General ecological information supports engagement with affordances for higher cognition

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "General ecological information supports engagement with affordances for higher cognition"

Transcription

1 General ecological information supports engagement with affordances for higher cognition Jelle Bruineberg 1 Anthony Chemero 2,3 Erik Rietveld 4 Received: 1 March 2017 / Accepted: 1 February 2018 The Author(s) This article is an open access publication Abstract In this paper, we address the question of how an agent can guide its behavior with respect to aspects of the sociomaterial environment that are not sensorily present. A simple example is how an animal can relate to a food source while only sensing a pheromone, or how an agent can relate to beer, while only the refrigerator is directly sensorily present. Certain cases in which something is absent have been characterized by others as requiring higher cognition. An example of this is how during the design process architects can let themselves be guided by the future behavior of visitors to an exhibit they are planning. The main question is what the sociomaterial environment and the skilled agent are like, such that they can relate to each other in these ways. We argue that this requires an account of the regularities in the environment. Introducing the notion of general ecological information, we will give an account of these regularities in terms of constraints, information and the form of life or ecological niche. In the first part of the paper, we will introduce the skilled intentionality framework as conceptualizing a special case of an animal s informational coupling with the environment namely skilled action. We will show how skilled agents can pick up on the regularities in the environment and let their behavior be guided by the practices in the form of life. This conceptual framework is important for radical embodied and enactive cognitive science, because it allows these increasingly influential paradigms B Jelle Bruineberg j.bruineberg@gmail.com 1 Institute for Logic, Language and Computation (ILLC), University of Amsterdam, Oude Turfmarkt 141, 1012 GC Amsterdam, Netherlands 2 Center for Cognition, Action and Perception, University of Cincinnati, Cincinnati, OH, USA 3 Department of Philosophy, University of Cincinnati, Cincinnati, OH, USA 4 AMC/ILLC/Amsterdam Brain and Cognition, University of Amsterdam, Amsterdam, Netherlands

2 to extend their reach to forms of higher cognition such as long-term planning and imagination. Keywords Affordances Ecological psychology Information Higher cognition Imagination Intentionality Introduction The main theoretical concepts of ecological psychology are affordance and ecological information (Gibson 1979/2015). Affordances are possibilities for action provided by the environment. Ecological information is the set of structures and regularities in the environment that allow an animal to engage with affordances. An important open question is how far the applicability of the affordance-framework reaches. Important theoretical developments have been made concerning the concept of affordances in order for it to be applicable to more socio-cultural aspects of human and animal activities (Chemero 2003a, 2009; Heft 2001; Reed 1996; Rietveld and Kiverstein 2014; Stoffregen 2003). In this paper, we investigate how we should conceptualize the corresponding notion of ecological information. For some of Gibson s later followers (e.g. Turvey et al. 1981), information is to be understood in terms of lawful relationships between structures in the environment and patterns in light, vibrations, and the like. On this account, affordances are perceivable in virtue of the availability of structures in the ambient array (say, a light pattern) that lawfully specify the presence of affordances. At the same time, Gibson himself states that understanding the affordances of things and other humans comprises the whole realm of social significance for human beings (1979/2015, p. 121). That is to say, ecological psychology is supposed to be able to deal with the full range of human social activities, not just with simple sensorimotor coordination. There is a tension between this emphasis on lawful specification and the claim that affordances can be applied to the whole domain of human interactions. Some authors take a narrow approach, limiting affordances exclusively to those action possibilities that are lawfully specified by information (e.g. Turvey et al. 1981; Runeson and Frykholm 1983; Golonka 2015; Golonka and Wilson 2016), while others understand affordances more broadly, relating them to the full range of our human form of life, structured by conventions, customs, socio-cultural practices, or other regularities (Costall 1999; Heft2001; Rietveld and Kiverstein 2014; Bruineberg et al. 2016; Van Dijk and Rietveld 2017). These two strands of research use different definitions of affordances (see Chemero 2003a; Rietveld and Kiverstein 2014) and require a different account of information. 1 In this paper we focus on the human form of life in all its richness and therefore take the broader approach. We are concerned with the 1 This also means that the broader understanding of affordances can do justice to (situated) normativity (Rietveld 2008; Chemero 2009) and the more restrictive (law-based) understanding cannot, which limits the extent in which the latter type of account is able to deal with many kinds of higher cognition.

3 informational structures that are able to support the whole realm of skilled human activities. 2 We will argue that what we call the human form of life is replete with (partially non-lawful) regularities that support our interactions with the environment. These regularities do not just support visually guided actions, but also activities that are traditionally seen as higher cognition such as imagination and long-term planning. In the first section of this paper, we present the Skilled Intentionality Framework (SIF) (Rietveld and Kiverstein 2014; Bruineberg and Rietveld 2014; Van Dijk and Rietveld 2017; Rietveld, Denys and van Westen forthcoming), a philosophical, ecological-enactive approach to understand the situated and affective embodied mind. SIF follows the guidelines of radical embodied cognitive science (Chemero 2009) to account for cognition, action, and perception in terms of dynamical systems theory and organism-environment coupling, and without invoking mental representations. In the second section of the paper we present different ways to analyse the structure of the human form of life and identify the notion of a constraint as a useful term in which to understand both lawful and non-lawful regularities. In the third section of the paper, we analyse how regularities in the form of life can support forms of cognition that are typically seen as forms of higher cognition. 1 The skilled intentionality framework The basic phenomenon that we are interested in, in this paper, is how a skilled animal can coordinate its behavior with a complex and dynamical environment. By this we mean that the animal is sensorily coupled to only a locally present aspect of its environment and still is able to coordinate its behavior with respect to distal aspects of the ecological niche. This requires an understanding of the relations between aspects of the environment such that a skilled agent can, based on its skills and learning history, coordinate adequately with it. Before we can move to the environmental regularities presupposed in this coupling, we first present the animal-environment coupling that forms the background of this paper. We will look at this organism-environment coupling in terms of three complementary perspectives: normativity, intentionality, and dynamics. First, the animal s coupling with the regularities in the environment is about appropriate behavior: for example there is something distinctively inadequate about waiting for a train in the middle of a meadow. Thanks to an extended process of the education of attention, mature actors have been introduced into their ecological niche by more experienced practitioners and are typically able to act in appropriate ways in concrete situations they encounter; they have become skilled (Rietveld 2008). Second, we follow the phenomenological tradition of Heidegger and Merleau-Ponty in realizing that our skills give us a distinct mode of intentional access to the world. The skilled animal perceives its environment in terms of the action possibilities that matter to it. Skilled access to relevant aspects of the world is the norm in cognition, not an exception (Noë 2 It is an open and interesting question to what extent these informational structures for higher cognition figure in the form of life of other animals as well. A comparative study is beyond the scope of this paper.

4 2012; Rietveld et al. Forthcoming; Ingold 2011). Third, from a dynamicist perspective we can understand skilled agency in terms of the dynamics of animal-environment systems, including the neurodynamics embedded or nested in the dynamics of the entire brain-body-environment system (Chiel and Beer 1997; Byrge et al. 2014). The skilled intentionality framework (SIF) attempts to integrate these three perspectives on an agent s interactions with the environment in one framework. Skilled intentionality is defined as the selective engagement with multiple affordances simultaneously. Some of the affordances we encounter in a specific situation go unnoticed, others solicit an action. Work by Rietveld (2008, 2012) and by Withagen et al. (2012, 2017) has shown that ecological psychology needs to distinguish between affordances and invitations or solicitations. We 3 have defined affordances at the level of the form of life as a whole (the ecological niche), namely as relations between aspects of the sociomaterial environment and abilities available in form of life (Rietveld and Kiverstein 2014). For understanding the engagement of a particular individual agent we need to look at the following two relata: the agent s ability and the aspect of the sociomaterial environment (Chemero 2003b, 2009). The notion of affordances characterizes what is possible for agents to do. Solicitations, on the other hand, characterizes what stands out for the individual agent as relevant to do in a particular situation. While sitting at a desk writing a journal article, there are lots of things an academic could do: watering the plants, rearranging books, going home early. However, in the current context the solicitations are, if all goes well, limited to the keyboard, the screen, a cup of coffee, and a small pile of papers. These solicitations or attracting affordances involve an experienced tension of something that stands out to be done (Merleau-Ponty 1945/2002; Dreyfus and Kelly 2007). The theory of affordances therefore needs a theory of agency or skilled intentionality, of how an individual agent can be selectively open to only the relevant affordances in a given situation. In Bruineberg and Rietveld (2014), we have developed a largely Gibsonian and Merleau-Pontyian account of skilled intentionality, which also complements the account of information that we will develop in this article. We have characterized skilled intentionality as the organism s tendency towards an optimal grip on a whole field of solicitations. In order to tend towards grip, we have to be selectively open to only the relevant affordances. We have argued that selective openness to affordances is constituted by the skilled animal s anticipatory dynamics, understood in terms of self-organizing states of action readiness, which are forms of action preparation (see also Bruineberg et al. 2016; Rietveld et al. Forthcoming; Frijda 2007). A key fact about skilled action is that of all the things an academic could do in her office, the vast majority of actions would be inappropriate, weird or forbidden. Her selective openness to affordances is appropriate with respect to a socio-cultural practice or form of life (Rietveld and Kiverstein 2014; Wittgenstein 1953, 1993): The form of life of a kind of animal consists of behavioral patterns, i.e., relatively stable and regular ways of doing things. For humans, these regular patterns in people s activities are manifest in normative behaviors, customs and conventions in communities. That 3 In the following, the pronoun we will be used for any work authored by at least one of the authors of this paper.

5 is to say, human beings share not only biology, but also embedding in sociocultural practices. We share more or less stable ways of living with others (cf. feste Lebensformen, ; Wittgenstein 1993, p. 397). (Rietveld and Kiverstein 2014). The richness of affordances here and now for the academic are available because she partakes in the form of life of humans and socio-cultural practices of academics, Macbook users etc. At the same time, her participation in these practices also limits which affordances can stand out as relevant in a given context. When she enters the university library, she adapts her gait, she will whisper rather than talk out loud and will switch her phone to silence-mode. As such her activities also contribute to the regular way of going on; to maintaining the conventions and socio-cultural practice of the library. On the one hand, SIF attempts to provide an accurate conceptualization of skilled action; on the other hand, the question is how such episodes of skilled action are possible. Skilled intentionality, i.e. coordinating with multiple relevant affordances simultaneously, requires the animal to be sensitive to and adapt to regularities and structures that are there in the environment. In the rest of this paper, we explore how this selective sensitivity is possible, and how to conceptualize the regularities that are there in the environment. We will see that these regularities involve the whole form of life. This brings us, in the last section, a step closer to how skilled intentionality might be applicable to what is traditionally understood as higher cognition. 2 The structure of the environment The central question of this section is the following: what is the structure of the world at the ecological scale such that animals can couple with it in ways that result in organized, adaptive and creative behavior? An observation made by a long list of thinkers in philosophy, psychology and biology, is that the world at the ecological scale is quite unlike the world as typically studied by physics (von Uexkull 1934/1992; Merleau- Ponty 2003; Jonas 1966/2001; Gibson 1979/2015; Ingold 2000, 2011; Thompson 2007). One reason for this is the environment of the animal is not the equilibrium world of Newtonian physics and classical thermodynamics, but rather an environment full with optical, acoustic, vibrational and pheromonal fluxes and patterns, partly generated by the movement and the presence of the animal itself. In The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception (1979/2015), Gibson devotes nearly half the book on the structure of the environment such that animals can directly perceive it. For Gibson, the main concept involved in understanding the direct coupling of the organism with the affordances in the environment is that of ecological information. Ecological information is traditionally understood as a relation between energy in the medium (in the form of light, vibrations etc.), and the substances and surfaces of the environment. Structured light from, for instance, the sun bounces of the surfaces and structures in the environment so that at each point of observation, the light carries information about the structures it has bounced of off. Gibson goes to great pains to show that the information in the environment is rich enough to be able to specify the structures and surfaces in the environment and the perceiver s relationship to these structures. For Gibson:

6 [t]he central question for the theory of affordances is not whether they exist and are real, but whether information is available in the ambient light for perceiving them (Gibson 1979/2015, p. 140) For example, Sedgewick (1973) points out that the horizon cuts across objects at a height that is equal to the height of the point of observation. That is to say, whenever light is reflected to some point of observation from the horizon, and from some object between that point and the horizon, then the light at that point of observation can be used to perceive affordances related to the relative height of that object and the observer, such as the reachability and the pass-under-ability of an object for an observer. Some of Gibson s most influential later followers (e.g. Turvey et al. 1981) focused on information provided by lawful relationships between structures in the environment and patterns in light, vibrations, and the like. However, importantly, lawful relations are not sufficient to account for the richness and diversity of the affordances available in the human form of life (Rietveld and Kiverstein 2014). The overwhelming majority of affordances in human social relations are not lawfully specified by the energy in the environment, but are determined in part by socio-cultural practices, such as conventions and customs, or other regularities. For instance, a colleague might make coffee every morning and put it in a thermos. The thermos normally affords pouring coffee, despite the fact that occasionally the colleague is ill, and the thermos is empty, or contains the cold coffee of the day before. Although these regularities are not strictly law-like, since there can be exceptions (like in this case of illness), they do form the basis for the majority of our everyday skillful engagement with the environment in the human form of life. We will see that this is crucial. As mentioned above, for Gibson, understanding the affordances of things and other humans comprises the whole realm of social significance for human beings (Gibson 1979/2015, p. 121). That is to say, ecological psychology is supposed to be able to deal with the full range of human social activities, not just with simple sensorimotor coordination. In the human form of life, these activities include creativity, long-term planning and imagination. Although the law-based notion of information is able to couple the light hitting our retina with the substances and surfaces in the environment, it is ill-equipped to couple us to the intricate patterns in human sociomaterial practices. Still, human living systems rely on these latter patterns of activities or regularities for most of the distinctively human things that they do. For instance, the supermarket at the corner correlates reliably enough with the presence of bananas to enable bananaoriented behavior, even though every now and then the bananas happen to be out of stock there. Lawful and general ecological information In this paper, we will therefore distinguish between lawful ecological information and general ecological information. The former notion, especially as used by Turvey et al. (1981), pertains to a lawful regularity in the ecological niche between structure at a point p in a medium and an aspect of the environment at point q such that there is a 1:1 specifying relationship between p and q. When an animal is at p, itcan be perceptually coupled to the affordances of q. We will call this restricted notion of ecological information lawful ecological information. In order to account for the

7 sociomaterial character of the environment in the human ecological niche, we argue that a more general account of ecological information is required (henceforth general ecological information). General ecological information is any regularity in the ecological niche between aspects of the environment, x and y, such that the occurrence of aspect x makes the occurrence of aspect y likely. Because of the regular relation between the aspects of the (sociomaterial) environment x and y, general ecological information allows an animal to couple to a distal (i.e. not sensorily present) aspect of the sociomaterial environment. General ecological information pertains to the ways in which aspects of the environment tend to occur together, like smoke and fire, an object and a shadow, or a pub and beer. Of course, an individual s adaptive behavior requires that the animal is able to couple to the relevant aspect of the environment. This depends on the abilities of an agent and the properties of the aspect of the environment i.e. a blind animal can t couple to a pattern in the light, and a human can only couple to the message on his phone by coupling to the light that shines off of it. General ecological information is not limited to aspects of the environment that are sensorily present: something (say a bird of prey, aspect y) does not need to be sensorily present to get me ready to act on its affordances, because its shadow (the shadow of the bird, environmental aspect x) can reliably inform me about the presence of aspect y,even though in exceptional cases the shadow (aspect x) might be caused by a different aspect of the environment than aspect y (say for example aspect z, a kite). This example of the bird and its shadow also shows that the case of such general ecological information due to the regularities in our ecological niche is such that an aspect of the environment constrains (but does not necessarily specify lawfully) another aspect of the environment. Lawful ecological information also depends on regularities in our ecological niche and can best be seen as a special case of general ecological information. Lawful ecological information is a special case, or subclass, of general ecological information understood from the perspective of regularities: all regularities between aspects of the environment constitute general ecological information, but only regularities that determine (rather than constrain) the state of another aspect of the environment constitute lawful ecological information. 4 Our notion of ecological information 5 (both lawful and general) pertains to regular relations between aspects of the environment (patterns, events, substances and surfaces etc.). This notion of ecological information is minimal, cheap and ubiquitous, in the sense that it is present whenever there are regularities. It is informational in the sense that regularities that hold between aspects of the environment allow animals to be informed about one aspect of the environment by the presence of another aspect. To avoid misunderstandings, we stress that this sort of information does not imply 4 As we will discuss below, this does not deny the fact that local lawful constraints can enable the use of conventional constraints by a particular individual. 5 Since this paper only deals with ecological information and not with other kinds of information, we will in the following use information and ecological information interchangeably.

8 meaning or aboutness encoded in a signal. 6 Information is nothing over and above these regularities between aspects of the environment. General ecological information and constraint Following situation semantics (Barwise and Perry 1981, 1983) we will use the term constraint for the regularities between situations that reduce possibilities. Whenever there are constraints between types, there is information between tokens. An example that (Chemero 2009) provides is the situation in which there is an unopened beer can on a table in a brightly lit room. Light from the source will reflect off the beer can and off the other surfaces in the environment. At each point in the room in which there is an uninterrupted path from the beer can, there will be light that has reflected of the beer can and is structured in a peculiar way. Due to the natural laws governing the reflection of light off surfaces and textures, the light at any such point in the room will be structured in a very particular way. In this case, there is a lawful constraint connecting the light-structure of type A to the beer-can presence of type B. In virtue of this constraint, the light structure at point p contains information about token beercan-presence b (of type B) at some other point p. Furthermore, and crucially for understanding our proposal, in our socio-cultural practices it is generally the case that unopened beer cans contain beer. Because of these conventional constraints governing cans and their contents, beer-can-presence b being of type B carries information about beer-presence c of type C. That is to say, because of the constraints and regularities, both physical and conventional, the light (ambient array) at some point in the room can carry information about the availability of beer. Importantly, this sociomaterial regularity allows for exceptions: a mistake at the brewery might cause the can to be filled with water rather than beer. In the most basic cases, it is the use of information rather than information itself that is normatively evaluable. 7 In other words, there is nothing wrong (nor right!) about the light bouncing off a beer-can when it is accidentally filled with water. The light-structure of type A specifies beer-can presence no matter what: it carries information about beer-can presence without being able to be right or wrong. It is someone s use of information (by for example drinking the beer or stating that this can contains beer ) that is normatively evaluable. In the case of human made artefacts, on the other hand, both the information itself and its use are normatively evaluable. If, by some other mistake in the factory, soda-cans end up with beer labels, the label misrepresents the contents of the can (even though the light bouncing of the can still specifies a beer-can). In summary, the use of information is always normative; human artifacts that contain information are subject to norms; energy arrays contain information but are not subject to norms. Information pertains to the constraints that exist in the (sociomaterial) environment. These constraints can be necessary, such as the principle of non-contradiction, nomological or lawful, such as the laws of optics, or conventional, such as a thermos containing coffee or a supermarket selling bananas. While ecological psychology has 6 Recall that it is skills that give an individual intentional access to the world (see Sect. 1). 7 Some authors (van Dijk et al. 2015) state that information about implies normative evaluability (i.e. true or false, accurate or inaccurate). They therefore claim that conceiving of information independent of, and prior to, use is inappropriate. See section Information and use for a discussion of their claim.

9 typically focussed on finding lawful constraints, we are interested in the combination of lawful and conventional constrains that allow us to understand the relation between affordances, ecological information and the human form of life in all its complexity. The information induced by conventional constraints differs from the lawful constraint in that it is not exception-free. The light structure of type fridge-presence does not infallibly specify the presence of beer in the fridge, but can still carry information about beer-presence if there is a constraint between the types of fridge-presence and beer-presence. A related notion of constraint-based ecological information, also departing from Barwise and Perry (1983), is proposed by Sverker Runeson (1988, 1989). However, Runeson uses conventional constraints to argue that information is specific even though purely lawful constraints do not specify the layout of the environment. 8 In this paper, we are not committed to the claim that perception needs to be specific in order to guide behavior. Although constraints and regularities serve different purposes, they are not necessarily different things. To give an example: the convention of driving on the right puts constraints on the possible layout of intersections (e.g. the placing of road signs) and the location of the steering wheel in an automobile. The fact that this convention holds across continental Europe is a regularity that allows the exercise of the skill of driving, which was learned at one particular location, all over the continent. Most of a skilled agent s interactions with the environment are far less explicit and articulable. Barwise and Perry (1981) provide the example that what makes someone a skilled basketball player is her extensive implicit knowledge of the constraints that affect her, the ball, and the other things on the court (p. 98). Although, in order to clearly lay out our theory of information, we focus in this paper on relatively common sense and straightforward examples, such as beer cans and fridges, we recognize that ecological psychology is at its best when uncovering non-trivial regularities that agents use to coordinate their behavior, ranging from perceptual variables such as time-toimpact (Lee and Reddish 1981) to multi-modal informational structures enacted by co-performers that constrain the behavior of interacting jazz musicians (Walton et al. 2015). Constraints, information and form of life Now let us try to apply the above account of information to the notion of a form of life. As we have seen before, the form of life of a kind of animal consists of patterns in its behavior, i.e., relatively stable and regular ways of doing things. The notion of a form of life allows us to capture the variety of socio-cultural practices within the human way of life. In the human form of life, the affordances available are related to the whole spectrum of abilities available in our human socio-cultural practices. Wittgenstein shows the dependency of the human form of life on regularities as well as the interwovenness of the material and the socio-cultural aspects of our environment with an example of a familiar practice: 8 One example Runeson discusses is the Ames-room (Wittreich 1952), a spatially distorted room which gets interpreted as a rectangular room, giving rise to size illusions. Runeson argues that although alternative configurations are geometrically possible, they do violate conventional and pragmatic constraints such as that rooms have rectangular and horizontal floors and vertical walls.

10 [ ] if things were quite different from what they actually are - if there were for instance no characteristic expressions of pain, of fear, of joy; if rule became exception and exception rule; or if both became phenomena of roughly equal frequency this would make our normal language-games lose their point. The procedure of putting a lump of cheese on a balance and fixing the price by the turn of the scale would lose its point if it frequently happened for such lumps suddenly grew or shrank for no obvious reason. (Wittgenstein 1953, p. 48, PI 142). In our human environment, the conventional practices (say, of weighing cheese in order to price it), can only exist in virtue of lawful stabilities in nature (most objects having a relatively stable weight over time). The interwovenness of the material and the socio-cultural aspects of the form of life allows for a multiplicity of such dependencies. There is a regularity between the location of the steering wheel in a car, the material layout of roads and the sociocultural norm of driving on the right. The fact that only driving left and right exist as stable norms might further be due to the fact that human and automobile locomotion takes place on surfaces and in gravitational circumstances that rule out passing on top or below. For scientific purposes, it might be interesting to investigate the historical or causal priority of some of these constraints; right-hand traffic existed before cars existed so the former constrained the latter and not vice versa. One might very well argue that the constancy of the gravitational force and the properties of cheese constrain and make possible the practice of weighing cheese. But from the perspective of a participant in the practice, what exactly brings these regularities about is irrelevant. All that is required is a sensitivity to the regularities that are there in the form of life such that, when for example approaching an intersection, the affordances that show up as relevant are in line with the regular ways in which things are done in the particular practice. To use another example of Barwise and Perry (1981), a skilled veterinarian does not need to possess a theory of how X-rays work in order to perceive that the dog s leg is broken. For the veterinarian, it suffices to be sensitive to the constraint the state of the dog s leg puts on the pattern on the X-ray, even though this constraint itself is the result of a complex interplay between the dog s leg, electrons and the detector. In effect, given the physical, technological, and conventional practices in which the veterinarian engages, and her skills acquired in these practices, she can see through the X-ray to the dog s leg in the same way that she can see through the window to the trees outside. In both cases, there is information available to enable perception. Many of our everyday activities are founded on conventional constraints. For example, at home one can look out of a window and see the roof of an arriving tram. Based on familiarity with the sociomaterial practice of tram 3 in Amsterdam, one can apprehend that this is the end point of the tram and that normally it will stop for a few minutes and everyone will get out, sometimes with the exception of the people working on the tram. There is a constraint between the arrival and the departure of the tram. There is a constraint between the clock of the tram driver and the fact that the tram is departing. There is a constraint between the clock of the tram driver and the clock hanging in the kitchen. As such, the sociomaterial environment that we inhabit is replete with

11 constraints. It might be next to impossible (and unnecessary) to figure out how these constraints come about, but it is the existence of these constraints that enable us to coordinate our behavior with respect to aspects of the environment to which we are not sensorily coupled. Just as the veterinarian is able to perceive what needs to be done to the dog s leg while being sensorily coupled to the X-ray, we can perceive it is time to leave to take the tram by looking at a watch. It is an open question how far back one can push the requirement for sensory coupling. Even if the tram were not yet actually present, we could still see the tram stop sign, we could still see the rails that lead it to, for example, the street called Ceintuurbaan in Amsterdam. In fact, nothing much is changed by the arrival of the tram because one can be familiar with this entire sociomaterial practice and attuned to the regularity of the arrival tram 3: another tram will arrive soon. Even if the curtain is closed and we do not see the tram, then we can still see that we are in the familiar apartment, a place that is constantly placed next to the tram 3 stop. The clock in the kitchen might still inform us that we have to leave now to catch the next tram. Anyone with the right abilities and sensitivity to the regularities that allow one to reliably couple to the affordances will be able to coordinate with these distal aspects of the form of life in virtue of information about more local aspects, we suggest. So no direct sensorily coupling with an object (e.g. the tram) is necessary in order for an agent to be open to its affordances. Part of being skilled, of being at home in the situation, is exactly that of being able to adequately coordinate actions with respect to a great number of aspects of the environment in virtue of the presence of a small number of things that reliably covary with these aspects. Needless to say, all of the constraints just mentioned are fallible, and none are lawful: the clock might be fast, the tram might be late, or the tram stop might be temporarily relocated due to construction work. Still, crucially, normally they provide the regularities that allow one to skillfully coordinate behavior in a form of life. There are a few things to note here. First, this notion of regularity is not inconsistent with the Gibsonian account of lawful ecological information. Lawful ecological information, understood traditionally as a 1:1 specifying relationship between the structure of the light and the substances and surfaces of the environment, is a special case of the notion of general ecological information as we develop it here. When you grasp the cup of coffee in front of you, the structure of the light at some point p might fully specify the location and structure of the cup, such that it affords grasping. What we want to resist, however, is that affordances are limited exclusively to cases where we are lawfully coupled to an affordance. For a skilled agent at home in her ecological niche, it is sufficient to be coupled to some relevant aspect of the sociomaterial practice even when that aspect is not present in the current environment. Even though we are not visually coupled to the beer inside the unopened beer can, the beer inside can still solicit us. Even with the curtains drawn, the tram can still afford catching due to the regularities in the form of life mentioned above. Second, note that the account of regularities that we propose is an interesting case of niche construction: many of the constraints and regularities we have talked about in this section are products of human invention. The construction of clock time, especially the construction of time zones, led to a great explosion of things happening simultaneously

12 or sequentially. A mobile phone can tell us when the tram arrives, even a tram in another city. It is an impressive technological feat that a pattern of light and sound at a point of observation somewhere else in a faraway country can appear in real time on a laptop in a Skype conversation. That is to say, it is not just the construction of material structures that change our ways of living, but also people actively inducing patterns that make events happen at regular moments. Within our framework, the regularities of time keeping induce new constraints between situations (cf. van Dijk and Withagen 2016). Without having to look out of the window, the light bouncing off the clock in the kitchen informs us that we should leave now in order to catch the tram and make it to the appointment on time. Third, we want to be clear that the abilities that allow us to be informed by conventional constraints are not independent of lawful constraints. Indeed, the use of conventional constraints to couple to distal features of the world depends on the use of local lawful constraints. An apartment dweller can be coupled to the distant tram via the conventions connecting its arrival to the printed schedule, the way that the schedule constrains the actions of the conductor, and the conventions according to which she and the train conductor set their clocks. But she can only be coupled to the tram via these conventional constraints if she is also lawfully coupled to, for example, the clock in her kitchen via the lawful, optical constraints governing the light reflected off the hands of the clock s hour and minute hands. In this section, we have introduced the notions of lawful ecological information and general ecological information. Lawful ecological information pertains to the currently most influential Gibsonian notion, especially as used and developed by Turvey et al. (1981). It is defined as a lawful regularity in the ecological niche between structure at a point p in a medium and an aspect of the environment at point q such that there is a 1:1 specifying relationship between p and q. General ecological information is defined as any regularity in the ecological niche between different aspects of the environment (xand y) such that the occurrence of x makes y likely. The regularities in the ecological niche can be captured by the notion of constraint. Constraints are relationships such that something being in a particular state constrains the state in which something else can be. For example, an aluminum can having a beer logo constrains the possible contents of the can, or a shadow having a particular shape constrains the object from which the shadow originates. The nature of these constraints can be the object of scientific research, but for the skilled agent it suffices to be sensitive to these constraints. Constraints might be brought about by complex causal structures (such as X-rays), by ecological laws (such as optics), conventions (driving on the right) or habits (beer in the fridge). In the human form of life all these constraints are meshed together. In the next Sect. 3, we will discuss how our notion of general ecological information can contribute to our understanding of episodes of higher cognition, but first we would like to deal with a potential objection to our account. Information and use One problem that emerges for a constraint-based notion of information, as proposed by us in this paper, has been articulated by Withagen and van der Kamp (2010). They argue that the extension of ecological information to include non-specifying

13 constraints poses, among others, the problem that information cannot specify the object of perception. If a structure in the array covaries with multiple aspects of the environment, then the array itself cannot individuate the object of perception. In other words: why does the light structure of type fridge-presence specify beer-presence rather than, say, milk-presence, even though both are reliably present? Withagen and Van der Kamp sketch two possible solutions to this problem. The first is to deny that information has to specify the perceptual object and to maintain that in fact the array carries information about all these aspects of the environment. Some internal process (such as an intention) then further determines which of these aspects is perceived. Withagen and Van der Kamp dismiss this option for they claim that a theory of information should, ideally, explain the object of perception and postulating internal process necessary to individuate the perceptual object violates the principles of ecological psychology. An alternative solution, they hold, is to define information relationally and to deny that the array carries information independent of use (see also van Dijk et al. 2015). Following developmental systems theory (Oyama 1985/2000, 2000), they argue that information is not intrinsic to a structure (such as an optic array or a strand of DNA), but relative to a system for whom that structure makes a difference. As such, the impact of sensory stimuli is a joint function of the stimuli and the sensing organism; the effective stimulus is defined by the organism that is affected by it (Oyama 1985/2000, p. 38). We want to argue that although our particular constraint-based notion of information and the usage-based notion of information are substantially different, their resulting treatment of perception and action are not. First of all, Withagen and Van der Kamp make clear that they do not wish to deny the highly structured energy patterns in the ambient arrays that animals can use (p. 158, our italics). For reasons mentioned above, they just take issue with equating information with such patterns. Constraints are necessary, but not sufficient for information, according to Withagen and Van der Kamp. We take it that both the usage-based and our constraint-based approach to information agree that perception is the result of a system of constraints interacting with a perceptual system sensitive to only some of these constraints. Constraint-based theorists like us define one of the relata (the constraints) as information; usage-based theorists define the relation itself as information. Consequently, for the former information is cheap, ubiquitous and user-independent, while for the latter it is rare, special and user-relative. We suggest then that as long as the different notions of information are kept apart, they are not incompatible. Information-as-constraint pertains to the regularities in the environment independent of use by a particular individual and does not specify either the object of perception or what is relevant. Information-as-use pertains to the relational significance of an environment for an agent and does specify the object of perception and what is relevant. On our view, information and affordances are present in the ecological niche independent of the use by a particular agent. However, the animal cannot attune to all of these affordances at the same time, it needs to be selectively open or sensitive to only the relevant ones. While Withagen and Van der Kamp are worried that any notion of information that does not specify the object of perception requires some sort of internal enrichment (e.g. an intention) in order to arrive at the object of perception,

14 we, instead, argue that it just takes a process of selective openness to arrive at only the relevant affordances, or solicitations. 9 Despite these differences, the user-based and our constraint based approach agree, contrary to traditional ecological psychology, that perception and action should be understood as a function of the agent-environment system as a whole. To understand an animal s directedness to its environment it is not sufficient to merely focus on the constraints and regularities in the form of life, but also to focus on how an agent is able to selectively be sensitive to or be invited by some affordances and not others. We have discussed in earlier work how to conceive of selective openness to affordances within radical embodied cognitive science and the Skilled Intentionality Framework (Chemero 2003a; Bruineberg and Rietveld 2014; Bruineberg et al. 2016). 3 Information for engagement with affordances for higher cognition In earlier work, we have discussed certain kinds of affordances for higher cognition (Rietveld and Kiverstein 2014; Rietveld and Brouwers 2017; Van Dijk and Rietveld 2017). For example, the possibility of judging correctly that this paper is written in English, or possibilities for imagining a future building. What is the nature of constraints and information involved in engaging with such an affordance? Based on the theory developed so far in this paper, this kind of affordance is to be understood in the same way as affordances for mundane activities like grasping a cup in the context of a particular situation. How do we couple with what is absent in the sense of not immediately present to one of the senses? Notice that already in the very definition of an affordance there is an interesting notion of absence. Affordances are possibilities for action, and those actions must occur in the future. You could get your telephone out of your pocket now. Even when we are ready to act on an affordance, we are prepared for something that we could do, but what we could do is not yet done, so in a sense something is not yet there. There is no light bouncing off the future. This implies that there is something necessarily anticipatory or future-oriented in the perception of an affordance (Turvey 1992). This absence only increases when the affordances become more complex. Crucially, we want to use affordances to talk about higher order cognition in a way that views cognition as an unmediated contact of the skilled person with the regularities in the environment. The regularities apply at many different spatial and temporal scales, including at the scale of sociocultural practices. The individual s skills (most of which are acquired via a process of education of attention in sociocultural practices) provide access to the regularities of the world; some skills are primarily sensorimotor, such as grasping a cup, others are typically characterized as more abstract skills (e.g. imagination, but also appropriately grasping your own coffee cup rather than someone else s from those on the table in front of you). Part of being 9 The problem for the user-based account is to explain how the agent is selectively sensitive to some constraints and not to others, or, in their own words, how an agent modulates the invitational character, or tunes the coupling strength (Withagen et al. 2017). of some affordances and not of others without presupposing some sort of internal agent or mysterious process that does this tuning.

15 skilled is knowing how to attune to the relevant pieces of information; i.e. coordinate with the relevant aspects of the environment. Imagination: general ecological information and anticipatory states of action readiness In this section, we will discuss some of the regularities involved in a specific case of imagination. Let us consider the real-life example of a team of architects designing an art installation, The End of Sitting, for the Chicago Architecture Biennial, while having previous built a similar installation in Amsterdam. 10 The End of Sitting is a large architectural art installation in which visitors are invited to engage with a landscape of standing affordances. It is a rock-like structure that affords a variety of supported leaning, standing and hanging postures. 11 Moreover, due to the large variety of positions offered and the temporary comfort offered by each of them, the installations affords switching positions about every min (Rietveld et al. 2015; Withagen and Caljouw 2016; Caljouw et al. 2017; Rietveld 2016). In the process of being responsive to the possibility of making the installation for Chicago, the architects are able to anticipate how the installation will be used because they have perceived how it is used in Amsterdam, both by observing visitors and by experiencing it themselves. The way people interact with the installation in Amsterdam is something very human: it is supported standing in different ways. Once one is familiar with how these human practices work in Amsterdam and that the human practices of supported standing in Chicago are sufficiently similar, one can imagine what will happen in the new installation in Chicago even though there are minor differences. But these differences are not radical: people are not leaning against air or against birds or earth worms in Chicago, they are leaning against materials that support leaning and they partake in the human form of life as well. The main differences are related to body posture: on average people are a bit less tall and a bit bigger in Chicago. That is to say, thanks to the similarities there will be a constraint between the practice in Amsterdam and the practice in Chicago, which enables the architects to be informed about the practice in Chicago by observing the practice in Amsterdam. Even though the architects in Amsterdam are not in sensory contact with Chicago in any standard sense, they are able to anticipate how their installation will be used in virtue of regularities concerning human bodies and practices of standing that hold both in Amsterdam and Chicago (plus minor adjustments for differences in body posture). The architects, located in Amsterdam, are in touch with the practice of standing and leaning in Chicago, in a way similar to the thirsty person, situated in a socio-cultural setting in which beer is a common beverage, who perceives a closed beer can is in touch 10 This section discusses one kind of imagination as used by architects in a design process. There might be other forms of imagination, such as for example daydreaming, that require a slightly different analysis. 11 Many human activities can be performed skillfully exactly because they rely on carefully designed niches. However, the design process of a new aspect of a niche itself (for example, a landscape of affordances for supported standing) is neither a blind process, nor a process in which one of the architects has the end result in mind and merely realizes it in the world (Ingold 2013). Rather, the construction of a new aspect of a niche is itself a result of skilled practices enabled by the skills of the architects and the affordance provided by the architecture studio (including for example the possibilities to build cardboard models and to make 3D-drawings) (Rietveld et al. 2015; Rietveld and Brouwers 2017).

Ecological-Enactive Cognition as engaging with a field of relevant affordances: The Skilled Intentionality Framework (SIF)

Ecological-Enactive Cognition as engaging with a field of relevant affordances: The Skilled Intentionality Framework (SIF) Forthcoming in Oxford Hanbook of 4E Cognition Ecological-Enactive Cognition as engaging with a field of relevant affordances: The Skilled Intentionality Framework (SIF) Erik Rietveld, Damiaan Denys & Maarten

More information

Comments on David Rosenthal s Consciousness, Content, and Metacognitive Judgments

Comments on David Rosenthal s Consciousness, Content, and Metacognitive Judgments Consciousness and Cognition 9, 215 219 (2000) doi:10.1006/ccog.2000.0438, available online at http://www.idealibrary.com on Comments on David Rosenthal s Consciousness, Content, and Metacognitive Judgments

More information

Language and Computation, University of Amsterdam, 1090 GE Amsterdam, University of Amsterdam, 1100 DD Amsterdam, The Netherlands;

Language and Computation, University of Amsterdam, 1090 GE Amsterdam, University of Amsterdam, 1100 DD Amsterdam, The Netherlands; Rietveld, E., De Haan, S. & Denys, D (forthcoming), Social affordances in context: What is it that we are bodily responsive to? Invited commentary article on Schilbach et al., BBS, Behavioral and Brain

More information

5.8 Departure from cognitivism: dynamical systems

5.8 Departure from cognitivism: dynamical systems 154 consciousness, on the other, was completely severed (Thompson, 2007a, p. 5). Consequently as Thompson claims cognitivism works with inadequate notion of cognition. This statement is at odds with practical

More information

Eliminative materialism

Eliminative materialism Michael Lacewing Eliminative materialism Eliminative materialism (also known as eliminativism) argues that future scientific developments will show that the way we think and talk about the mind is fundamentally

More information

Skepticism about perceptual content

Skepticism about perceptual content Skepticism about perceptual content phil 93515 Jeff Speaks March 29, 2007 1 Contents v. objects of perception The view that perceptual experiences have contents is the view that perceptual experiences

More information

Thinking the environment aurally An enactive approach to auditory-architectural research and design

Thinking the environment aurally An enactive approach to auditory-architectural research and design 1 Thinking the environment aurally An enactive approach to auditory-architectural research and design Alex Arteaga (Lecture given in the Architecture and Urban Planning section of the conference Invisible

More information

Views of autistic adults on assessment in the early years

Views of autistic adults on assessment in the early years Views of autistic adults on what should be assessed and how assessment should be conducted on children with autism in the early years Summary of autistic adults views on assessment 1. Avoid drawing negative

More information

A Comment on the Absent-Minded Driver Paradox*

A Comment on the Absent-Minded Driver Paradox* Ž. GAMES AND ECONOMIC BEHAVIOR 20, 25 30 1997 ARTICLE NO. GA970508 A Comment on the Absent-Minded Driver Paradox* Itzhak Gilboa MEDS KGSM, Northwestern Uni ersity, E anston, Illinois 60201 Piccione and

More information

The Standard Theory of Conscious Perception

The Standard Theory of Conscious Perception The Standard Theory of Conscious Perception C. D. Jennings Department of Philosophy Boston University Pacific APA 2012 Outline 1 Introduction Motivation Background 2 Setting up the Problem Working Definitions

More information

PSYCHOLOGICAL CONSCIOUSNESS AND PHENOMENAL CONSCIOUSNESS. Overview

PSYCHOLOGICAL CONSCIOUSNESS AND PHENOMENAL CONSCIOUSNESS. Overview Lecture 28-29 PSYCHOLOGICAL CONSCIOUSNESS AND PHENOMENAL CONSCIOUSNESS Overview David J. Chalmers in his famous book The Conscious Mind 1 tries to establish that the problem of consciousness as the hard

More information

Review of Tim Bayne s The Unity of Consciousness

Review of Tim Bayne s The Unity of Consciousness Review of Tim Bayne s The Unity of Consciousness Angela Mendelovici amendel5@uwo.ca July 21, 2011 Tim Bayne, The Unity of Consciousness, Oxford University Press, 2010, 341pp., $55.00 (hbk), ISBN 9780199215386.

More information

Our previous accounts of perceptual experience accepted the phenomenal principle:

Our previous accounts of perceptual experience accepted the phenomenal principle: PHL340 Handout 3: Representationalism 1 Representationalism and the Phenomenal Principle An experience s representational content is the way the world must be if the experience is to be veridical. Representationalism

More information

Recording Transcript Wendy Down Shift #9 Practice Time August 2018

Recording Transcript Wendy Down Shift #9 Practice Time August 2018 Recording Transcript Wendy Down Shift #9 Practice Time August 2018 Hi there. This is Wendy Down and this recording is Shift #9 in our 6 month coaching program. [Excuse that I referred to this in the recording

More information

Representational Content and Phenomenal Character

Representational Content and Phenomenal Character By David Hilbert, Unversity of Illinois at Chicago, Forthcoming in Sage Encyclopedia of Perception QUALIA Perception and thought are often, although not exclusively, concerned with information about the

More information

Appearance properties

Appearance properties Appearance properties phil 93507 Jeff Speaks October 12, 2009 1 The role of appearance properties If we think that spectrum inversion/spectrum shift of certain sorts is possible, and that neither of the

More information

Suppressed Belief. [PENULTIMATE DRAFT: Please consult published version for citation

Suppressed Belief. [PENULTIMATE DRAFT: Please consult published version for citation Suppressed Belief [PENULTIMATE DRAFT: Please consult published version for citation purposes.] Self-knowledge is a special kind of knowledge each of us can have of her own mental states, which is expressed

More information

Spectrum inversion and intentionalism

Spectrum inversion and intentionalism Spectrum inversion and intentionalism phil 93507 Jeff Speaks September 15, 2009 1 What is a spectrum inversion scenario?..................... 1 2 Intentionalism is false because inverts could have in common.........

More information

Durkheim. Durkheim s fundamental task in Rules of the Sociological Method is to lay out

Durkheim. Durkheim s fundamental task in Rules of the Sociological Method is to lay out Michelle Lynn Tey Meadow Jane Jones Deirdre O Sullivan Durkheim Durkheim s fundamental task in Rules of the Sociological Method is to lay out the basic disciplinary structure of sociology. He begins by

More information

Consciousness and Intrinsic Higher- Order Content

Consciousness and Intrinsic Higher- Order Content 1 Consciousness and Intrinsic Higher- Order Content David Rosenthal City University of New York Graduate Center http://web.gc.cuny.edu/cogsci Tucson VII, April 7, 2006 OVERVIEW (Some slides were skipped

More information

Competing Frameworks in Perception

Competing Frameworks in Perception Competing Frameworks in Perception Lesson II: Perception module 08 Perception.08. 1 Views on perception Perception as a cascade of information processing stages From sensation to percept Template vs. feature

More information

Competing Frameworks in Perception

Competing Frameworks in Perception Competing Frameworks in Perception Lesson II: Perception module 08 Perception.08. 1 Views on perception Perception as a cascade of information processing stages From sensation to percept Template vs. feature

More information

Psychology, Neuroscience, and the Consciousness Dilemma. Katalin Balog

Psychology, Neuroscience, and the Consciousness Dilemma. Katalin Balog Psychology, Neuroscience, and the Consciousness Dilemma Katalin Balog In this paper, I present a dilemma for theorizing about the connection between phenomenality (the what it s like character of mental

More information

How do Categories Work?

How do Categories Work? Presentations Logistics Think about what you want to do Thursday we ll informally sign up, see if we can reach consensus. Topics Linear representations of classes Non-linear representations of classes

More information

Ideas in progress/regress. Adaptive Systems. A problem with viability. The world upside-down. A problem with viability. Ecological Adaptation

Ideas in progress/regress. Adaptive Systems. A problem with viability. The world upside-down. A problem with viability. Ecological Adaptation Adaptive Systems Ezequiel Di Paolo Informatics Ecological Adaptation Ideas in progress/regress Ashby did an excellent job in showing how adaptation could be the observable outcome of a system able to reconfigure

More information

The scope of perceptual content, II: properties

The scope of perceptual content, II: properties The scope of perceptual content, II: properties Jeff Speaks November 16, 2009 1 What are the candidates?............................ 1 2 Arguments for inclusion............................. 2 2.1 From

More information

Chapter 6. Attention. Attention

Chapter 6. Attention. Attention Chapter 6 Attention Attention William James, in 1890, wrote Everyone knows what attention is. Attention is the taking possession of the mind, in clear and vivid form, of one out of what seem several simultaneously

More information

Behaviorism: An essential survival tool for practitioners in autism

Behaviorism: An essential survival tool for practitioners in autism Behaviorism: An essential survival tool for practitioners in autism What we re going to do today 1. Review the role of radical behaviorism (RB) James M. Johnston, Ph.D., BCBA-D National Autism Conference

More information

Obstacle- something that obstructs or hinders progress or action.

Obstacle- something that obstructs or hinders progress or action. Obstacle- something that obstructs or hinders progress or action. Notice that there are two main ways that an obstacle gets in the way of progress. The first is that an obstacle may obstruct progress.

More information

CHAPTER 2: PERCEPTION, SELF, AND COMMUNICATION

CHAPTER 2: PERCEPTION, SELF, AND COMMUNICATION Communication Age Connecting and Engaging 2nd Edition Edwards Solutions Manual Full Download: https://testbanklive.com/download/communication-age-connecting-and-engaging-2nd-edition-edwards-solu THE COMMUNICATION

More information

The Vine Assessment System by LifeCubby

The Vine Assessment System by LifeCubby The Vine Assessment System by LifeCubby A Fully Integrated Platform for Observation, Daily Reporting, Communications and Assessment For Early Childhood Professionals and the Families that they Serve Alignment

More information

What Constitutes a Good Contribution to the Literature (Body of Knowledge)?

What Constitutes a Good Contribution to the Literature (Body of Knowledge)? What Constitutes a Good Contribution to the Literature (Body of Knowledge)? Read things that make good contributions to the body of knowledge. The purpose of scientific research is to add to the body of

More information

School of Nursing, University of British Columbia Vancouver, British Columbia, Canada

School of Nursing, University of British Columbia Vancouver, British Columbia, Canada Data analysis in qualitative research School of Nursing, University of British Columbia Vancouver, British Columbia, Canada Unquestionably, data analysis is the most complex and mysterious of all of the

More information

Is it possible to give a philosophical definition of sexual desire?

Is it possible to give a philosophical definition of sexual desire? Issue 1 Spring 2016 Undergraduate Journal of Philosophy Is it possible to give a philosophical definition of sexual desire? William Morgan - The University of Sheffield pp. 47-58 For details of submission

More information

The Mind-Body Problem: Physicalism

The Mind-Body Problem: Physicalism The Mind-Body Problem: Physicalism Physicalism According to physicalism, everything that makes you up is physical, material, spatial, and subject to laws of physics. Because of that, we need not worry

More information

Chapter 7. Mental Representation

Chapter 7. Mental Representation Chapter 7 Mental Representation Mental Representation Mental representation is a systematic correspondence between some element of a target domain and some element of a modeling (or representation) domain.

More information

Chapter 7: Descriptive Statistics

Chapter 7: Descriptive Statistics Chapter Overview Chapter 7 provides an introduction to basic strategies for describing groups statistically. Statistical concepts around normal distributions are discussed. The statistical procedures of

More information

A Direct Object of Perception

A Direct Object of Perception E-LOGOS Electronic Journal for Philosophy 2015, Vol. 22(1) 28 36 ISSN 1211-0442 (DOI 10.18267/j.e-logos.411),Peer-reviewed article Journal homepage: e-logos.vse.cz A Direct Object of Perception Mika Suojanen

More information

U. T. Place, Is consciousness a brain process?

U. T. Place, Is consciousness a brain process? 24.09x Minds and Machines U. T. Place, Is consciousness a brain process? Excerpts from U.T. Place, Is consciousness a brain process?, British Journal of Psychology 47: 44-50, 1956. Place begins by noting

More information

Sensation and Perception

Sensation and Perception 1 Sensation and Perception DR. ARNEL BANAGA SALGADO, Doctor of Psychology (USA) FPM (Ph.D.) Psychology (India) Doctor of Education (Phl) Master of Arts in Nursing (Phl) Master of Arts in Teaching Psychology

More information

Qualitative and Quantitative Approaches Workshop. Comm 151i San Jose State U Dr. T.M. Coopman Okay for non-commercial use with attribution

Qualitative and Quantitative Approaches Workshop. Comm 151i San Jose State U Dr. T.M. Coopman Okay for non-commercial use with attribution Qualitative and Quantitative Approaches Workshop Comm 151i San Jose State U Dr. T.M. Coopman Okay for non-commercial use with attribution This Workshop This is a research skill workshop. This workshop

More information

H.O.T. Theory, Concepts, and Synesthesia: A Reply to Adams and Shreve

H.O.T. Theory, Concepts, and Synesthesia: A Reply to Adams and Shreve H.O.T. Theory, Concepts, and Synesthesia: A Reply to Adams and Shreve Rocco J. Gennaro Abstract: In response to Fred Adams and Charlotte Shreve s (2016) paper entitled What Can Synesthesia Teach Us about

More information

Commentary on The Erotetic Theory of Attention by Philipp Koralus. Sebastian Watzl

Commentary on The Erotetic Theory of Attention by Philipp Koralus. Sebastian Watzl Commentary on The Erotetic Theory of Attention by Philipp Koralus A. Introduction Sebastian Watzl The study of visual search is one of the experimental paradigms for the study of attention. Visual search

More information

Effective Intentions: The Power of Conscious Will

Effective Intentions: The Power of Conscious Will Book Review Effective Intentions: The Power of Conscious Will Alfred R. Mele Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2009 Marco Fenici* fenici@unisi.it Mele s book is a concise analysis of much research in neurophysiology

More information

Foundations for a Science of Social Inclusion Systems

Foundations for a Science of Social Inclusion Systems Foundations for a Science of Social Inclusion Systems Fabio N. Akhras Renato Archer Center of Information Technology Rodovia Dom Pedro I, km 143,6 13089-500 Campinas, São Paulo, Brazil Phone: 0055-19-37466268

More information

On A Distinction Between Access and Phenomenal Consciousness

On A Distinction Between Access and Phenomenal Consciousness On A Distinction Between Access and Phenomenal Consciousness By BRENT SILBY Department of Philosophy University of Canterbury New Zealand Copyright (c) Brent Silby 1998 www.def-logic.com/articles In his

More information

Math HL Chapter 12 Probability

Math HL Chapter 12 Probability Math HL Chapter 12 Probability Name: Read the notes and fill in any blanks. Work through the ALL of the examples. Self-Check your own progress by rating where you are. # Learning Targets Lesson I have

More information

Doing High Quality Field Research. Kim Elsbach University of California, Davis

Doing High Quality Field Research. Kim Elsbach University of California, Davis Doing High Quality Field Research Kim Elsbach University of California, Davis 1 1. What Does it Mean to do High Quality (Qualitative) Field Research? a) It plays to the strengths of the method for theory

More information

(Visual) Attention. October 3, PSY Visual Attention 1

(Visual) Attention. October 3, PSY Visual Attention 1 (Visual) Attention Perception and awareness of a visual object seems to involve attending to the object. Do we have to attend to an object to perceive it? Some tasks seem to proceed with little or no attention

More information

Gold and Hohwy, Rationality and Schizophrenic Delusion

Gold and Hohwy, Rationality and Schizophrenic Delusion PHIL 5983: Irrational Belief Seminar Prof. Funkhouser 2/6/13 Gold and Hohwy, Rationality and Schizophrenic Delusion There are two plausible departments of rationality: procedural and content. Procedural

More information

Introduction to Phenomenology as philosophy and research method. Maria Luisa Pérez Cavana Research Forum

Introduction to Phenomenology as philosophy and research method. Maria Luisa Pérez Cavana Research Forum Introduction to Phenomenology as philosophy and research method Maria Luisa Pérez Cavana 18.10.2016 Research Forum Overview Philosophical foundation of phenomenology Phenomenology schools Conditions of

More information

24.500/Phil253 topics in philosophy of mind/perceptual experience

24.500/Phil253 topics in philosophy of mind/perceptual experience 24.500/Phil253 topics in philosophy of mind/perceptual experience session 10 24.500/Phil253 S07 1 plan tea @ 2.30 Block on consciousness, accessibility, FFA VWFA 24.500/Phil253 S07 2 phenomenal consciousness

More information

Models of Information Retrieval

Models of Information Retrieval Models of Information Retrieval Introduction By information behaviour is meant those activities a person may engage in when identifying their own needs for information, searching for such information in

More information

Perception LECTURE FOUR MICHAELMAS Dr Maarten Steenhagen

Perception LECTURE FOUR MICHAELMAS Dr Maarten Steenhagen Perception LECTURE FOUR MICHAELMAS 2017 Dr Maarten Steenhagen ms2416@cam.ac.uk Last week Lecture 1: Naive Realism Lecture 2: The Argument from Hallucination Lecture 3: Representationalism Lecture 4: Disjunctivism

More information

Physiological Function, Health and Medical Theory

Physiological Function, Health and Medical Theory Physiological Function, Health and Medical Theory Amanda Thorell PhD-student at the Department of Philosophy, Stockholm University amanda.thorell@philosophy.su.se Abstract In medicine, the concepts of

More information

Why Gifts and Strengths? (an article written for The Whole Self Center an agency that provides services for individuals with autism in Maryland)

Why Gifts and Strengths? (an article written for The Whole Self Center an agency that provides services for individuals with autism in Maryland) Why Gifts and Strengths? (an article written for The Whole Self Center an agency that provides services for individuals with autism in Maryland) Adolescents and young adults with ASD and other related

More information

Pain Self-Management Strategies Wheel

Pain Self-Management Strategies Wheel Pain Self-Management Strategies Wheel Each strategy has its own wedge on this wheel. Each wedge is divided into three sections. After you read about a strategy, use the key below to rate how well you think

More information

Multimodal interactions: visual-auditory

Multimodal interactions: visual-auditory 1 Multimodal interactions: visual-auditory Imagine that you are watching a game of tennis on television and someone accidentally mutes the sound. You will probably notice that following the game becomes

More information

The architect s perspective on the tour and map perspective

The architect s perspective on the tour and map perspective The architect s perspective on the tour and map perspective The MIT Faculty has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters. Citation As Published

More information

Chapter 5 Car driving

Chapter 5 Car driving 5 Car driving The present thesis addresses the topic of the failure to apprehend. In the previous chapters we discussed potential underlying mechanisms for the failure to apprehend, such as a failure to

More information

Principals of Object Perception

Principals of Object Perception Principals of Object Perception Elizabeth S. Spelke COGNITIVE SCIENCE 14, 29-56 (1990) Cornell University Summary Infants perceive object by analyzing tree-dimensional surface arrangements and motions.

More information

Perception, Biology, Action, and Knowledge

Perception, Biology, Action, and Knowledge Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXXXVIII No. 2, March 2014 doi: 10.1111/phpr.12092 2014 Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LLC Perception, Biology, Action, and Knowledge CHRISTOPHER

More information

2014 Philosophy. National 5. Finalised Marking Instructions

2014 Philosophy. National 5. Finalised Marking Instructions National Qualifications 2014 2014 Philosophy National 5 Finalised Marking Instructions Scottish Qualifications Authority 2014 The information in this publication may be reproduced to support SQA qualifications

More information

A High Resolution Picture of the Observer Questions and Answers

A High Resolution Picture of the Observer Questions and Answers A High Resolution Picture of the Observer Questions and Answers After further contemplation, our most recent revelations regarding the observer have been further modified. The precise locations of conscious

More information

Why do Psychologists Perform Research?

Why do Psychologists Perform Research? PSY 102 1 PSY 102 Understanding and Thinking Critically About Psychological Research Thinking critically about research means knowing the right questions to ask to assess the validity or accuracy of a

More information

Intentional Horizons

Intentional Horizons Mind Knowledge Communication Intentional Horizons The Mind from an Epistemic Point of View von Magdalena Balcerak Jackson 1. Auflage mentis 2009 Verlag C.H. Beck im Internet: www.beck.de ISBN 978 3 89785

More information

Presence and Perception: theoretical links & empirical evidence. Edwin Blake

Presence and Perception: theoretical links & empirical evidence. Edwin Blake Presence and Perception: theoretical links & empirical evidence Edwin Blake edwin@cs.uct.ac.za This Talk 2 Perception Bottom-up Top-down Integration Presence Bottom-up Top-down BIPs Presence arises from

More information

LEAVING EVERYONE WITH THE IMPRESSION OF INCREASE The Number One Key to Success

LEAVING EVERYONE WITH THE IMPRESSION OF INCREASE The Number One Key to Success LESSON ELEVEN LEAVING EVERYONE WITH THE IMPRESSION OF INCREASE The Number One Key to Success 167 Lesson Eleven AREA 1 NAME AREA 2 NAME AREA 3 NAME KEY POINTS Riches, in the context of this program, refers

More information

7 WAYS TO BECOME YOUR OWN MEDICINE. In order to have a solid platform to heal from trauma, we need to ensure we have our foundation in place.

7 WAYS TO BECOME YOUR OWN MEDICINE. In order to have a solid platform to heal from trauma, we need to ensure we have our foundation in place. 7 WAYS TO BECOME YOUR OWN MEDICINE In order to have a solid platform to heal from trauma, we need to ensure we have our foundation in place. Think about the importance of having a solid foundation in your

More information

Nature of the mind Intersection of Philosophy and Neuroscience

Nature of the mind Intersection of Philosophy and Neuroscience 1 Nature of the mind Classically part of philosophy Thought about without insight from neuroscience. Topics traditionally included: memory and learning consciousness free will Intersection of Philosophy

More information

UNDERSTANDING MEMORY

UNDERSTANDING MEMORY Communication Chain UNDERSTANDING MEMORY HEARING EXPRESSION thoughts/ ideas ATTENTION select words to use speech production FEEDBACK Hello, how are you? Communication Chain The Communication Chain picture

More information

Introduction to Research Methods

Introduction to Research Methods Introduction to Research Methods Updated August 08, 2016 1 The Three Types of Psychology Research Psychology research can usually be classified as one of three major types: 1. Causal Research When most

More information

Observation is the capacity of the individual to know the environment by the use of his senses. There are two steps in the process of observation:

Observation is the capacity of the individual to know the environment by the use of his senses. There are two steps in the process of observation: Definition Observation is the capacity of the individual to know the environment by the use of his senses. There are two steps in the process of observation: 1) Attention: is the preparatory step, the

More information

Paradoxes of personal identity: teletransportation, split brains, and immaterial souls

Paradoxes of personal identity: teletransportation, split brains, and immaterial souls Paradoxes of personal identity: teletransportation, split brains, and immaterial souls What is a theory of personal identity? Suppose that you have a person, A, who exists at some time, and a person, B,

More information

Perceptual Imagination and Perceptual Memory

Perceptual Imagination and Perceptual Memory 1 Perceptual Imagination and Perceptual Memory An Overview Fiona Macpherson The essays in this volume explore the nature of perceptual imagination and perceptual memory. How do perceptual imagination and

More information

Running Head: NARRATIVE COHERENCE AND FIDELITY 1

Running Head: NARRATIVE COHERENCE AND FIDELITY 1 Running Head: NARRATIVE COHERENCE AND FIDELITY 1 Coherence and Fidelity in Fisher s Narrative Paradigm Amy Kuhlman Wheaton College 13 November 2013 NARRATIVE COHERENCE AND FIDELITY 2 Abstract This paper

More information

Williamson applies his argumentative strategy to the following two supposedly clear examples of an a priori and an a posteriori truth, respectively:

Williamson applies his argumentative strategy to the following two supposedly clear examples of an a priori and an a posteriori truth, respectively: WILLIAMSON ON THE DISTINCTION BETWEEN THE A PRIORI AND THE A POSTERIORI In his paper How Deep is the Distinction between A Priori and A Posteriori Knowledge?, Timothy Williamson argues for the claim that

More information

Is it ever possible, in being aware of an attribute of one s own body from the inside, to

Is it ever possible, in being aware of an attribute of one s own body from the inside, to This is the author s version of an article that is forthcoming in Philosophical Studies. All citations should be to the published version, available online at http://www.springerlink.com/content/r63ht43687310366/.

More information

Some Important Concepts in EFT

Some Important Concepts in EFT Measuring Intensity Some Important Concepts in EFT Measuring intensity is extremely important because it gives a benchmark of the progress made. It also indicates when the problem has gone, and it is important

More information

Speech Spatial Qualities -C

Speech Spatial Qualities -C Speech Spatial Qualities -C Advice about answering the questions The following questions inquire about aspects of your ability and experience hearing and listening in different situations. You answered

More information

Bernhard Wolf University of Landau, Germany February, Fundamental Principles of Brunswik s Representative Design

Bernhard Wolf University of Landau, Germany February, Fundamental Principles of Brunswik s Representative Design Bernhard Wolf University of Landau, Germany February, 2005 Fundamental Principles of Brunswik s Representative Design Mainly between 94 and 955, Brunswik developed the basic outline for a completely new

More information

A Historical Introduction to the Philosophy of Mind. Lily Trapkin Intro to Philosophy November 2013

A Historical Introduction to the Philosophy of Mind. Lily Trapkin Intro to Philosophy November 2013 + A Historical Introduction to the Philosophy of Mind Lily Trapkin Intro to Philosophy November 2013 + B.F. Skinner Hamilton College alumni He was an atheist Studied radical behaviorism, which is the study

More information

Introduction to. Metaphysics. Mary ET Boyle, Ph.D. Department of Cognitive Science UCSD

Introduction to. Metaphysics. Mary ET Boyle, Ph.D. Department of Cognitive Science UCSD Introduction to 1 Metaphysics Mary ET Boyle, Ph.D. Department of Cognitive Science UCSD LECTURE BASED ON READINGS FROM: WHY NEUROPHILOSOPHY? Nature of the mind Classically part of philosophy Thought about

More information

Functionalist theories of content

Functionalist theories of content Functionalist theories of content PHIL 93507 April 22, 2012 Let s assume that there is a certain stable dependence relation between the physical internal states of subjects and the phenomenal characters

More information

Anyone can practice Deep Listening. The form given in this book has evolved from many years of this practice in workshops, retreats and classes.

Anyone can practice Deep Listening. The form given in this book has evolved from many years of this practice in workshops, retreats and classes. Introduction Anyone can practice Deep Listening. The form given in this book has evolved from many years of this practice in workshops, retreats and classes. What is Deep Listening? This question is answered

More information

What Effect Do Schemas Have On The Recall Of

What Effect Do Schemas Have On The Recall Of What Effect Do Schemas Have On The Recall Of Memories AIM:Bartlett aimed to investigate the effect of culture on memory. memory ability/ability to recall and have advantageous effects if asked to do a

More information

Artificial Intelligence: Its Scope and Limits, by James Fetzer, Kluver Academic Publishers, Dordrecht, Boston, London. Artificial Intelligence (AI)

Artificial Intelligence: Its Scope and Limits, by James Fetzer, Kluver Academic Publishers, Dordrecht, Boston, London. Artificial Intelligence (AI) Artificial Intelligence: Its Scope and Limits, by James Fetzer, Kluver Academic Publishers, Dordrecht, Boston, London. Artificial Intelligence (AI) is the study of how to make machines behave intelligently,

More information

Coaching, a scientific method

Coaching, a scientific method Coaching, a scientific method ROSELYNE KATTAR I. What is coaching? II. What is The Scientific Method in coaching? What are the phases of this process? III. How does a coach help his client? This article

More information

The SAGE Deaf Studies Encyclopedia Geographies

The SAGE Deaf Studies Encyclopedia Geographies The SAGE Deaf Studies Encyclopedia Geographies Contributors: Mike Gulliver & Mary Beth Kitzel Edited by: Genie Gertz & Patrick Boudreault Book Title: Chapter Title: "Geographies" Pub. Date: 2016 Access

More information

Adjusting the way to speak when communicating with people who have visual impairment and additional needs

Adjusting the way to speak when communicating with people who have visual impairment and additional needs Adjusting the way to speak when communicating with people who have visual impairment and additional needs Ian Bell Specialist Independent Speech and Language Therapist Article 17 in the series Facilitating

More information

Is Cognitive Science Special? In what way is it special? Cognitive science is a delicate mixture of the obvious and the incredible

Is Cognitive Science Special? In what way is it special? Cognitive science is a delicate mixture of the obvious and the incredible Sept 3, 2013 Is Cognitive Science Special? In what way is it special? Zenon Pylyshyn, Rutgers Center for Cognitive Science Cognitive science is a delicate mixture of the obvious and the incredible What

More information

Thinkers on Education -Carl Ransom Rogers ( )

Thinkers on Education -Carl Ransom Rogers ( ) Thinkers on Education -Carl Ransom Rogers (1902-1987) Best known for his contribution to client-centered therapy and his role in the development of counseling, Rogers also had much to say about education

More information

Ontology of Observing: The Biological Foundations of Self-Consciousness and of The Physical Domain of Existence

Ontology of Observing: The Biological Foundations of Self-Consciousness and of The Physical Domain of Existence Ontology of Observing: The Biological Foundations of Self-Consciousness and of The Physical Domain of Existence Humberto R. Maturana (1988) Contents 1 Purpose 3 2 The problem 3 3 Nature of the answer 3

More information

Speech Spatial Qualities

Speech Spatial Qualities Speech Spatial Qualities Advice about answering the questions The following questions inquire about aspects of your ability and experience hearing and listening in different situations. For each question,

More information

Cognitive Ecology. Implications for Contemplative Science. Evan Thompson Upaya Institute and Zen Center Zen Brain 2016

Cognitive Ecology. Implications for Contemplative Science. Evan Thompson Upaya Institute and Zen Center Zen Brain 2016 Cognitive Ecology Implications for Contemplative Science Evan Thompson Upaya Institute and Zen Center Zen Brain 2016 Outline Complexity and connectivity 4E cognition Cognitive ecology Implications for

More information

Guidelines for the Westmead PTA scale

Guidelines for the Westmead PTA scale Guidelines for the Westmead PTA scale N.E.V. Marosszeky, L. Ryan, E.A. Shores, J. Batchelor & J.E. Marosszeky Dept. of Rehabilitation Medicine, Westmead Hospital Dept. of Psychology, Macquarie University

More information

IS A TWO WAY STREET BETTER COMMUNICATION HABITS A GUIDE FOR FAMILY AND FRIENDS

IS A TWO WAY STREET BETTER COMMUNICATION HABITS A GUIDE FOR FAMILY AND FRIENDS Communication IS A TWO WAY STREET BETTER COMMUNICATION HABITS A GUIDE FOR FAMILY AND FRIENDS Good communication builds GOOD RELATIONSHIPS. The sense of hearing is a vital link to the world a source of

More information

Games for Young Mathematicians Dot Cards

Games for Young Mathematicians Dot Cards ABOUT THE MATH If you watch and listen to how students interact with the dot cards, you can learn a lot about what they know and what they are ready to learn. Once you see what they can do, you can help

More information

Brainy Brownson & the Body of Brown: The Reduction of Psychological Identity to

Brainy Brownson & the Body of Brown: The Reduction of Psychological Identity to 1 Brainy Brownson & the Body of Brown: The Reduction of Psychological Identity to Bodily Identity Abstract: Psychological accounts of personal identity have typically taken the psychological aspects of

More information

Embodied Emotion: designing interactive products for a person s emotional being-in-the-world

Embodied Emotion: designing interactive products for a person s emotional being-in-the-world Embodied Emotion: designing interactive products for a person s emotional being-in-the-world Valerie Mencke University of Twente Utrecht, the Netherlands valerie_mencke@hotmail.com Jelle van Dijk University

More information