Dual process theories: A key for understanding the diversification bias?

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Dual process theories: A key for understanding the diversification bias?"

Transcription

1 J Risk Uncertainty (2007) 34: DOI /s Dual process theories: A key for understanding the diversification bias? Christoph Kogler & Anton Kühberger Published online: 8 March 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media, LLC 2007 Abstract The diversification bias in repeated lotteries is the finding that a majority of participants fail to select the option offering the highest probability. This phenomenon is systematic and immune to classical manipulations (e.g. monetary rewards). We apply dual process theories and argue that the diversification bias is a consequence of System 1 (automatic, intuitive, associative) triggering a matching response, which fails to be corrected by System 2 (intentional, analytic, rational). Empirically, supporting the corrective functions of System 2 through appropriate contextual cues (describing the task as a statistical test rather than as a lottery) led to a decrease of diversification. Keywords Dual process theories. Diversification. Probability matching. Statistical independence JEL Classification D83. D81 Repetitions of similar risky choices are characteristic for everyday life, e.g. in betting, health decisions or when using seatbelts. Some of these repeated choices are practically identical, and assuming that preferences are relatively stable over time, it seems easy to formulate an optimal decision rule: find the best option when the choice comes up for the first time, and then stick to this option in all subsequent instances. Thus, if you believe that using a seatbelt is a good choice for your first trip, you should use it on any trip. As simple as this rule is, people do nevertheless violate it. For instance, Baron et al. (1993) reported that, although adolescent subjects believe that using seatbelts is beneficial, some failed to see that they then should use them on every single trip. Rather many respondents held the view that they should use seatbelts most, but not all of the time, to match the fact that there are C. Kogler: A. Kühberger (*) Department of Psychology, University of Salzburg, Hellbrunnerstr. 34, 5020 Salzburg, Austria anton.kuehberger@sbg.ac.at url:

2 146 J Risk Uncertainty (2007) 34: rare situations where this can do harm. Researchers named the tendency to choose differently in identical choice situations diversification. More specifically, when confronted with a choice between alternatives that have different rates of occurrence, experimental participants have been found to proportion their choices in accord with the relative expected rates. This phenomenon called probability matching has been demonstrated years ago in animals (see Herrnstein s 1961 classic demonstration of the matching law; and, for an overview, Gallistel 1990, chapter 11) and with humans (Fantino and Esfandiari 2002). In recent research, probability matching has been found in multiple decision problems with constant probabilities. Gal and Baron (1996) asked participants to predict the outcome of rolling a die with four red and two green faces repeatedly. Uniform prediction of red maximizes the chances of predicting correctly, but 37% of the participants failed to do so and the majority of them did not know that the best strategy was to constantly predict red, when explicitly asked about strategies. Similar results are reported by Loomes (1998), who identified probability matching as the dominant strategy in multiple choice problems with constant probabilities. That is, rather than predicting the most likely outcome for every single event of a series, the majority of people matched predicted outcomes to frequencies. For example, if the frequency of red is four out of six, and the frequency of green is two out of six, people tend to produce predictions of about 67% red and 33% green in the long run. A similar finding is reported by Rubinstein (2002): in his task five cards were chosen randomly from a deck of 100 cards (36 green, 25 blue, 22 yellow, and 17 brown). Then the cards were put into five separate envelopes and participants had to guess the color of the card in each envelope. Since p(green)=0.36 is the highest probability for any color, 1 green should be predicted for each envelope. However, the majority of participants failed to do so, but rather matched predictions to probabilities by predicting a mixture of colors that resembled their frequencies, for instance by predicting green, blue, yellow, brown, and again green. This probability matching strategy is very popular in multiple choice problems with constant probabilities (for an overview, see Vulkan 2000), and has been extensively documented in the experimental literature. Probability matching has been found with gains and losses (Myers et al. 1963; Suppes and Atkinson 1960), with asymmetric payoffs and different distributions of probabilities (Estes and Straughan 1954), and with monetary incentives (Healy and Kubovy 1981; Kogler and Kühberger 2006). Yet probability matching also occurs in more natural settings, representing more realistic everyday dilemmas (Fisher and Mazur 1997). Even if people correctly perceive the rate of items, they prefer to follow the probability matching strategy and thus fail to adopt the rule that maximizes their prospects of guessing correctly. Why do people prefer to adopt the probability matching strategy instead of the maximization rule? One can only speculate, but it seems that the explanation is partly grounded in the preference for a strategy that can guarantee full success (although with very little probability) over a strategy that would yield a relatively large number of correct guesses, but would inevitably lead to some errors (Arkes, 1 Even without replacement p(green) is maximal, since there are 11 green cards more than cards of any other color and only five draws. Although strict independence is not applicable to our task (which is without replacement), we will use this notion in its loose sense, of quasi-independence.

3 J Risk Uncertainty (2007) 34: Dawes and Christensen 1986). Some scholars have argued that probability matching might actually be a rational strategy. For instance, in a competitive environment with multiple agents and constant payoff, opting for the less frequent event can be efficient. If most subjects choose the more frequent event, this payoff will be distributed among many. In contrast, choosing the less frequent event delivers the whole payoff, undivided, when it materializes (Gallistel 1990). Other researchers suggest that this type of diversification is a systematic mistake: Gal and Baron (1996) found that failure to rank different outcome patterns correctly in the die problem was strongly connected to a misunderstanding of the concept of statistical independence. Similarly Kogler and Kühberger (2006) found that correct ranking of different outcome patterns according to probability was strongly associated with application of the independence rule. The present research delves more deeply into the reasons for diversification and probability matching. We will use the card task developed by Rubinstein (2002) where participants have to predict the color of five cards randomly drawn from a deck of 100 cards (36 green, 25 blue, 22 yellow, and 17 red). We shall apply dual cognitive process theories to this task. Dual process theories propose the presence of two distinct thinking systems referring to collections of cognitive processes that differ in content, speed and control (see Epstein 1994; Sloman 1996; Stanovich and West 2000; Kahneman and Frederick 2002; Kahneman 2003). In general, System 1 works mainly on affective and concrete inputs and is rapid, automatic, and associative in nature, while System 2 mainly works on affectively neutral, abstract inputs in a slow, controlled, and deductive way. In typical decisions, the response is assumed to depend on both systems in a predetermined way: System 1 gives the preliminary, intuitive answer, which may or may not be corrected by System 2 (Gilbert 1989). We propose that the matching tendency is the result of System 1 processing. On presentation of the differently colored cards System 1 produces a prediction of the plausible outcome of five consecutive draws. This prediction is based on the similarity between sample and outcome. Since the drawing is from a sample of different colors, the outcome is similar to the degree that it also consists of different colors. The probability matching pattern is the pattern that is qualitatively most similar to the sample. Note that, according to Kahneman and Frederick (2002), similarity is an attribute that is assessed routinely and automatically, and forms the basis for a judgment by representativeness. In detail, prediction by similarity goes like this: There are cards of four different colors: green (36), blue (25), yellow (22), and red (17). Since the outcome needs to be similar to the sample, the first four cards will be predicted to be green, blue, yellow, and red. What will be the outcome of the fifth draw? Most probably, it will be the most likely color, that is green, because green is the most frequent color. Note, however, the last prediction cannot be based on similarity, but is based on a theoretical insight that frequency predicts probability. This chain of reasoning leads to a prediction of green, green, blue, yellow, and red (GGBYR), which we will term probability matching, since it is the pattern closest to probability matching, and exact probability matching is not possible in this task. Thus, a GGBYR pattern is, irrespective of the temporal order of predictions, indicative of a judgment by similarity, plus a judgment by probability. The former is, in all likelihood, an intuitive judgement, based on System 1 thinking, while the latter is based on System 2 thinking. We therefore have a mixture of cognitive processes,

4 148 J Risk Uncertainty (2007) 34: leading to probability matching, where System 2 thinking only joins in at the penultimate stage. Of course, System 2 thinking can also inform predictions from the outset. If so, and if people understand that probability predicts frequency, they will realize that green is the most likely color in every singles draw and therefore they will predict GGGGG. Actually, Kogler and Kühberger (2006) have found that most people do understand that probability predicts frequency in this task. When people had to evaluate the likelihood of some predetermined patterns of drawing, they realized that GGGGB is more likely than GGGGR, because blue is more frequent than red. Note, however: at the same time they failed to see that GGGGG, i.e., four greens and one green, is more likely than GGGGB, because green is more frequent than blue. In sum, two processes seem to interact in this task. We construe these processes along the System 1 and System 2 distinction. What is the nature of this interaction? Gilbert (1999) distinguishes four architectures for the interaction of System 1 and System 2: (1) Selective architecture. The two different systems are activated by different stimuli. Thus, people do one thing at one occasion and do another thing at another occasion, because on all occasions two qualitatively distinct processes are possible, one of which is active and one of which is dormant. The (2) Competitive architecture is similar, with the exception that one process controls the output and the other does not. Thus, the noncontrolling process is active but ultimately ineffective. Both these architectures are not plausible in our case, since the data indicate both automatic as well as controlled processes having an effect on the output. (3) Consolidative architecture. Any stimulus activates both processes, and the result is a joint function of both processes. In our task such an architecture is involved, but presumably it is of the type of (4) Corrective architecture. Here any stimulus activates both processes, but the result is determined by only one process exclusively (e.g. winner takes all). Following Gilbert (1999) and Kahneman (2003), we assume that people will adhere to the maximization rule rather than do probability matching to the degree that System 2 succeeds in correcting the output of System 1, provided that System 1 produces an output. Thus, if we want people to overcome their tendency to rely on probability matching, we either have to arrange the task in a way that renders the similarity feature unavailable, or we have to strengthen the corrective functions of System 2 thinking. The following experiment is an attempt at doing the latter. 1 Experiment The following experiment is based on the card task of Rubinstein (2002) and on findings of Kogler and Kühberger (2006), where we showed that people have a strong tendency to emit the probability matching response in this task. Specifically, we found that only about 5% of participants predicted according to probability theory (i.e., they uniformly predicted the most frequent color). This pattern, which is termed probability maximizing, was clearly less common than the probability matching pattern, which was found in about 35% of participants (the rest being patterns resembling probability matching). In different versions of the task we investigated the robustness of probability matching and found that probability matching was robust across stimuli (symbols and colors) and incentives (real and hypothetical payoffs). In

5 J Risk Uncertainty (2007) 34: sum, participants withstood our aim to raise the percentage of probability maximizers at least up to the level of probability matchers (Kogler 2006). The following experiment is another try at accomplishing this. 1.1 Method Participants Ninety-seven undergraduates (78 females and 19 males; mean age=22.6 years) from six introductory statistics courses at the University of Salzburg participated voluntarily. Participants had basic knowledge about probabilities and statistical independence Design and procedure The experiment was designed to support the corrective functions of System 2. Kahneman (2003) suggests three procedures to strengthen System 2: (1) provide strong cues to the relevant rules; (2) increase the vigilance of the monitoring activities; and (3) extensive training in statistical reasoning. We implemented (1) and (2), keeping (3) constant. Participants were instructed on the card-task. They learned that five cards were to be randomly drawn from a deck of 100 colored cards and that each of the five cards had to be put into a separate envelope. The deck of cards consisted of 36 green, 25 blue, 22 yellow, and 17 red cards. Thus, each of the envelopes labelled 1 to 5 was to contain either a green, a blue, a yellow, or a red card. The participants task was to predict the color of the card in each particular envelope. Two different groups were formed and instructed according to Kahneman s(2003) advice to strengthen System 2. First, we provided cues to the relevant rules. This was done by referring to the task as a lottery task (group A), or as a statistical test (group B). In addition, participants in Group B were informed that the task was a test to find out about their level of statistical competence, and participants were encouraged to show the best of their ability in this test, presumably increasing the vigilance of the monitoring activities. Furthermore we advised them to take their time (low time pressure), and to carefully reconsider a second time their predictions (hint at correction). Generally speaking, participants in both groups received the same task, but the instruction for Group B represents an attempt to support the corrective functions of System 2. Thus, in accordance with dual process theories, less probability matching is predicted for Group B compared to Group A. 2 Results and discussion Table 1 presents the results in terms of groupings of response patterns: probability maximizing (GGGGG); probability matching (GGBYR); and other predictions. We found a higher rate of probability-maximizing predictions in the condition aiming at supporting the corrective functions of System 2. Whereas in the control group only 15% of participants repeatedly opted for the most frequent color, 43% of participants did so in the experimental condition. This difference is significant

6 150 J Risk Uncertainty (2007) 34: Table 1 Frequencies (percentages in parenthesis) of basic response patterns Probability-maximizing Probability matching Other Control (N=46) 7 (15.2%) 28 (60.9%) 11 (23.9%) Corrective a (N=51) 22 (43.1%) 19 (37.3%) 10 (19.6%) Total (N=97) 29 (29.9%) 47 (48.5%) 21 (21.6%) a Instruction to support corrective functions of System 2. (χ 2 (1)=9.00; p<0.01). This goes to show that the rate of maximizing predictions increased via arranging the setting in a way to enhance System 2 thinking as proposed in the literature of dual process theories. As can be seen in Table 1, this increase was at the cost of matching choices, which decreased from 61% to 37% while other choices remained largely at their level (about 20%). Note that our experiment enables a very specific test of the dual processes idea. As we already discussed, the matching pattern involves both systems of thinking in a sequential way: first a judgment by similarity (System 1) leads to a prediction of different colors; second, an evaluation of frequency (System 2) leads to a prediction that green (the most frequent color) will appear two times, given that there are four colors and five cards. Thus, in this model System 2 joins in only at the second stage. Interestingly, our findings show that our attempt to strengthen System 2 did work, but not in stage 2, which actually contains the process that is in the realms of System 2. If we actually had strengthened the System 2 process, people would more frequently predict that the pattern contains two times green. We therefore would see a decrease of the patterns that are similar to matching (by containing four different colors, with only one green), and an increase in the matching pattern (four different colors, two greens). However, we found no such tendency. Rather, our finding of an increase of the maximizing-prediction indicates that participants did either rely more on System 2-thinking from the outset, or that they put more faith in the results of System 2- thinking such that the outcome of System 1 was overridden in some cases. Given that System 1 processes occur automatically and without intention (Stanovich and West 2002), we suggest that an intuitive answer was provided by System 1, but was suppressed. This is indicative of a consolidative or a corrective architecture. That means, while our stimuli seem to activate both processes, the result does not seem to be a joint function of both processes. Rather, we observe a the-winner-takes-all response: people do either stick to their intuitive answer (matching), or change it altogether according to reasoning based on frequency (maximizing). It does not seem to be the case that people apply the System 2 process more carefully. In addition, our data rule out the possibility of a selective or a competitive architecture, since these architectures would predict an increase in the frequency of other responses, which follows if matching and maximizing predictions are mixed. 3 General discussion Experimental research in simple repeated risky choices shows a striking violation of rational choice theory: the tendency to match probabilities by allocating the frequency of responses in proportion to their relative probabilities. We investigated

7 J Risk Uncertainty (2007) 34: this matching tendency in the card task developed by Rubinstein (2002). While our earlier research had shown that neither paying for correct prediction, nor making the independence of single outcomes salient, led to an increase of the rate of maximizing predictions (Kogler 2006), here we demonstrated that by strengthening the corrective functions of System 2, it was possible to significantly increase maximizing predictions. However, although our manipulation was successful, there was still a fair degree of matching (about 40%). What are the reasons for the robustness of the matching tendency? Of course, cognitive skills play an important role for coming up with an optimal prediction. For instance, people who do not know the principle of statistical independence will in all likelihood fail to behave accordingly. This is indicated by the finding that general cognitive ability is correlated with maximizing responses in probabilistic choice tasks: West and Stanovich (2003) showed that probability-matchers had lower SAT scores than optimal responders when predicting the outcome of rolling a die. Although lack of statistical knowledge may contribute to the predominance of matching, it is certainly not the only reason. In our task, people reported awareness of conflicting tendencies indicating that they had an idea about the maximizing answer, but they somehow failed to emit it. By appropriate contextual cues faith in the maximizing response obviously increased. Stanovich and West (2000) identify four alternative explanations for a gap between normative and empirical predictions: performance errors, computational limitations, a different construal of the task by the participant, and the wrong norm being applied by the experimenter. Performance errors as well as computational limitations are in all likelihood not the main reason for our findings because (1) we found a systematic matching tendency, rather than random predictions; (2) performance errors should decrease under conditions of incentive, which is not the case in our task (Kogler and Kühberger 2006); (3) the maximizing strategy is to always predict the same color, and this strategy is truly simple, being by far simpler than any prediction of a mixture of colors. We suggest that our appeal to cognitive ability led to a change in task construal to an understanding of the task as a test rather than a lottery. However, this does not by itself explain the higher rate of maximizing predictions. If people knew the correct answer, why should they withhold it in the lottery situation, but emit it in the test situation? The dual systems view of thinking is helpful here: the test situation is a strong cue for the reliance on System 2 thinking while the lottery situation fails to provide such a cue. This interpretation is also in accordance with other findings in the literature on dual processes (for an overview see Chaiken and Trope 1999), where the monitoring functions of System 2 are said to be quite lax, allowing many intuitive judgments to be expressed, including erroneous ones. Thus, people seem to be reluctant to think hard and are tempted to trust a plausible judgment that quickly comes to mind (Kahneman 2003, p. 699). There is also some neurophysiological evidence for dual processes in reasoning, in particular supporting the idea that System 2 can intervene or inhibit System 1 processes (Goel and Dolan 2003). Concerning the interaction between the two systems, these neurophysiological findings as well as our data favor the corrective type of architecture, where both processes (Systems 1+2) are said to be jointly activated, but finally one overrules the other. In our case we presume an automatic activation of the matching tendency

8 152 J Risk Uncertainty (2007) 34: (System 1) generated by the representativeness heuristic, and a subsequent possibility for System 2 to correct this intuitive judgment, or to accept it. Doubt is obviously a System 2 phenomenon and it seems that we enhanced it by arranging the setting in an appropriate way. Note however, that the rate of matching was still very impressive. Thus, it is surely possible that participants applied a norm other than statistical independence to the task. Probability matching is an instance of a more general tendency to opt for variety. Selecting variety in repeated choices is a risk-minimizing strategy (Read and Loewenstein 1995), and may be evolutionarily advantageous in many real-life situations (Gallistel 1990). The preference for variety is related to findings such as risk-sensitive foraging (e.g., Kacelnik and Bateson 1997), where it is argued that risky choices should reflect not only the expected outcome, but in addition the need of the organism, and the variance associated with each option (e.g., Rohde et al. 1999). Similar findings are reported in the field of consumer research (Simonson 1990; Read and Loewenstein 1995) where people often end up choosing more variety than they actually wanted when purchasing food. A way to reduce matching might thus be to use a more real-life task. Indeed, Rubinstein (2002) found that diversification was noticeably reduced when he used tasks like ours, however couched in a practical cover story (e.g., predicting the gate through which a messenger will enter a shopping mall on five consecutive days, given different probabilities for the gates). However, other research found matching even in practical tasks. For instance, in a medical task participants learned the correlation between certain symptoms and the likelihood of a disease. Then they were presented with the symptoms of several patients. To maximize the probability of correct diagnosis, participants should consistently choose the outcome that is more frequently associated with that particular symptom pattern. They failed to do so but rather their judgments were guided by the ratio of probabilities (Friedman et al. 1995). Admittedly, there are various differences between artificial and real-life diversification tasks. For instance, real-life diversification tasks are characterized by learning. Thus, repeated sampling (e.g. gaining experience by seeing the results of, say, 100 five-card-draws) might lead to a decrease in probability matching (Shanks, Tunney, and McCarthy 2002). For our task this is unlikely, however. What would be experienced by repeated sampling? People would probably just realize that patterns consisting of different colors are by far more frequent than the pattern of the single most frequent color. Thus experience would correctly inform people that mixed outcomes are more frequent than pure outcomes. They might easily over-generalize this to mean that matching is better than maximizing. Thus, experience might not always be the cure to probability matching. References Arkes, Hal R., Robyn M. Dawes, and Caryn Christensen. (1986). Factors Influencing the Use of a Decision Rule in a Probabilistic Task, Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 37, Baron, Jonathan, Leonardo Granato, Mark Spranca, and Eva Teubal. (1993). Decision Making Biases in Children and Early Adolescents: Exploratory Studies, Merril Palmer Quarterly 39, Chaiken, Shelly, and Yaacov Trope (eds.). (1999). Dual-Process Theories in Social Psychology. New York: Guilford.

9 J Risk Uncertainty (2007) 34: Epstein, Seymour. (1994). Integration of the Cognitive and Psychodynamic Unconscious, American Psychologist 49, Estes, William K., and J. H. Straughan. (1954). Analysis of a Verbal Conditioning Situation in Terms of Statistical Learning Theory, Journal of Experimental Psychology 47, Fantino, Edmund, and Ali Esfandiari. (2002). Probability Matching: Encouraging Optimal Responding in Humans, Canadian Journal of Experimental Psychology 56, Fisher, Wayne W., and James E. Mazur. (1997). Basic and Applied Research on Choice Responding, Journal of Applied Behavior Analysis 30, Friedman, Daniel, Dominic W. Massaro, Stephen Kitzis, and Michael Cohen. (1995). A Comparison of Learning Models, Journal of Mathematical Psychology 39, Gal, Ido, and Jonathan Baron. (1996). Understanding Repeated Simple Choices, Thinking and Reasoning 2, Gallistel, Charles R. (1990). The Organization of Learning. Cambridge, MA: MIT. Gilbert, Daniel T. (1989). Thinking Lightly About Others: Automatic Components of the Social Inference Process. In James Uleman and John A. Bargh (eds.), Unintended Thought (pp ). Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. Gilbert, Daniel T. (1999). What the Mind s Not. In Shelly Chaiken and Yaacov Trope (eds.), Dualprocess Theories in Social Psychology (pp. 3 11). New York: Guilford. Goel, Vinod, and Raymond Dolan. (2003). Explaining Modulation of Reasoning by Belief, Cognition 87, B11 B22. Healy, Alice F., and Michael Kubovy. (1981). Probability Matching and the Formation of Conservative Decision Rules in a Numerical Analog of Signal Detection, Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Learning and Memory 7, Herrnstein, R. J. (1961). Relative and Absolute Strength of Response as a Function of Frequency of Reinforcement, Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior 4, Kacelnik, Alex, and Melissa Bateson. (1997). Risk-sensitivity: Crossroads for Theories of Decisionmaking, Trends in Cognitive Sciences 1, Kahneman, Daniel. (2003). A Perspective on Judgement and Choice: Mapping Bounded Rationality, American Psychologist 58, Kahneman, Daniel, and Shane Frederick. (2002). Representativeness Revisited: Attribute Substitution in Intuitive Judgement. In Thomas Gilovich, Dale Griffin, and Daniel Kahneman (eds.), Heuristics and Biases: The Psychology of Intuitive Judgment (pp ). New York: Cambridge University Press. Kogler, Christoph. (2006). How Robust is the Diversification Bias? The Role of Dual Cognitive Processtheories in Multiple Decision Problems with Objective Probabilities. Ph.D., University of Salzburg. Kogler, Christoph, and Anton Kühberger. (2006). Dual Process Theories and the Diversification Bias. In Bartosz Gula, Rainer Alexandrowizc, Sabine Strauß, Eva Brunner, Barbara Jenull-Schiefer, and Oliver Vitouch (eds.), Perspektiven psychologischer Forschung in Österreich (pp.62 70). Lengerich: Pabst. Loomes, Graham. (1998). Probability vs. Money: A Test of Some Fundamental Assumptions about Rational Decision Making, The Economic Journal 108, Myers, Jerome L., Jane G. Fort, Leonard Katz, and Mary M. Suydam. (1963). Differential Memory Gains and Losses and Event Probability in a Two-choice Situation, Journal of Experimental Psychology 66, Read, Daniel, and George Loewenstein. (1995). Diversification Bias: Explaining the Discrepancy in Variety Seeking Between Combined and Separate Choices, Journal of Experimental Psychology: Applied 1, Rohde, Catrin, Leda Cosmides, Wolfgang Hell, and John Tooby. (1999). When and Why do People Avoid Unknown Probabilities in Decisions Under Uncertainty? Testing Some Predictions from Optimal Foraging Theory, Cognition 72, Rubinstein, Ariel. (2002). Irrational Diversification in Multiple Decision Problems, European Economic Review 46, Shanks, David R., Richard J. Tunney, and John D. McCarthy. (2002). A Re-examination of Probability Matching and Rational Choice, Journal of Behavioral Decision Making 15, Simonson, Itmar. (1990). The Effect of Purchase Quantity and Timing on Variety Seeking Behavior, Journal of Marketing Research 32, Stanovich, Keith E., and Richard F. West. (2000). Individual Differences in Reasoning: Implications for the Rationality Debate, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 23, Stanovich, Keith E., and Richard F. West. (2002). Individual Differences in Reasoning: Implications for the Rationality Debate? In Thomas Gilovich, Dale W. Griffin, and Daniel Kahneman (eds.), Heuristics and Biases: The Psychology of Intuitive Judgment (pp ). New York: Cambridge University Press.

10 154 J Risk Uncertainty (2007) 34: Suppes, Patrick, and Richard C. Atkinson. (1960). Markov Learning Models for Multiperson Interactions. Stanford: Stanford University Press. Vulkan, Nir. (2000). An Economist s Perspective on Probability Matching, Journal of Economic Surveys 14, West, Richard F., and Keith E. Stanovich. (2003). Is Probability Matching Smart? Associations Between Probabilistic Choices and Cognitive Ability, Memory & Cognition 31,

Probability matching and strategy availability

Probability matching and strategy availability Memory & Cognition 2010, 38 (6), 667-676 doi:10.3758/mc.38.6.667 Probability matching and strategy availability DEREK J. KOEHLER AND GRETA JAMES University of Waterloo, Waterloo, Ontario, Canada Findings

More information

Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition

Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition Conflict and Bias in Heuristic Judgment Sudeep Bhatia Online First Publication, September 29, 2016. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/xlm0000307

More information

Irrational diversication in multiple decision problems

Irrational diversication in multiple decision problems European Economic Review 46 (2002) 1369 1378 www.elsevier.com/locate/econbase Irrational diversication in multiple decision problems Ariel Rubinstein a;b; a School of Economics, Tel Aviv University, 69978

More information

Who Is Rational? Studies of Individual Differences in Reasoning

Who Is Rational? Studies of Individual Differences in Reasoning Book Review/Compte rendu 291 Who Is Rational? Studies of Individual Differences in Reasoning Keith E. Stanovich Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, 1999. Pp. xvi, 1-296. Hardcover: ISBN 0-8058-2472-3,

More information

Adults guesses on probabilistic tasks reveal incremental representativeness biases

Adults guesses on probabilistic tasks reveal incremental representativeness biases Adults guesses on probabilistic tasks reveal incremental representativeness biases Habiba Azab 1 (hazab@mail.bcs.rochester.edu) David Ruskin 1 (druskin@mail.bcs.rochester.edu) Celeste Kidd 1,2 (celestekidd@gmail.com)

More information

American Law & Economics Association Annual Meetings

American Law & Economics Association Annual Meetings American Law & Economics Association Annual Meetings Year 2004 Paper 39 Probability Matching and the Law: A New Behavioral Challenge to Law and Economics Ehud Guttel Alon Harel Hebrew University Faculty

More information

An Understanding of Role of Heuristic on Investment Decisions

An Understanding of Role of Heuristic on Investment Decisions International Review of Business and Finance ISSN 0976-5891 Volume 9, Number 1 (2017), pp. 57-61 Research India Publications http://www.ripublication.com An Understanding of Role of Heuristic on Investment

More information

Psychological. Influences on Personal Probability. Chapter 17. Copyright 2005 Brooks/Cole, a division of Thomson Learning, Inc.

Psychological. Influences on Personal Probability. Chapter 17. Copyright 2005 Brooks/Cole, a division of Thomson Learning, Inc. Psychological Chapter 17 Influences on Personal Probability Copyright 2005 Brooks/Cole, a division of Thomson Learning, Inc. 17.2 Equivalent Probabilities, Different Decisions Certainty Effect: people

More information

GUEN DONDÉ HEAD OF RESEARCH INSTITUTE OF BUSINESS ETHICS

GUEN DONDÉ HEAD OF RESEARCH INSTITUTE OF BUSINESS ETHICS WHAT DOES ETHICS AT WORK MEAN TO EMPLOYEES? GUEN DONDÉ HEAD OF RESEARCH INSTITUTE OF BUSINESS ETHICS IBE 05/07/2018 1 ABOUT THE IBE The IBE was established in 1986 to promote high standards of business

More information

Effects of Sequential Context on Judgments and Decisions in the Prisoner s Dilemma Game

Effects of Sequential Context on Judgments and Decisions in the Prisoner s Dilemma Game Effects of Sequential Context on Judgments and Decisions in the Prisoner s Dilemma Game Ivaylo Vlaev (ivaylo.vlaev@psy.ox.ac.uk) Department of Experimental Psychology, University of Oxford, Oxford, OX1

More information

It is Whether You Win or Lose: The Importance of the Overall Probabilities of Winning or Losing in Risky Choice

It is Whether You Win or Lose: The Importance of the Overall Probabilities of Winning or Losing in Risky Choice The Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 30:1; 5 19, 2005 c 2005 Springer Science + Business Media, Inc. Manufactured in The Netherlands. It is Whether You Win or Lose: The Importance of the Overall Probabilities

More information

Assessment and Estimation of Risk Preferences (Outline and Pre-summary)

Assessment and Estimation of Risk Preferences (Outline and Pre-summary) Assessment and Estimation of Risk Preferences (Outline and Pre-summary) Charles A. Holt and Susan K. Laury 1 In press (2013) for the Handbook of the Economics of Risk and Uncertainty, Chapter 4, M. Machina

More information

Some Thoughts on the Principle of Revealed Preference 1

Some Thoughts on the Principle of Revealed Preference 1 Some Thoughts on the Principle of Revealed Preference 1 Ariel Rubinstein School of Economics, Tel Aviv University and Department of Economics, New York University and Yuval Salant Graduate School of Business,

More information

An Experimental Investigation of Self-Serving Biases in an Auditing Trust Game: The Effect of Group Affiliation: Discussion

An Experimental Investigation of Self-Serving Biases in an Auditing Trust Game: The Effect of Group Affiliation: Discussion 1 An Experimental Investigation of Self-Serving Biases in an Auditing Trust Game: The Effect of Group Affiliation: Discussion Shyam Sunder, Yale School of Management P rofessor King has written an interesting

More information

Implicit Conflict Detection During Decision Making

Implicit Conflict Detection During Decision Making Implicit Conflict Detection During Decision Making Wim De Neys (Wim.Deneys@psy.kuleuven.be) Department of Psychology, K.U.Leuven, Tiensestraat 102 3000 Leuven, Belgium Abstract Popular dual process theories

More information

Kahneman, Daniel. Thinking Fast and Slow. New York: Farrar, Straus & Giroux, 2011.

Kahneman, Daniel. Thinking Fast and Slow. New York: Farrar, Straus & Giroux, 2011. The accumulating research indicates that individuals cognitive and behavioral orientations to objects (their thoughts and actions) are frequently based on rapid shortcuts or heuristics. The past few decades

More information

FAQ: Heuristics, Biases, and Alternatives

FAQ: Heuristics, Biases, and Alternatives Question 1: What is meant by the phrase biases in judgment heuristics? Response: A bias is a predisposition to think or act in a certain way based on past experience or values (Bazerman, 2006). The term

More information

Wason's Cards: What is Wrong?

Wason's Cards: What is Wrong? Wason's Cards: What is Wrong? Pei Wang Computer and Information Sciences, Temple University This paper proposes a new interpretation

More information

Mental operations on number symbols by-children*

Mental operations on number symbols by-children* Memory & Cognition 1974, Vol. 2,No. 3, 591-595 Mental operations on number symbols by-children* SUSAN HOFFMAN University offlorida, Gainesville, Florida 32601 TOM TRABASSO Princeton University, Princeton,

More information

Sleeping Beauty is told the following:

Sleeping Beauty is told the following: Sleeping beauty Sleeping Beauty is told the following: You are going to sleep for three days, during which time you will be woken up either once Now suppose that you are sleeping beauty, and you are woken

More information

Choice set options affect the valuation of risky prospects

Choice set options affect the valuation of risky prospects Choice set options affect the valuation of risky prospects Stian Reimers (stian.reimers@warwick.ac.uk) Neil Stewart (neil.stewart@warwick.ac.uk) Nick Chater (nick.chater@warwick.ac.uk) Department of Psychology,

More information

How rational are humans? Many important implications hinge. Qu a r t e r ly Jo u r n a l of. Vol. 15 N o Au s t r i a n.

How rational are humans? Many important implications hinge. Qu a r t e r ly Jo u r n a l of. Vol. 15 N o Au s t r i a n. The Qu a r t e r ly Jo u r n a l of Vol. 15 N o. 3 370 374 Fall 2012 Au s t r i a n Ec o n o m i c s Book Review Thinking, Fast and Slow Dan i e l Ka h n e m a n Lon d o n: Al l e n La n e, 2011, 499 p

More information

A Computational Model of Counterfactual Thinking: The Temporal Order Effect

A Computational Model of Counterfactual Thinking: The Temporal Order Effect A Computational Model of Counterfactual Thinking: The Temporal Order Effect Clare R. Walsh (cwalsh@tcd.ie) Psychology Department, University of Dublin, Trinity College, Dublin 2, Ireland Ruth M.J. Byrne

More information

The Conference That Counts! March, 2018

The Conference That Counts! March, 2018 The Conference That Counts! March, 2018 Statistics, Definitions, & Theories The Audit Process Getting it Wrong Practice & Application Some Numbers You Should Know Objectivity Analysis Interpretation Reflection

More information

Intuitive Confidence Reflects Speed of Initial Responses in Point Spread Predictions. Alexander C. Walker. A thesis

Intuitive Confidence Reflects Speed of Initial Responses in Point Spread Predictions. Alexander C. Walker. A thesis Intuitive Confidence Reflects Speed of Initial Responses in Point Spread Predictions by Alexander C. Walker A thesis presented to the University of Waterloo in fulfilment of the thesis requirement for

More information

Striving for perfection and falling short: The influence of goals on probability matching

Striving for perfection and falling short: The influence of goals on probability matching Mem Cogn (2015) 43:748 759 DOI 10.3758/s13421-014-0500-4 Striving for perfection and falling short: The influence of goals on probability matching Jie Gao & James E. Corter Published online: 10 January

More information

MBTI. Populations & Use. Theoretical Background 7/19/2012

MBTI. Populations & Use. Theoretical Background 7/19/2012 MBTI Myers-Briggs Type Indicator Populations & Use General population use, most appropriate for ages 14+ 14 translations available 7 th grade or above reading level Measurement of normal personality differences

More information

Comparing Direct and Indirect Measures of Just Rewards: What Have We Learned?

Comparing Direct and Indirect Measures of Just Rewards: What Have We Learned? Comparing Direct and Indirect Measures of Just Rewards: What Have We Learned? BARRY MARKOVSKY University of South Carolina KIMMO ERIKSSON Mälardalen University We appreciate the opportunity to comment

More information

Further Properties of the Priority Rule

Further Properties of the Priority Rule Further Properties of the Priority Rule Michael Strevens Draft of July 2003 Abstract In Strevens (2003), I showed that science s priority system for distributing credit promotes an allocation of labor

More information

Exploring the reference point in prospect theory

Exploring the reference point in prospect theory 3 Exploring the reference point in prospect theory Gambles for length of life Exploring the reference point in prospect theory: Gambles for length of life. S.M.C. van Osch, W.B. van den Hout, A.M. Stiggelbout

More information

PS3003: Judgment and Decision Making

PS3003: Judgment and Decision Making PS3003: Judgment and Decision Making View Online 1. 2. Ayton P. Judgement and decision making. In: Cognitive psychology. 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2012. 3. Baron J. Normative Models of Judgment

More information

VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW IN BRIEF

VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW IN BRIEF VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW IN BRIEF VOLUME 96 JUNE 15, 2010 PAGES 35 39 REPLY GOOD INTENTIONS MATTER Katharine T. Bartlett * W HILE writing the article to which Professors Mitchell and Bielby have published responses,

More information

UNESCO EOLSS. This article deals with risk-defusing behavior. It is argued that this forms a central part in decision processes.

UNESCO EOLSS. This article deals with risk-defusing behavior. It is argued that this forms a central part in decision processes. RISK-DEFUSING BEHAVIOR Oswald Huber University of Fribourg, Switzerland Keywords: cognitive bias, control, cost of risk-defusing operators, decision making, effect of risk-defusing operators, lottery,

More information

THE USE OF MULTIVARIATE ANALYSIS IN DEVELOPMENT THEORY: A CRITIQUE OF THE APPROACH ADOPTED BY ADELMAN AND MORRIS A. C. RAYNER

THE USE OF MULTIVARIATE ANALYSIS IN DEVELOPMENT THEORY: A CRITIQUE OF THE APPROACH ADOPTED BY ADELMAN AND MORRIS A. C. RAYNER THE USE OF MULTIVARIATE ANALYSIS IN DEVELOPMENT THEORY: A CRITIQUE OF THE APPROACH ADOPTED BY ADELMAN AND MORRIS A. C. RAYNER Introduction, 639. Factor analysis, 639. Discriminant analysis, 644. INTRODUCTION

More information

Behavioral Game Theory

Behavioral Game Theory School of Computer Science, McGill University March 4, 2011 1 2 3 4 5 Outline Nash equilibria One-shot games 1 2 3 4 5 I Nash equilibria One-shot games Definition: A study of actual individual s behaviors

More information

Audio: In this lecture we are going to address psychology as a science. Slide #2

Audio: In this lecture we are going to address psychology as a science. Slide #2 Psychology 312: Lecture 2 Psychology as a Science Slide #1 Psychology As A Science In this lecture we are going to address psychology as a science. Slide #2 Outline Psychology is an empirical science.

More information

PSYCHOLOGICAL CONSCIOUSNESS AND PHENOMENAL CONSCIOUSNESS. Overview

PSYCHOLOGICAL CONSCIOUSNESS AND PHENOMENAL CONSCIOUSNESS. Overview Lecture 28-29 PSYCHOLOGICAL CONSCIOUSNESS AND PHENOMENAL CONSCIOUSNESS Overview David J. Chalmers in his famous book The Conscious Mind 1 tries to establish that the problem of consciousness as the hard

More information

On the diversity principle and local falsifiability

On the diversity principle and local falsifiability On the diversity principle and local falsifiability Uriel Feige October 22, 2012 1 Introduction This manuscript concerns the methodology of evaluating one particular aspect of TCS (theoretical computer

More information

Examples of Feedback Comments: How to use them to improve your report writing. Example 1: Compare and contrast

Examples of Feedback Comments: How to use them to improve your report writing. Example 1: Compare and contrast Examples of Feedback Comments: How to use them to improve your report writing This document contains 4 examples of writing and feedback comments from Level 2A lab reports, and 4 steps to help you apply

More information

I. Introduction. Armin Falk IZA and University of Bonn April Falk: Behavioral Labor Economics: Psychology of Incentives 1/18

I. Introduction. Armin Falk IZA and University of Bonn April Falk: Behavioral Labor Economics: Psychology of Incentives 1/18 I. Introduction Armin Falk IZA and University of Bonn April 2004 1/18 This course Study behavioral effects for labor related outcomes Empirical studies Overview Introduction Psychology of incentives Reciprocity

More information

January 2, Overview

January 2, Overview American Statistical Association Position on Statistical Statements for Forensic Evidence Presented under the guidance of the ASA Forensic Science Advisory Committee * January 2, 2019 Overview The American

More information

PLANNING THE RESEARCH PROJECT

PLANNING THE RESEARCH PROJECT Van Der Velde / Guide to Business Research Methods First Proof 6.11.2003 4:53pm page 1 Part I PLANNING THE RESEARCH PROJECT Van Der Velde / Guide to Business Research Methods First Proof 6.11.2003 4:53pm

More information

When Intuition. Differs from Relative Frequency. Chapter 18. Copyright 2005 Brooks/Cole, a division of Thomson Learning, Inc.

When Intuition. Differs from Relative Frequency. Chapter 18. Copyright 2005 Brooks/Cole, a division of Thomson Learning, Inc. When Intuition Chapter 18 Differs from Relative Frequency Copyright 2005 Brooks/Cole, a division of Thomson Learning, Inc. Thought Question 1: Do you think it likely that anyone will ever win a state lottery

More information

Cognitive modeling versus game theory: Why cognition matters

Cognitive modeling versus game theory: Why cognition matters Cognitive modeling versus game theory: Why cognition matters Matthew F. Rutledge-Taylor (mrtaylo2@connect.carleton.ca) Institute of Cognitive Science, Carleton University, 1125 Colonel By Drive Ottawa,

More information

Sawtooth Software. The Number of Levels Effect in Conjoint: Where Does It Come From and Can It Be Eliminated? RESEARCH PAPER SERIES

Sawtooth Software. The Number of Levels Effect in Conjoint: Where Does It Come From and Can It Be Eliminated? RESEARCH PAPER SERIES Sawtooth Software RESEARCH PAPER SERIES The Number of Levels Effect in Conjoint: Where Does It Come From and Can It Be Eliminated? Dick Wittink, Yale University Joel Huber, Duke University Peter Zandan,

More information

Experimental Testing of Intrinsic Preferences for NonInstrumental Information

Experimental Testing of Intrinsic Preferences for NonInstrumental Information Experimental Testing of Intrinsic Preferences for NonInstrumental Information By Kfir Eliaz and Andrew Schotter* The classical model of decision making under uncertainty assumes that decision makers care

More information

The Regression-Discontinuity Design

The Regression-Discontinuity Design Page 1 of 10 Home» Design» Quasi-Experimental Design» The Regression-Discontinuity Design The regression-discontinuity design. What a terrible name! In everyday language both parts of the term have connotations

More information

Alternative Payoff Mechanisms for Choice under Risk. by James C. Cox, Vjollca Sadiraj Ulrich Schmidt

Alternative Payoff Mechanisms for Choice under Risk. by James C. Cox, Vjollca Sadiraj Ulrich Schmidt Alternative Payoff Mechanisms for Choice under Risk by James C. Cox, Vjollca Sadiraj Ulrich Schmidt No. 1932 June 2014 Kiel Institute for the World Economy, Kiellinie 66, 24105 Kiel, Germany Kiel Working

More information

Decisions based on verbal probabilities: Decision bias or decision by belief sampling?

Decisions based on verbal probabilities: Decision bias or decision by belief sampling? Decisions based on verbal probabilities: Decision bias or decision by belief sampling? Hidehito Honda (hitohonda.02@gmail.com) Graduate School of Arts and Sciences, The University of Tokyo 3-8-1, Komaba,

More information

Involuntary and Voluntary Memory Sequencing Phenomena

Involuntary and Voluntary Memory Sequencing Phenomena 5 Involuntary and Voluntary Memory Sequencing Phenomena An Interesting Puzzle for the Study of Autobiographical Memory Organization and Retrieval Jennifer Talarico and John H. Mace Introduction One of

More information

Gender specific attitudes towards risk and ambiguity an experimental investigation

Gender specific attitudes towards risk and ambiguity an experimental investigation Research Collection Working Paper Gender specific attitudes towards risk and ambiguity an experimental investigation Author(s): Schubert, Renate; Gysler, Matthias; Brown, Martin; Brachinger, Hans Wolfgang

More information

On the Link between Cognitive Control and Heuristic Processes

On the Link between Cognitive Control and Heuristic Processes On the Link between Cognitive Control and Heuristic Processes Edward T. Cokely (cokely@mpib-berlin.mpg.de) Paula Parpart (parpart@mpib-berlin.mpg.de) Lael J. Schooler (schooler@mpib-berlin.mpg.de) Max

More information

GROUP DECISION MAKING IN RISKY ENVIRONMENT ANALYSIS OF GENDER BIAS

GROUP DECISION MAKING IN RISKY ENVIRONMENT ANALYSIS OF GENDER BIAS GROUP DECISION MAKING IN RISKY ENVIRONMENT ANALYSIS OF GENDER BIAS Andrea Vasiľková, Matúš Kubák, Vladimír Gazda, Marek Gróf Abstract Article presents an experimental study of gender bias in group decisions.

More information

Chapter 11. Experimental Design: One-Way Independent Samples Design

Chapter 11. Experimental Design: One-Way Independent Samples Design 11-1 Chapter 11. Experimental Design: One-Way Independent Samples Design Advantages and Limitations Comparing Two Groups Comparing t Test to ANOVA Independent Samples t Test Independent Samples ANOVA Comparing

More information

Introduction to Research Methods

Introduction to Research Methods Introduction to Research Methods Updated August 08, 2016 1 The Three Types of Psychology Research Psychology research can usually be classified as one of three major types: 1. Causal Research When most

More information

References. Christos A. Ioannou 2/37

References. Christos A. Ioannou 2/37 Prospect Theory References Tversky, A., and D. Kahneman: Judgement under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases, Science, 185 (1974), 1124-1131. Tversky, A., and D. Kahneman: Prospect Theory: An Analysis of

More information

A model of parallel time estimation

A model of parallel time estimation A model of parallel time estimation Hedderik van Rijn 1 and Niels Taatgen 1,2 1 Department of Artificial Intelligence, University of Groningen Grote Kruisstraat 2/1, 9712 TS Groningen 2 Department of Psychology,

More information

Why Does Similarity Correlate With Inductive Strength?

Why Does Similarity Correlate With Inductive Strength? Why Does Similarity Correlate With Inductive Strength? Uri Hasson (uhasson@princeton.edu) Psychology Department, Princeton University Princeton, NJ 08540 USA Geoffrey P. Goodwin (ggoodwin@princeton.edu)

More information

Implicit Information in Directionality of Verbal Probability Expressions

Implicit Information in Directionality of Verbal Probability Expressions Implicit Information in Directionality of Verbal Probability Expressions Hidehito Honda (hito@ky.hum.titech.ac.jp) Kimihiko Yamagishi (kimihiko@ky.hum.titech.ac.jp) Graduate School of Decision Science

More information

Evaluating framing e ects

Evaluating framing e ects Journal of Economic Psychology 22 2001) 91±101 www.elsevier.com/locate/joep Evaluating framing e ects James N. Druckman * Department of Political Science, University of Minnesota, 1414 Social Sciences

More information

Rational Choice Theory I: The Foundations of the Theory

Rational Choice Theory I: The Foundations of the Theory Rational Choice Theory I: The Foundations of the Theory Benjamin Ferguson Administrative Keep in mind that your second papers are due this coming Friday at midnight. They should be emailed to me, roughly

More information

Reinforcement Learning : Theory and Practice - Programming Assignment 1

Reinforcement Learning : Theory and Practice - Programming Assignment 1 Reinforcement Learning : Theory and Practice - Programming Assignment 1 August 2016 Background It is well known in Game Theory that the game of Rock, Paper, Scissors has one and only one Nash Equilibrium.

More information

Lec 02: Estimation & Hypothesis Testing in Animal Ecology

Lec 02: Estimation & Hypothesis Testing in Animal Ecology Lec 02: Estimation & Hypothesis Testing in Animal Ecology Parameter Estimation from Samples Samples We typically observe systems incompletely, i.e., we sample according to a designed protocol. We then

More information

Learning Objectives. Learning Objectives 17/03/2016. Chapter 4 Perspectives on Consumer Behavior

Learning Objectives. Learning Objectives 17/03/2016. Chapter 4 Perspectives on Consumer Behavior Chapter 4 Perspectives on Consumer Behavior Copyright 2015 McGraw-Hill Education. All rights reserved. No reproduction or distribution without the prior written consent of McGraw-Hill Education. Learning

More information

Recognizing Ambiguity

Recognizing Ambiguity Recognizing Ambiguity How Lack of Information Scares Us Mark Clements Columbia University I. Abstract In this paper, I will examine two different approaches to an experimental decision problem posed by

More information

good reputation, and less chance to be chosen as potential partners. Fourth, not everyone values a good reputation to the same extent.

good reputation, and less chance to be chosen as potential partners. Fourth, not everyone values a good reputation to the same extent. English Summary 128 English summary English Summary S ocial dilemmas emerge when people experience a conflict between their immediate personal interest and the long-term collective interest of the group

More information

Discrimination and Generalization in Pattern Categorization: A Case for Elemental Associative Learning

Discrimination and Generalization in Pattern Categorization: A Case for Elemental Associative Learning Discrimination and Generalization in Pattern Categorization: A Case for Elemental Associative Learning E. J. Livesey (el253@cam.ac.uk) P. J. C. Broadhurst (pjcb3@cam.ac.uk) I. P. L. McLaren (iplm2@cam.ac.uk)

More information

Are Retrievals from Long-Term Memory Interruptible?

Are Retrievals from Long-Term Memory Interruptible? Are Retrievals from Long-Term Memory Interruptible? Michael D. Byrne byrne@acm.org Department of Psychology Rice University Houston, TX 77251 Abstract Many simple performance parameters about human memory

More information

Why do Psychologists Perform Research?

Why do Psychologists Perform Research? PSY 102 1 PSY 102 Understanding and Thinking Critically About Psychological Research Thinking critically about research means knowing the right questions to ask to assess the validity or accuracy of a

More information

Running head: INDIVIDUAL DIFFERENCES 1. Why to treat subjects as fixed effects. James S. Adelman. University of Warwick.

Running head: INDIVIDUAL DIFFERENCES 1. Why to treat subjects as fixed effects. James S. Adelman. University of Warwick. Running head: INDIVIDUAL DIFFERENCES 1 Why to treat subjects as fixed effects James S. Adelman University of Warwick Zachary Estes Bocconi University Corresponding Author: James S. Adelman Department of

More information

Lecture 4: Research Approaches

Lecture 4: Research Approaches Lecture 4: Research Approaches Lecture Objectives Theories in research Research design approaches ú Experimental vs. non-experimental ú Cross-sectional and longitudinal ú Descriptive approaches How to

More information

This is an Author's Original Manuscript of an article submitted to Behavior & Brain Science and may differ from the final version which is available here: http://journals.cambridge.org/action/displayabstract?frompage=online&aid=8242505

More information

Comparative Ignorance and the Ellsberg Paradox

Comparative Ignorance and the Ellsberg Paradox The Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 22:2; 129 139, 2001 2001 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Manufactured in The Netherlands. Comparative Ignorance and the Ellsberg Paradox CLARE CHUA CHOW National University

More information

Psych 1Chapter 2 Overview

Psych 1Chapter 2 Overview Psych 1Chapter 2 Overview After studying this chapter, you should be able to answer the following questions: 1) What are five characteristics of an ideal scientist? 2) What are the defining elements of

More information

Introduction to Behavioral Economics Like the subject matter of behavioral economics, this course is divided into two parts:

Introduction to Behavioral Economics Like the subject matter of behavioral economics, this course is divided into two parts: Economics 142: Behavioral Economics Spring 2008 Vincent Crawford (with very large debts to Colin Camerer of Caltech, David Laibson of Harvard, and especially Botond Koszegi and Matthew Rabin of UC Berkeley)

More information

Verbal and behavioural indicators of trust: How well are they associated? Nigel Harvey University College London. Harvey Toulouse October 2009

Verbal and behavioural indicators of trust: How well are they associated? Nigel Harvey University College London. Harvey Toulouse October 2009 Verbal and behavioural indicators of trust: How well are they associated? Nigel Harvey University College London Outline Definitions of trust Some research issues for psychologists Ways of studying trust

More information

Quality Digest Daily, March 3, 2014 Manuscript 266. Statistics and SPC. Two things sharing a common name can still be different. Donald J.

Quality Digest Daily, March 3, 2014 Manuscript 266. Statistics and SPC. Two things sharing a common name can still be different. Donald J. Quality Digest Daily, March 3, 2014 Manuscript 266 Statistics and SPC Two things sharing a common name can still be different Donald J. Wheeler Students typically encounter many obstacles while learning

More information

Behavioral Game Theory

Behavioral Game Theory Outline (September 3, 2007) Outline (September 3, 2007) Introduction Outline (September 3, 2007) Introduction Examples of laboratory experiments Outline (September 3, 2007) Introduction Examples of laboratory

More information

Is probability matching smart? Associations between probabilistic choices and cognitive ability

Is probability matching smart? Associations between probabilistic choices and cognitive ability Memory & Cognition 2003, 31 (2), 243-251 Is probability matching smart? Associations between probabilistic choices and cognitive ability RICHARD F. WEST James Madison University, Harrisonburg, Virginia

More information

Chapter 02 Developing and Evaluating Theories of Behavior

Chapter 02 Developing and Evaluating Theories of Behavior Chapter 02 Developing and Evaluating Theories of Behavior Multiple Choice Questions 1. A theory is a(n): A. plausible or scientifically acceptable, well-substantiated explanation of some aspect of the

More information

On the Conjunction Fallacy in Probability Judgment: New Experimental Evidence

On the Conjunction Fallacy in Probability Judgment: New Experimental Evidence On the Conjunction Fallacy in Probability Judgment: New Experimental Evidence June 6, 2008 Abstract This paper reports the results of experiments designed to test whether and to what extent individuals

More information

An Investigation of Factors Influencing Causal Attributions in Managerial Decision Making

An Investigation of Factors Influencing Causal Attributions in Managerial Decision Making Marketing Letters 9:3 (1998): 301 312 1998 Kluwer Academic Publishers, Manufactured in The Netherlands An Investigation of Factors Influencing Causal Attributions in Managerial Decision Making SUNDER NARAYANAN

More information

DePaul Journal of Health Care Law

DePaul Journal of Health Care Law DePaul Journal of Health Care Law Volume 10 Issue 4 Summer 2007: Book Review Issue Article 4 Against Bioethics Margaret Byrne Follow this and additional works at: https://via.library.depaul.edu/jhcl Recommended

More information

A Brief Introduction to Bayesian Statistics

A Brief Introduction to Bayesian Statistics A Brief Introduction to Statistics David Kaplan Department of Educational Psychology Methods for Social Policy Research and, Washington, DC 2017 1 / 37 The Reverend Thomas Bayes, 1701 1761 2 / 37 Pierre-Simon

More information

Choice adaptation to increasing and decreasing event probabilities

Choice adaptation to increasing and decreasing event probabilities Choice adaptation to increasing and decreasing event probabilities Samuel Cheyette (sjcheyette@gmail.com) Dynamic Decision Making Laboratory, Carnegie Mellon University Pittsburgh, PA. 15213 Emmanouil

More information

Reduce Tension by Making the Desired Choice Easier

Reduce Tension by Making the Desired Choice Easier Daniel Kahneman Talk at Social and Behavioral Sciences Meeting at OEOB Reduce Tension by Making the Desired Choice Easier Here is one of the best theoretical ideas that psychology has to offer developed

More information

Chapter 1 Introduction to I/O Psychology

Chapter 1 Introduction to I/O Psychology Chapter 1 Introduction to I/O Psychology 1. I/O Psychology is a branch of psychology that in the workplace. a. treats psychological disorders b. applies the principles of psychology c. provides therapy

More information

Generalization and Theory-Building in Software Engineering Research

Generalization and Theory-Building in Software Engineering Research Generalization and Theory-Building in Software Engineering Research Magne Jørgensen, Dag Sjøberg Simula Research Laboratory {magne.jorgensen, dagsj}@simula.no Abstract The main purpose of this paper is

More information

1 The conceptual underpinnings of statistical power

1 The conceptual underpinnings of statistical power 1 The conceptual underpinnings of statistical power The importance of statistical power As currently practiced in the social and health sciences, inferential statistics rest solidly upon two pillars: statistical

More information

Chapter 6: Attribution Processes

Chapter 6: Attribution Processes Chapter 6: Attribution Processes 1. Which of the following is an example of an attributional process in social cognition? a. The act of planning the actions to take given a social situation b. The act

More information

Human and Optimal Exploration and Exploitation in Bandit Problems

Human and Optimal Exploration and Exploitation in Bandit Problems Human and Optimal Exploration and ation in Bandit Problems Shunan Zhang (szhang@uci.edu) Michael D. Lee (mdlee@uci.edu) Miles Munro (mmunro@uci.edu) Department of Cognitive Sciences, 35 Social Sciences

More information

More on Methodological Issues in Free-Response Psi Experiments

More on Methodological Issues in Free-Response Psi Experiments Other Methodology Articles More on Methodological Issues in Free-Response Psi Experiments J. E. KENNEDY (Original publication and copyright: Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 1979,

More information

Qualitative Data Analysis. Richard Boateng, PhD. Arguments with Qualitative Data. Office: UGBS RT18 (rooftop)

Qualitative Data Analysis. Richard Boateng, PhD. Arguments with Qualitative Data. Office: UGBS RT18 (rooftop) Qualitative Data Analysis Lecturer/Convenor: Richard Boateng, PhD. Email: richard@pearlrichards.org Office: UGBS RT18 (rooftop) Arguments with Qualitative Data Photo Illustrations from Getty Images www.gettyimages.com

More information

[1] provides a philosophical introduction to the subject. Simon [21] discusses numerous topics in economics; see [2] for a broad economic survey.

[1] provides a philosophical introduction to the subject. Simon [21] discusses numerous topics in economics; see [2] for a broad economic survey. Draft of an article to appear in The MIT Encyclopedia of the Cognitive Sciences (Rob Wilson and Frank Kiel, editors), Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press, 1997. Copyright c 1997 Jon Doyle. All rights reserved

More information

HERO. Rational addiction theory a survey of opinions UNIVERSITY OF OSLO HEALTH ECONOMICS RESEARCH PROGRAMME. Working paper 2008: 7

HERO. Rational addiction theory a survey of opinions UNIVERSITY OF OSLO HEALTH ECONOMICS RESEARCH PROGRAMME. Working paper 2008: 7 Rational addiction theory a survey of opinions Hans Olav Melberg Institute of Health Management and Health Economics UNIVERSITY OF OSLO HEALTH ECONOMICS RESEARCH PROGRAMME Working paper 2008: 7 HERO Rational

More information

This article appeared in a journal published by Elsevier. The attached copy is furnished to the author for internal non-commercial research and

This article appeared in a journal published by Elsevier. The attached copy is furnished to the author for internal non-commercial research and This article appeared in a journal published by Elsevier. The attached copy is furnished to the author for internal non-commercial research and education use, including for instruction at the authors institution

More information

Streak Biases in Decision Making: Data and a Memory Model

Streak Biases in Decision Making: Data and a Memory Model Streak Biases in Decision Making: Data and a Memory Model Erik M. Altmann (ema@msu.edu) Bruce D. Burns (burnsbr@msu.edu) Department of Psychology Michigan State University East Lansing, MI Abstract Streaks

More information

Response Availability and the Apparent Spontaneity of Numerical Choices

Response Availability and the Apparent Spontaneity of Numerical Choices Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance 1977, Vol. 3, No. 2, 359-364 Response Availability and the Apparent Spontaneity of Numerical Choices Michael Kubovy Yale University

More information

The Game Prisoners Really Play: Preference Elicitation and the Impact of Communication

The Game Prisoners Really Play: Preference Elicitation and the Impact of Communication The Game Prisoners Really Play: Preference Elicitation and the Impact of Communication Michael Kosfeld University of Zurich Ernst Fehr University of Zurich October 10, 2003 Unfinished version: Please do

More information

Is It Time for a Tri-Process Theory? Distinguishing the Reflective and the Algorithmic Mind. Keith E. Stanovich University of Toronto

Is It Time for a Tri-Process Theory? Distinguishing the Reflective and the Algorithmic Mind. Keith E. Stanovich University of Toronto Is It Time for a Tri-Process Theory? Distinguishing the Reflective and the Algorithmic Mind Keith E. Stanovich University of Toronto Missing Components of Current Dual-Process Theories and Their Implications

More information