T(26) 5 95, p,.001]. We then looked at the change in performance on the two forms of inference as a function of age. We performed a log-linear analysis on the number of MP acceptances, with grade as a dependent variable. This showed no effect of grade. We then performed a log-linear analysis on the number of AC acceptances, with grade as a dependent variable. This showed a significant effect of grade [χ 2 (2) , p,.01]. There was a significant decrease in AC acceptance between the 6-year-olds and the 7-yearolds [χ 2 (1) , p,.01], with no difference between the 7-year-olds and the 9-year-olds [χ 2 (1) , n.s.]. In sum, consistent with our predictions, acceptance of the AC inference under deductive instructions declined with increasing age. No other developmental trends were noted. Thus, although there was a very strong decrease in the percentage of AC acceptances under categorical instructions between 6 and 7 years of age (from 61.8% to 11.5%), this was not mirrored under probabilistic instructions, for which there was no significant difference between these same ages (from 3.57 to 3.38). Moreover, a basic acceptance of the premise, as shown by the high rates of acceptance of the MP inferences with categorical instructions and the high rating of the MP inference with probabilistic instructions, was evident at all age levels. Note that although the relatively small number of participants precludes any absolute judgment as to the developmental pattern underlying probabilistic inferences, we can nonetheless conclude that the change in performance under categorical instructions, between 6 and 7 years of age, was clearly stronger than that observed with probabilistic inferences for the same premises. Relation between justifications and inferential performance. A second set of analyses then examined the relation between the children s explicit justifications and their inferential performance. This was done in order to test our prediction that the relation between counterexample generation and inferential performance would be more closely tied to categorical than to probabilistic inferences among the older children. We started by examining developmental patterns in the children s justifications for the AC inferences. We were specifically interested in justifications that referred to potential alternative antecedents either those that stated a specific alternative (e.g., because cats and dogs have legs) or those that stated a general alternative (e.g., other things have legs). These categories have been used previously (e.g., Janveau-Brennan & Markovits, 1999) and are very clearly defined. Justifications were coded separately by two experimenters. There were disagreements on fewer than 5% of the codes, and these were resolved by subsequent discussion between the two coders. Table 2 gives the percentage of justifications that referred to alternative antecedents for the categorical and

7 1072 Markovits and Thompson Table 2 Mean Percentages of All Justifications That Referred to Alternatives on the Affirmation of the Consequent Inferences by Grade Level for Categorical and Probabilistic Inferences Grade Level n Categorical Probabilistic probabilistic inferences as a function of grade level. We first looked at whether the number of justifications referring to alternatives differed between the two types of inferential problems. We performed an ANOVA for the number of justifications referring to alternatives on the categorical inferences and on the probabilistic inferences, with problem type as a repeated variable and grade level as the independent variable. This analysis was repeated using rank order and gave the same pattern of results (see, e.g., Conover, 1980). This showed a significant effect of grade [F(1,53) , p,.01] and of problem type [F(1,53) , p,.001]. More justifications referring to alternatives were produced under categorical instructions than under probabilistic instructions. Also, as was predicted, there was an overall increase in the relative production of such justifications with age, with contrast analyses indicating a significant increase between 6 and 7 years of age only. These data provide support for our hypothesis that counterexample reasoning develops with age. Just as important, the data in Table 3 confirm that the use of counterexamples develops differently for categorical and probabilistic inferences. Table 3 shows the percentage of acceptances of the AC inference under categorical instructions and the mean ratings for AC inferences under probabilistic instructions as a function of production of an alternative antecedent as a justification. An examination of Table 3 shows that the percentage of acceptances of the AC inference under categorical instructions when an explicit alternative antecedent was produced as a justification was less than the percentage of acceptances when an explicit alternative antecedent was not produced, at all age levels. Under probabilistic instructions, the mean AC rating was greater when an alternative antecedent was not produced than when it was produced, for the two younger age levels. However, for the oldest participants, this pattern was reversed. We corroborated these conclusions by calculating the correlations between the rate of production of an alterna- tive antecedent and responses to the AC inferences for both the categorical and the probabilistic conditions. In order to do this, we calculated the number of justifications to the two AC problems that involved at least one alternative antecedent (out of a total of two), separately for the categorical and the probabilistic conditions. We then calculated Pearson correlations between justifications with alternative antecedents and responses to the AC inferences for the categorical and the probabilistic instructions. Correlations between justifications and number of acceptances of the AC inference under categorical instructions were significant for the 6-year-olds [r(17) , p,.01], the 7-year-olds [r(13) , p,.05], and the 9-year-olds [r(26) , p,.001]. The children who produced more alternative antecedents as justifications rejected the AC inference more often under categorical instructions, at all ages. The correlation between justifications and mean ratings of the AC inferences under probabilistic instructions was significant for the 6-year-olds [r(17) , p,.05] and for the 7-year-olds [r(13) , p,.05], but not at all for the older children [r(26) , n.s.]. In other words, younger children who produced more alternative antecedents gave lower ratings to the AC inferences under probabilistic instructions, whereas older children showed no relation between justifications and ratings. For the 9-year-olds, correlations between justifications and AC inferences were significantly higher under categorical instructions than under probabilistic instructions [t(25) , p,.001]. Discussion The results of this study provided a focused look at the developmental patterns and relations between simple conditional reasoning under deductive instructions and under probabilistic instructions. The children of all ages and in both instruction conditions accepted the MP inference at a high rate. Moreover, even the 6-year-olds accepted the AC inferences less often than the MP inferences under categorical instructions and evaluated the AC inference as less likely than the MP inference under probabilistic instructions. More important, unlike for the MP inference, there were changes in the tendency to reject the AC inference as a function of age and differences in the development trends for categorical and probabilistic inferences. Specifically, there was a strong tendency for the 6 yearold children to accept the AC inference under categorical instructions, with acceptance rates around 60%, even Table 3 Mean Percentages of Acceptance of the Invited Affirmation of the Consequent Inference in the Categorical Condition and Mean Probability Ratings (on a Scale From 1 to 5) in the Probabilistic Condition As a Function of Production or Lack of Production of an Alternative Antecedent on Justifications Generated for the Corresponding Inferences Categorical Condition Probabilistic Condition Alternative Produced No Alternative Alternative Produced No Alternative Grade Level n % Acceptance n % Acceptance n Mean Rating n Mean Rating

8 Deductive and Probabilistic Inference 1073 with premises that allowed very easy access to potential alternative antecedents. There was a very steep drop in acceptances of the AC inference between 6 and 7 years of age (from 62% to 12%). This was accompanied by similar patterns of change between these two age levels involving both increasing production of explicit alternative antecedents in both conditions and an increased use of intermediate scale points in the probabilistic condition. These different factors indicate that 6 years of age may be the lower limit for the ability to differentiate AC and MP inferences with the very simple kinds of verbal premises used in this study. What do these results indicate about the reasoning processes used under categorical and probabilistic instructions? First, these two forms of reasoning have different developmental patterns. Categorical reasoning showed a steep increase in AC refusals between 6 and 7 years of age. There was no such effect with probabilistic reasoning, which overall showed a much flatter pattern of developmental change. Second, the correlation between responses to the AC inferences and numbers of justifications referring to alternatives was similarly high among the 6 and 7 year-old children under both categorical and probabilistic instructions. However, among the 9-yearolds, there was no correlation between justifications and ratings of the AC inference under probabilistic instructions, whereas the same correlation was very high under categorical instructions. This is exactly the pattern that is found in adults (Markovits & Handley, 2005) and is also consistent with Verschueren et al. s (2005) results. These results clearly are consistent with the hypothesis that children as young as 9 years of age have access to two distinct modes of inferential reasoning, one of which corresponds to a reasoning-by-counterexample model, whereas the other corresponds to a form of probabilistic inference. In contrast, the 6-year-olds showed difficulty in using an explicit process of reasoning by counterexample, since they were less likely to generate counterexamples than were their older counterparts. In contrast, when a counterexample was produced, likelihood ratings of the AC inference were relatively constant across grades, suggesting that even the youngest children had access to a probabilistic form of inference, which showed a weaker pattern of developmental change in the age range between 6 and 9 years than was shown by reasoning by counterexample. Study 2 The results of Study 1 suggested that even 6-year-old children can make adequate conditional inferences under probabilistic instructions with simple verbal premises, whereas basic counterexample-based reasoning is still difficult at this age specifically, because 6-year-olds are less likely to retrieve and use a counterexample under categorical instructions, as compared with older children. Retrieval, when not automatic, uses working memory capacity (Rosen & Engle, 1997) and presents an additional level of difficulty for very young children. Thus, we hypothesized that very young children s counterexample-based reasoning would improve if they were given problems for which counterexamples were directly accessible. We thus decided to replicate the initial study by constructing inferential problems for which the universe of alternatives was directly visible. In order to do this, we presented children with a series of red and blue shapes. In one situation, the red shapes consisted of four squares and one circle, and the premise referred to the fact that all the squares were red. In this case, since the probability of a red shape s being a square was.8, the AC inference was highly probable. In the second situation, the red shapes consisted of one triangle and four circles, and the premise referred to the fact that all the triangles were red. In this case, since the probability of a red shape s being a triangle was.2, the AC inference was highly unlikely. We made two specific hypotheses. First, the results of the previous study had indicated that even 6-year-olds were able to make adequate conditional inferences under probabilistic instructions with purely verbal premises with very familiar content. Thus, we anticipated that the 6-year-olds in the present study would be able to distinguish between the high and low-probability AC inferences under probabilistic instructions. The results of the previous study had also shown that whereas 7-year-olds were able to reject the AC inference under categorical instructions at a very high level, 6-year-olds were not able to do so. We predicted that providing 6 year-old children with these kinds of problems would facilitate counterexample-based reasoning and would allow them to reject the AC inference under categorical instructions at a higher level than had been observed in the initial study. Finally, given the way that the stimuli were presented, we did not ask the children for justifications in this case but simply examined responses to the inferential questions. Method Participants. A total of 53 elementary school children participated in the study. Of these, 21 were in Level 1 (average age: 6 years 5 months; 11 girls, 10 boys), 18 were in Level 2 (average age: 7 years 7 months; 8 girls, 10 boys), and 14 were in Level 4 (average age: 9 years 8 months; 8 girls, 6 boys). The children attended various rural state schools in southwest England. Materials. A set of four videotaped sequences were prepared that were identical to those used in the first study, with one difference. When the inferential problems were presented, a set of colored shapes appeared on the screen. For the first set of inferences, these were four red squares, one red circle, and four blue circles, in that order (we will refer to this as the high-probability problem). The corresponding inferential problems in the categorical condition referred to these shapes and were Inference 1 (MP): It is true that: If a shape is a square, it is red. Now, suppose that a shape is a square. Is it certain that it is red? Inference 2 (AC): Now, suppose that a shape is red. Is it certain that it is a square? The shapes used in the next two problems were one red triangle, four red circles, and four blue circles, in that order (we will refer to this as the low-probability problem). The corresponding inferential problems in the categorical condition referred to these shapes and were Inference 3 (MP): It is true that: If a shape is a triangle, it is red. Now, suppose that a shape is a triangle. Is it certain that it is red?

Is inferential reasoning just probabilistic reasoning in disguise?

Is inferential reasoning just probabilistic reasoning in disguise? Memory & Cognition 2005, 33 (7), 1315-1323 Is inferential reasoning just probabilistic reasoning in disguise? HENRY MARKOVITS and SIMON HANDLEY University of Plymouth, Plymouth, England Oaksford, Chater,

More information

Does pure water boil, when it s heated to 100 C? : The Associative Strength of Disabling Conditions in Conditional Reasoning

Does pure water boil, when it s heated to 100 C? : The Associative Strength of Disabling Conditions in Conditional Reasoning Does pure water boil, when it s heated to 100 C? : The Associative Strength of Disabling Conditions in Conditional Reasoning Wim De Neys (Wim.Deneys@psy.kuleuven.ac.be) Department of Psychology, K.U.Leuven,

More information

Chronometric evidence for memory retrieval in causal conditional reasoning: The case of the association strength effect

Chronometric evidence for memory retrieval in causal conditional reasoning: The case of the association strength effect Memory & Cognition 2005, 33 (4), 734-741 Chronometric evidence for memory retrieval in causal conditional reasoning: The case of the association strength effect NELLY GROSSET and PIERRE BARROUILLET Université

More information

Working Memory Span and Everyday Conditional Reasoning: A Trend Analysis

Working Memory Span and Everyday Conditional Reasoning: A Trend Analysis Working Memory Span and Everyday Conditional Reasoning: A Trend Analysis Wim De Neys (Wim.Deneys@psy.kuleuven.ac.be) Walter Schaeken (Walter.Schaeken@psy.kuleuven.ac.be) Géry d Ydewalle (Géry.dYdewalle@psy.kuleuven.ac.be)

More information

Interactions between inferential strategies and belief bias

Interactions between inferential strategies and belief bias Mem Cogn (2017) 45:1182 1192 DOI 10.3758/s13421-017-0723-2 Interactions between inferential strategies and belief bias Henry Markovits 1 & Janie Brisson 1 & Pier-Luc de Chantal 1 & Valerie A. Thompson

More information

Information processing and reasoning with premises that are empirically false: Interference, working memory, and processing speed

Information processing and reasoning with premises that are empirically false: Interference, working memory, and processing speed Memory & Cognition 2004, 32 (4), 592-601 Information processing and reasoning with premises that are empirically false: Interference, working memory, and processing speed HENRY MARKOVITS and CELINE DOYON

More information

Metacognition and abstract reasoning

Metacognition and abstract reasoning Mem Cogn (2015) 43:681 693 DOI 10.3758/s13421-014-0488-9 Metacognition and abstract reasoning Henry Markovits & Valerie A. Thompson & Janie Brisson Published online: 22 November 2014 # Psychonomic Society,

More information

Content Effects in Conditional Reasoning: Evaluating the Container Schema

Content Effects in Conditional Reasoning: Evaluating the Container Schema Effects in Conditional Reasoning: Evaluating the Container Schema Amber N. Bloomfield (a-bloomfield@northwestern.edu) Department of Psychology, 2029 Sheridan Road Evanston, IL 60208 USA Lance J. Rips (rips@northwestern.edu)

More information

PREDICTORS OF DEDUCTIVE REASONING IN PRIMARY SCHOOL CHILDREN

PREDICTORS OF DEDUCTIVE REASONING IN PRIMARY SCHOOL CHILDREN Journal of Psychological and Educational Research JPER - 2014, 22 (2), November, 45-60 PREDICTORS OF DEDUCTIVE REASONING IN PRIMARY SCHOOL CHILDREN Denisa Ardelean University of Oradea, Romania Abstract

More information

What Makes People Revise Their Beliefs Following Contradictory Anecdotal Evidence?: The Role of Systemic Variability and Direct Experience

What Makes People Revise Their Beliefs Following Contradictory Anecdotal Evidence?: The Role of Systemic Variability and Direct Experience Cognitive Science 31 (2007) 535 547 Copyright C 2007 Cognitive Science Society, Inc. All rights reserved. What Makes People Revise Their Beliefs Following Contradictory Anecdotal Evidence?: The Role of

More information

The effect of premise order in conditional reasoning: a test of the mental model theory

The effect of premise order in conditional reasoning: a test of the mental model theory Cognition 63 (1997) 1 28 The effect of premise order in conditional reasoning: a test of the mental model theory Vittorio Girotto *, Alberto Mazzocco, Alessandra Tasso a, b b a CREPCO CNRS and University

More information

Working memory and everyday conditional reasoning: Retrieval and inhibition of stored counterexamples

Working memory and everyday conditional reasoning: Retrieval and inhibition of stored counterexamples THINKING & REASONING, 2005, 11 (4), 349 381 Working memory and everyday conditional reasoning: Retrieval and inhibition of stored counterexamples Wim De Neys, Walter Schaeken, and Ge ry d Ydewalle University

More information

Why Does Similarity Correlate With Inductive Strength?

Why Does Similarity Correlate With Inductive Strength? Why Does Similarity Correlate With Inductive Strength? Uri Hasson (uhasson@princeton.edu) Psychology Department, Princeton University Princeton, NJ 08540 USA Geoffrey P. Goodwin (ggoodwin@princeton.edu)

More information

Everyday conditional reasoning: A working memory dependent tradeoff between counterexample and likelihood use

Everyday conditional reasoning: A working memory dependent tradeoff between counterexample and likelihood use Memory & Cognition 2005, 33 (1), 107-119 Everyday conditional reasoning: A working memory dependent tradeoff between counterexample and likelihood use NIKI VERSCHUEREN, WALTER SCHAEKEN, and GERY D YDEWALLE

More information

Negations Without Not : Alternative forms of Negation and Contrast Classes in Conditional Inference. James Richard Hazlett Vance

Negations Without Not : Alternative forms of Negation and Contrast Classes in Conditional Inference. James Richard Hazlett Vance Negations Without Not : Alternative forms of Negation and Contrast Classes in Conditional Inference James Richard Hazlett Vance Doctor of Philosophy Birkbeck, University of London 2018 1 Declaration I

More information

Issues in Reasoning about Iffy Propositions: The Initial Representation of Conditionals

Issues in Reasoning about Iffy Propositions: The Initial Representation of Conditionals Issues in Reasoning about Iffy Propositions: The Initial Representation of Conditionals Walter J. Schroyens (Walter.Schroyens@hec.ca) HEC Montréal, Université de Montréal. 3000, Chemin de la Côte-Sainte-Catherine,

More information

Causal conditional reasoning and semantic memory retrieval: A test of the semantic memory framework

Causal conditional reasoning and semantic memory retrieval: A test of the semantic memory framework Memory & Cognition 2002, 30 (6), 908-920 Causal conditional reasoning and semantic memory retrieval: A test of the semantic memory framework WIM DE NEYS, WALTER SCHAEKEN, and GÉRY D YDEWALLE University

More information

Advice conditionals about tips and warnings: interpretations and inferences

Advice conditionals about tips and warnings: interpretations and inferences Journal of Cognitive Psychology ISSN: 2044-5911 (Print) 2044-592X (Online) Journal homepage: http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/pecp21 Advice conditionals about tips and warnings: interpretations and inferences

More information

Looking back: reasoning and metacognition with narrative texts

Looking back: reasoning and metacognition with narrative texts Looking back: reasoning and metacognition with narrative texts Bridget A. Franks, David J. Therriault, Miriam I. Buhr, Evelyn S. Chiang, Claire M. Gonzalez, Heekyung K. Kwon, Jenni L. Schelble, et al.

More information

Is it possible to gain new knowledge by deduction?

Is it possible to gain new knowledge by deduction? Is it possible to gain new knowledge by deduction? Abstract In this paper I will try to defend the hypothesis that it is possible to gain new knowledge through deduction. In order to achieve that goal,

More information

Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition

Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition Conflict and Bias in Heuristic Judgment Sudeep Bhatia Online First Publication, September 29, 2016. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/xlm0000307

More information

Thinking about conditionals: A study of individual differences

Thinking about conditionals: A study of individual differences Memory & Cognition 2007, 35 (7), 1772-1784 Thinking about conditionals: A study of individual differences JONATHAN ST. B. T. EVANS, SIMON J. HANDLEY, AND HELEN NEILENS University of Plymouth, Plymouth,

More information

Implicit Information in Directionality of Verbal Probability Expressions

Implicit Information in Directionality of Verbal Probability Expressions Implicit Information in Directionality of Verbal Probability Expressions Hidehito Honda (hito@ky.hum.titech.ac.jp) Kimihiko Yamagishi (kimihiko@ky.hum.titech.ac.jp) Graduate School of Decision Science

More information

Running Head: TRUST INACCURATE INFORMANTS 1. In the Absence of Conflicting Testimony Young Children Trust Inaccurate Informants

Running Head: TRUST INACCURATE INFORMANTS 1. In the Absence of Conflicting Testimony Young Children Trust Inaccurate Informants Running Head: TRUST INACCURATE INFORMANTS 1 In the Absence of Conflicting Testimony Young Children Trust Inaccurate Informants Kimberly E. Vanderbilt, Gail D. Heyman, and David Liu University of California,

More information

Inferences: What inferences about the hypotheses and questions can be made based on the results?

Inferences: What inferences about the hypotheses and questions can be made based on the results? QALMRI INSTRUCTIONS QALMRI is an acronym that stands for: Question: (a) What was the broad question being asked by this research project? (b) What was the specific question being asked by this research

More information

Counterexample retrieval and inhibition during conditional reasoning: Direct evidence from memory probing

Counterexample retrieval and inhibition during conditional reasoning: Direct evidence from memory probing 1 Chapter 2 Counterexample retrieval and inhibition during conditional reasoning: Direct evidence from memory probing Wim De Neys 2 2 0 1 2 In one of Bill Waterson s hilarious Calvin and Hobbes cartoons,

More information

Instituto Superior de Psicologia Aplicada, Lisbon, Portugal b Princeton University, Princeton, NJ, USA PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

Instituto Superior de Psicologia Aplicada, Lisbon, Portugal b Princeton University, Princeton, NJ, USA PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE This article was downloaded by: [Princeton University] On: 11 May 2010 Access details: Access Details: [subscription number 917276147] Publisher Psychology Press Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales

More information

Chapter 11 Decision Making. Syllogism. The Logic

Chapter 11 Decision Making. Syllogism. The Logic Chapter 11 Decision Making Syllogism All men are mortal. (major premise) Socrates is a man. (minor premise) (therefore) Socrates is mortal. (conclusion) The Logic Mortal Socrates Men 1 An Abstract Syllogism

More information

Wason's Cards: What is Wrong?

Wason's Cards: What is Wrong? Wason's Cards: What is Wrong? Pei Wang Computer and Information Sciences, Temple University This paper proposes a new interpretation

More information

A Probabilistic Approach to Conditional Reasoning Development. Click for updates

A Probabilistic Approach to Conditional Reasoning Development. Click for updates This article was downloaded by: [National Chung Cheng University], [In-mao Liu] On: 01 August 2015, At: 00:02 Publisher: Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954

More information

Thompson, Valerie A, Ackerman, Rakefet, Sidi, Yael, Ball, Linden, Pennycook, Gordon and Prowse Turner, Jamie A

Thompson, Valerie A, Ackerman, Rakefet, Sidi, Yael, Ball, Linden, Pennycook, Gordon and Prowse Turner, Jamie A Article The role of answer fluency and perceptual fluency in the monitoring and control of reasoning: Reply to Alter, Oppenheimer, and Epley Thompson, Valerie A, Ackerman, Rakefet, Sidi, Yael, Ball, Linden,

More information

Insight Assessment Measuring Thinking Worldwide

Insight Assessment Measuring Thinking Worldwide California Critical Thinking Skills Test (CCTST). The CCTST measures the reasoning skills human beings use in the process of reflectively deciding what to believe or what to do. Skill/Attribute Name SE

More information

Why do Psychologists Perform Research?

Why do Psychologists Perform Research? PSY 102 1 PSY 102 Understanding and Thinking Critically About Psychological Research Thinking critically about research means knowing the right questions to ask to assess the validity or accuracy of a

More information

Directionality of conditionals in the context of visual priming

Directionality of conditionals in the context of visual priming Review of Psychology, 2013, Vol. 20, No. 1-2, 61-68 UDC 159.9 Directionality of conditionals in the context of visual priming IGOR BAJŠANSKI, PAVLE VALERJEV and TANJA GULAN The theory of mental models

More information

Modeling Unconscious Gender Bias in Fame Judgments: Finding the Proper Branch of the Correct (Multinomial) Tree

Modeling Unconscious Gender Bias in Fame Judgments: Finding the Proper Branch of the Correct (Multinomial) Tree CONSCIOUSNESS AND COGNITION 5, 221 225 (1996) ARTICLE NO. 0013 Modeling Unconscious Gender Bias in Fame Judgments: Finding the Proper Branch of the Correct (Multinomial) Tree SEAN C. DRAINE AND ANTHONY

More information

Necessity, possibility and belief: A study of syllogistic reasoning

Necessity, possibility and belief: A study of syllogistic reasoning THE QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF EXPERIMENTAL PSYCHOLOGY, 2001, 54A (3), 935 958 Necessity, possibility and belief: A study of syllogistic reasoning Jonathan St. B.T. Evans, Simon J. Handley, and Catherine N.J.

More information

9 research designs likely for PSYC 2100

9 research designs likely for PSYC 2100 9 research designs likely for PSYC 2100 1) 1 factor, 2 levels, 1 group (one group gets both treatment levels) related samples t-test (compare means of 2 levels only) 2) 1 factor, 2 levels, 2 groups (one

More information

Relations between premise similarity and inductive strength

Relations between premise similarity and inductive strength Psychonomic Bulletin & Review 2005, 12 (2), 340-344 Relations between premise similarity and inductive strength EVAN HEIT University of Warwick, Coventry, England and AIDAN FEENEY University of Durham,

More information

The Regression-Discontinuity Design

The Regression-Discontinuity Design Page 1 of 10 Home» Design» Quasi-Experimental Design» The Regression-Discontinuity Design The regression-discontinuity design. What a terrible name! In everyday language both parts of the term have connotations

More information

Problem representations and illusions in reasoning

Problem representations and illusions in reasoning CogSci99 3 Problem representations and illusions in reasoning Vladimir M. Sloutsky (sloutsky.@osu.edu) Center for Cognitive Science & School of Teaching & Learning; 945 N. High Street Columbus, OH 430,

More information

Encoding of Elements and Relations of Object Arrangements by Young Children

Encoding of Elements and Relations of Object Arrangements by Young Children Encoding of Elements and Relations of Object Arrangements by Young Children Leslee J. Martin (martin.1103@osu.edu) Department of Psychology & Center for Cognitive Science Ohio State University 216 Lazenby

More information

Does everyone love everyone? The psychology of iterative reasoning

Does everyone love everyone? The psychology of iterative reasoning THINKING & REASONING, 2004, 10 (1), 31 53 Does everyone love everyone? The psychology of iterative reasoning Paolo Cherubini Universita` di Milano-Bicocca, Italy P. N. Johnson-Laird Princeton University,

More information

CPS331 Lecture: Coping with Uncertainty; Discussion of Dreyfus Reading

CPS331 Lecture: Coping with Uncertainty; Discussion of Dreyfus Reading CPS331 Lecture: Coping with Uncertainty; Discussion of Dreyfus Reading Objectives: 1. To discuss ways of handling uncertainty (probability; Mycin CF) 2. To discuss Dreyfus views on expert systems Materials:

More information

Cognitive Psychology

Cognitive Psychology Cognitive Psychology 63 (2011) 107 140 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Cognitive Psychology journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/cogpsych Intuition, reason, and metacognition Valerie A.

More information

On the Evaluation of If p then q Conditionals

On the Evaluation of If p then q Conditionals On the Evaluation of If p then q Conditionals Constantinos Hadjichristidis (constantinos.hadjichristidis@durham.ac.uk) Department of Psychology, University of Durham Durham, DH1 3LE, UK Rosemary J. Stevenson

More information

Describe what is meant by a placebo Contrast the double-blind procedure with the single-blind procedure Review the structure for organizing a memo

Describe what is meant by a placebo Contrast the double-blind procedure with the single-blind procedure Review the structure for organizing a memo Please note the page numbers listed for the Lind book may vary by a page or two depending on which version of the textbook you have. Readings: Lind 1 11 (with emphasis on chapters 10, 11) Please note chapter

More information

Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition

Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition The Impact of Disablers on Predictive Inference Denise Dellarosa Cummins Online First Publication, June 9, 014. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/xlm000004

More information

FULL REPORT OF RESEARCH ACTIVITIES. Background

FULL REPORT OF RESEARCH ACTIVITIES. Background FULL REPORT OF RESEARCH ACTIVITIES Background There has been a recent upsurge of interest in individual differences in reasoning which has been well summarised by Stanovich & West (2000). The reason for

More information

Running head: INDIVIDUAL DIFFERENCES 1. Why to treat subjects as fixed effects. James S. Adelman. University of Warwick.

Running head: INDIVIDUAL DIFFERENCES 1. Why to treat subjects as fixed effects. James S. Adelman. University of Warwick. Running head: INDIVIDUAL DIFFERENCES 1 Why to treat subjects as fixed effects James S. Adelman University of Warwick Zachary Estes Bocconi University Corresponding Author: James S. Adelman Department of

More information

CHAPTER 3 DATA ANALYSIS: DESCRIBING DATA

CHAPTER 3 DATA ANALYSIS: DESCRIBING DATA Data Analysis: Describing Data CHAPTER 3 DATA ANALYSIS: DESCRIBING DATA In the analysis process, the researcher tries to evaluate the data collected both from written documents and from other sources such

More information

Sleeping Beauty is told the following:

Sleeping Beauty is told the following: Sleeping beauty Sleeping Beauty is told the following: You are going to sleep for three days, during which time you will be woken up either once Now suppose that you are sleeping beauty, and you are woken

More information

Running Head: SENSITIVITY TO TAXNOMIC ASSOCIATIONS

Running Head: SENSITIVITY TO TAXNOMIC ASSOCIATIONS Taxonomic Association Sensitivity 1 Running Head: SENSITIVITY TO TAXNOMIC ASSOCIATIONS Sensitivity to Purely Taxonomic Associations among Young Children Wyatt D Emilia Carnegie Mellon University Taxonomic

More information

Appendix: Instructions for Treatment Index B (Human Opponents, With Recommendations)

Appendix: Instructions for Treatment Index B (Human Opponents, With Recommendations) Appendix: Instructions for Treatment Index B (Human Opponents, With Recommendations) This is an experiment in the economics of strategic decision making. Various agencies have provided funds for this research.

More information

THE USE OF MULTIVARIATE ANALYSIS IN DEVELOPMENT THEORY: A CRITIQUE OF THE APPROACH ADOPTED BY ADELMAN AND MORRIS A. C. RAYNER

THE USE OF MULTIVARIATE ANALYSIS IN DEVELOPMENT THEORY: A CRITIQUE OF THE APPROACH ADOPTED BY ADELMAN AND MORRIS A. C. RAYNER THE USE OF MULTIVARIATE ANALYSIS IN DEVELOPMENT THEORY: A CRITIQUE OF THE APPROACH ADOPTED BY ADELMAN AND MORRIS A. C. RAYNER Introduction, 639. Factor analysis, 639. Discriminant analysis, 644. INTRODUCTION

More information

AP Psychology -- Chapter 02 Review Research Methods in Psychology

AP Psychology -- Chapter 02 Review Research Methods in Psychology AP Psychology -- Chapter 02 Review Research Methods in Psychology 1. In the opening vignette, to what was Alicia's condition linked? The death of her parents and only brother 2. What did Pennebaker s study

More information

Children's Differential Performance on Deductive and Inductive Syllogisms

Children's Differential Performance on Deductive and Inductive Syllogisms Developmental Psychology 1997, Vol. 33, No. 1, 70-78 Copyright 1997 by the American Psychological Association, Inc. 0012-1649/97/$3.00 Children's Differential Performance on and Syllogisms Kathleen M.

More information

Chapter 11. Experimental Design: One-Way Independent Samples Design

Chapter 11. Experimental Design: One-Way Independent Samples Design 11-1 Chapter 11. Experimental Design: One-Way Independent Samples Design Advantages and Limitations Comparing Two Groups Comparing t Test to ANOVA Independent Samples t Test Independent Samples ANOVA Comparing

More information

The Scientific Method

The Scientific Method The Scientific Method Objectives 1. To understand the central role of hypothesis testing in the modern scientific process. 2. To design and conduct an experiment using the scientific method. 3. To learn

More information

Psychology Research Process

Psychology Research Process Psychology Research Process Logical Processes Induction Observation/Association/Using Correlation Trying to assess, through observation of a large group/sample, what is associated with what? Examples:

More information

Relationships Between the High Impact Indicators and Other Indicators

Relationships Between the High Impact Indicators and Other Indicators Relationships Between the High Impact Indicators and Other Indicators The High Impact Indicators are a list of key skills assessed on the GED test that, if emphasized in instruction, can help instructors

More information

Assignment 4: True or Quasi-Experiment

Assignment 4: True or Quasi-Experiment Assignment 4: True or Quasi-Experiment Objectives: After completing this assignment, you will be able to Evaluate when you must use an experiment to answer a research question Develop statistical hypotheses

More information

EXPERIMENTAL DESIGN Page 1 of 11. relationships between certain events in the environment and the occurrence of particular

EXPERIMENTAL DESIGN Page 1 of 11. relationships between certain events in the environment and the occurrence of particular EXPERIMENTAL DESIGN Page 1 of 11 I. Introduction to Experimentation 1. The experiment is the primary means by which we are able to establish cause-effect relationships between certain events in the environment

More information

Cognitive domain: Comprehension Answer location: Elements of Empiricism Question type: MC

Cognitive domain: Comprehension Answer location: Elements of Empiricism Question type: MC Chapter 2 1. Knowledge that is evaluative, value laden, and concerned with prescribing what ought to be is known as knowledge. *a. Normative b. Nonnormative c. Probabilistic d. Nonprobabilistic. 2. Most

More information

Negations in syllogistic reasoning: Evidence for a heuristic analytic conflict

Negations in syllogistic reasoning: Evidence for a heuristic analytic conflict Negations in syllogistic reasoning: Evidence for a heuristic analytic conflict Item type Article Authors Stupple, Edward J. N.; Waterhouse, Eleanor F. Citation Stupple, Edward J. N., Waterhouse, Eleanor

More information

When Falsification is the Only Path to Truth

When Falsification is the Only Path to Truth When Falsification is the Only Path to Truth Michelle Cowley (cowleym@tcd.ie) Psychology Department, University of Dublin, Trinity College, Dublin, Ireland Ruth M.J. Byrne (rmbyrne@tcd.ie) Psychology Department,

More information

Thinking 2. Dual-Process Theory. Dual-Process Theory. Can you describe the cues you use to distinguish all dogs from all cats? What is this?

Thinking 2. Dual-Process Theory. Dual-Process Theory. Can you describe the cues you use to distinguish all dogs from all cats? What is this? Dual-Process Theory Heuristics: Strategies that can be used in all kinds of directed thinking to quickly make judgments, decisions, reason, or solve problems, at the price of occasional errors. Which of

More information

Inference suppression and moral dilemmas

Inference suppression and moral dilemmas Inference suppression and moral dilemmas Barbara Kuhnert University of Freiburg - October 2013 SPP1516 Project: Non-monotonicity, consistency and rationality in human reasoning Human non-monotonic reasoning

More information

Group Assignment #1: Concept Explication. For each concept, ask and answer the questions before your literature search.

Group Assignment #1: Concept Explication. For each concept, ask and answer the questions before your literature search. Group Assignment #1: Concept Explication 1. Preliminary identification of the concept. Identify and name each concept your group is interested in examining. Questions to asked and answered: Is each concept

More information

Perception Lie Paradox: Mathematically Proved Uncertainty about Humans Perception Similarity

Perception Lie Paradox: Mathematically Proved Uncertainty about Humans Perception Similarity Perception Lie Paradox: Mathematically Proved Uncertainty about Humans Perception Similarity Ahmed M. Mahran Computer and Systems Engineering Department, Faculty of Engineering, Alexandria University,

More information

Advanced Logical Thinking Skills (1) Revisit the concepts of logic

Advanced Logical Thinking Skills (1) Revisit the concepts of logic Mei-Writing Academic Writing II(A) - Lecture 3 November 12, 2013 Advanced Logical Thinking Skills (1) Revisit the concepts of logic by Paul W. L. Lai Build&the&& Thesis&Statement& * Build&a&one*sentence&thesis&statement&

More information

What do External Representations Tell about Mental Models? An Exploratory Study in Deductive Reasoning

What do External Representations Tell about Mental Models? An Exploratory Study in Deductive Reasoning What do External Representations Tell about Mental Models? An Exploratory Study in Deductive Reasoning Barbara Bazzanella (B.Bazzanella@studenti.unitn.it) University of Trento LASDEC experimental laboratory,

More information

The Abstract Selection Task: New Data and an Almost Comprehensive Model

The Abstract Selection Task: New Data and an Almost Comprehensive Model Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition 2007, Vol. 33, No. 4, 680 703 Copyright 2007 by the American Psychological Association 0278-7393/07/$12.00 DOI: 10.1037/0278-7393.33.4.680

More information

Reasoning Deduction. Dual-Process Theories of Deductive Reasoning

Reasoning Deduction. Dual-Process Theories of Deductive Reasoning Reasoning Deduction. Dual-Process Theories of Deductive Reasoning Mariusz Urbański Institute of Psychology Adam Mickiewicz University Poznań, Poland http://mu.edu.pl Table of Contents 1 Memento 2 Two paradigms

More information

Readings: Textbook readings: OpenStax - Chapters 1 11 Online readings: Appendix D, E & F Plous Chapters 10, 11, 12 and 14

Readings: Textbook readings: OpenStax - Chapters 1 11 Online readings: Appendix D, E & F Plous Chapters 10, 11, 12 and 14 Readings: Textbook readings: OpenStax - Chapters 1 11 Online readings: Appendix D, E & F Plous Chapters 10, 11, 12 and 14 Still important ideas Contrast the measurement of observable actions (and/or characteristics)

More information

The Case Against Deliberative Decision Making

The Case Against Deliberative Decision Making The Case Against Deliberative Decision Making Psychology 466: Judgment & Decision Making Instructor: John Miyamoto 11/30/2017: Lecture 10-2 Note: This Powerpoint presentation may contain macros that I

More information

Answers to end of chapter questions

Answers to end of chapter questions Answers to end of chapter questions Chapter 1 What are the three most important characteristics of QCA as a method of data analysis? QCA is (1) systematic, (2) flexible, and (3) it reduces data. What are

More information

Autonomy as a Positive Value Some Conceptual Prerequisites Niklas Juth Dept. of Philosophy, Göteborg University

Autonomy as a Positive Value Some Conceptual Prerequisites Niklas Juth Dept. of Philosophy, Göteborg University Philosophical Communications, Web Series, No. 28 Dept. of Philosophy, Göteborg University, Sweden ISSN 1652-0459 Autonomy as a Positive Value Some Conceptual Prerequisites Niklas Juth Dept. of Philosophy,

More information

INFERENCING STRATEGIES

INFERENCING STRATEGIES INFERENCING STRATEGIES Table of Content Introduction Categories of Reasoning Inference Techniques Control Strategies Comparative Summary of Backward and Forward Chaining Conflict Resolution Goal Agenda

More information

If and the problems of conditional reasoning

If and the problems of conditional reasoning Opinion If and the problems of conditional reasoning Ruth M.J. Byrne 1 and P.N. Johnson-Laird 2 1 School of Psychology and Institute of Neuroscience, Lloyd Building, Trinity College Dublin, University

More information

9.65 March 29, 2004 Concepts and Prototypes Handout

9.65 March 29, 2004 Concepts and Prototypes Handout 9.65 - Cognitive Processes - Spring 2004 MIT Department of Brain and Cognitive Sciences Course Instructor: Professor Mary C. Potter 9.65 March 29, 2004 Concepts and Prototypes Handout Outline: I. Categorization:

More information

This is an Author's Original Manuscript of an article submitted to Behavior & Brain Science and may differ from the final version which is available here: http://journals.cambridge.org/action/displayabstract?frompage=online&aid=8242505

More information

Decisions based on verbal probabilities: Decision bias or decision by belief sampling?

Decisions based on verbal probabilities: Decision bias or decision by belief sampling? Decisions based on verbal probabilities: Decision bias or decision by belief sampling? Hidehito Honda (hitohonda.02@gmail.com) Graduate School of Arts and Sciences, The University of Tokyo 3-8-1, Komaba,

More information

A POWER STRUGGLE: BETWEEN- VS. WITHIN-SUBJECTS DESIGNS IN DEDUCTIVE REASONING RESEARCH

A POWER STRUGGLE: BETWEEN- VS. WITHIN-SUBJECTS DESIGNS IN DEDUCTIVE REASONING RESEARCH Psychologia, 2004, 47, 277 296 A POWER STRUGGLE: BETWEEN- VS. WITHIN-SUBJECTS DESIGNS IN DEDUCTIVE REASONING RESEARCH Valerie A. THOMPSON 1) and Jamie I. D. CAMPBELL 1) 1) University of Saskatchewan, Canada

More information

CONCEPT LEARNING WITH DIFFERING SEQUENCES OF INSTANCES

CONCEPT LEARNING WITH DIFFERING SEQUENCES OF INSTANCES Journal of Experimental Vol. 51, No. 4, 1956 Psychology CONCEPT LEARNING WITH DIFFERING SEQUENCES OF INSTANCES KENNETH H. KURTZ AND CARL I. HOVLAND Under conditions where several concepts are learned concurrently

More information

2. Which of the following is not an element of McGuire s chain of cognitive responses model? a. Attention b. Comprehension c. Yielding d.

2. Which of the following is not an element of McGuire s chain of cognitive responses model? a. Attention b. Comprehension c. Yielding d. Chapter 10: Cognitive Processing of Attitudes 1. McGuire s (1969) model of information processing can be best described as which of the following? a. Sequential b. Parallel c. Automatic 2. Which of the

More information

Syllogistic reasoning time: Disconfirmation disconfirmed

Syllogistic reasoning time: Disconfirmation disconfirmed Psychonomic Bulletin & Review 2003, 10 (1), 184-189 Syllogistic reasoning time: Disconfirmation disconfirmed VALERIE A. THOMPSON, CHRISTOPHER L. STRIEMER, RHETT REIKOFF, RAYMOND W. GUNTER, and JAMIE I.

More information

Fukuoka University of Education

Fukuoka University of Education Tomoko Sugimura sugitomo@fukuoka-edu.ac.jp Fukuoka University of Education 18 5 6 facial perception, gender-discrimination, young children Developmental studies have demonstrated that young children inaccurately

More information

Chapter 02. Basic Research Methodology

Chapter 02. Basic Research Methodology Chapter 02 Basic Research Methodology Definition RESEARCH Research is a quest for knowledge through diligent search or investigation or experimentation aimed at the discovery and interpretation of new

More information

INTERVIEWS II: THEORIES AND TECHNIQUES 5. CLINICAL APPROACH TO INTERVIEWING PART 1

INTERVIEWS II: THEORIES AND TECHNIQUES 5. CLINICAL APPROACH TO INTERVIEWING PART 1 INTERVIEWS II: THEORIES AND TECHNIQUES 5. CLINICAL APPROACH TO INTERVIEWING PART 1 5.1 Clinical Interviews: Background Information The clinical interview is a technique pioneered by Jean Piaget, in 1975,

More information

The Probability of Conditionals: The Psychological Evidence

The Probability of Conditionals: The Psychological Evidence In Press, Mind & Language The Probability of Conditionals: The Psychological Evidence David E Over Jonathan St B T Evans David E. Over Department of Psychology University of Sunderland Sunderland SR6 0DD,

More information

A. Indicate the best answer to each the following multiple-choice questions (20 points)

A. Indicate the best answer to each the following multiple-choice questions (20 points) Phil 12 Fall 2012 Directions and Sample Questions for Final Exam Part I: Correlation A. Indicate the best answer to each the following multiple-choice questions (20 points) 1. Correlations are a) useful

More information

Indicative and counterfactual only if conditionals

Indicative and counterfactual only if conditionals Indicative and counterfactual only if conditionals Suzanne M. Egan a, *, Juan A. García-Madruga b, Ruth M.J. Byrne c a Department of Psychology, Mary Immaculate College, University of Limerick, South Circular

More information

Conditional Reasoning

Conditional Reasoning JOURNAL OF VERBAL LEARNING AND VERBAL BEHAVIOR 18, 199--223 (t979) Conditional Reasoning SANDRA L. MARCUS AND LANCE J. RIPS University of Chicago Several techniques have been developed to examine how people

More information

Truth Table Task: Working Memory Load, Latencies and Perceived. Relevance

Truth Table Task: Working Memory Load, Latencies and Perceived. Relevance Truth Table Task: Working Memory Load, Latencies and Perceived Relevance Aline Sevenants (Aline.Sevenants@ppw.kuleuven.be) Kristien Dieussaert (Kristien.Dieussaert@ppw.kuleuven.be) Walter Schaeken (Walter.Schaeken@ppw.kuleuven.be)

More information

Comment on McLeod and Hume, Overlapping Mental Operations in Serial Performance with Preview: Typing

Comment on McLeod and Hume, Overlapping Mental Operations in Serial Performance with Preview: Typing THE QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF EXPERIMENTAL PSYCHOLOGY, 1994, 47A (1) 201-205 Comment on McLeod and Hume, Overlapping Mental Operations in Serial Performance with Preview: Typing Harold Pashler University of

More information

Business Statistics Probability

Business Statistics Probability Business Statistics The following was provided by Dr. Suzanne Delaney, and is a comprehensive review of Business Statistics. The workshop instructor will provide relevant examples during the Skills Assessment

More information

Learning Deterministic Causal Networks from Observational Data

Learning Deterministic Causal Networks from Observational Data Carnegie Mellon University Research Showcase @ CMU Department of Psychology Dietrich College of Humanities and Social Sciences 8-22 Learning Deterministic Causal Networks from Observational Data Ben Deverett

More information

Confirmation, Falsification, and Fallibility

Confirmation, Falsification, and Fallibility Confirmation, Falsification, and Fallibility Phil 12: Logic and Decision Making Winter 2010 UC San Diego 1/15/2010 1 1 Review Key feature of scientific reasoning: confirming or falsifying hypotheses based

More information

Chapter 7. Mental Representation

Chapter 7. Mental Representation Chapter 7 Mental Representation Mental Representation Mental representation is a systematic correspondence between some element of a target domain and some element of a modeling (or representation) domain.

More information

Tense, Aspect, and Temporal Reasoning

Tense, Aspect, and Temporal Reasoning THINKING AND REASONING, 1996, 2 (4), 309 327 309 Tense, Aspect, and Temporal Reasoning W. Schaeken Laboratory of Experimental Psychology, Leuven, Belgium P.N. Johnson-Laird Princeton University, USA G.

More information