Discussion Paper No. 288 Fairness: A Critique to the Utilitarian Approach Philipp Kircher* Alvaro Sandroni** Sandra Ludwig***

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Discussion Paper No. 288 Fairness: A Critique to the Utilitarian Approach Philipp Kircher* Alvaro Sandroni** Sandra Ludwig***"

Transcription

1 Discussion Paper No. 288 Fairness: A Critique to the Utilitarian Approach Philipp Kircher* Alvaro Sandroni** Sandra Ludwig*** *Department of Economics, University of Pennsylvania kircher@econ.upenn.edu **Department of Economics, University of Pennsylvania sandroni@sas.upenn.edu *** Department of Economics, University of Munich sandra.ludwig@lrz.uni-muenchen.de November 2009 Financial support from the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft through SFB/TR 15 is gratefully acknowledged. Sonderforschungsbereich/Transregio 15 Universität Mannheim Freie Universität Berlin Humboldt-Universität zu Berlin Ludwig-Maximilians-Universität München Rheinische Friedrich-Wilhelms-Universität Bonn Zentrum für Europäische Wirtschaftsforschung Mannheim Speaker: Prof. Dr. Urs Schweizer. Department of Economics University of Bonn D Bonn, Phone: +49(0228) Fax: +49(0228)739221

2 Fairness: A Critique to the Utilitarian Approach Philipp Kircher, Sandra Ludwig and Alvaro Sandroni November 27, 2009 Abstract We address a basic difficulty with incorporating fairness into standard utilitarian choice theories. Standard utilitarian theories evaluate lotteries according to the (weighted) utility over final outcomes and assume in particular that a lottery is never preferred over getting the most preferred underlying outcome with certainty. While nearly universally adopted in economics (including behavioral economics) and appealing for choices among consumption goods, this approach is problematic when choices directly affect the payoffs of other individuals. A difficulty is that randomization may in itself be valued as a desirable procedure for allocating scarce resources. We highlight this in two simple choice settings. Individuals can choose between three options: to get more money; to get less money and some other good; to flip a coin between these two alternatives. When the good is a regular consumption good like a coffee mug, hardly any of our subjects randomize. When the good is a social good that yields payoffs directly to some other individual, nearly a third of our subjects choose to randomize. Our results indicate that fairness concerns are conducive to behavioral anomalies that the standard utilitarian model cannot accommodate. JEL Classification: D81, C91, D63 Keywords: risky choice, betweenness axiom, social preferences, preference for randomness Financial support from LMUexcellent, the National Science Foundation, grant SES , and SFB/TR 15 is gratefully acknowledged. For providing laboratory resources we kindly thank MELESSA of the University of Munich. Philipp Kircher <kircher@econ.upenn.edu> and Alvaro Sandroni <sandroni@sas.upenn.edu> may be reached at the Department of Economics, University of Pennsylvania. Sandra Ludwig <sandra.ludwig@lrz.uni-muenchen.de> may be reached at Department of Economics, University of Munich.

3 1 Introduction The allocation of scarce resources is one of the most basic concerns in economics. In most economic analysis of resource allocation, agents derive utility from the resources they get, but not from the resources other agents receive. 1 However, behavior in laboratory experiments and in the field does not always support this assumption. In particular, subjects seem to care about the perceived fairness of social allocations. In fact, a decision maker, henceforth called Dee, may be willing to sacrifice some of her resources in order to improve the fairness of social outcomes. One of the most successful approaches to the question of how to incorporate fairness into economic analysis was proposed, among several others, by Bolton and Ockenfels (2000) and Fehr and Schmidt (1999). The key to the success of this approach is the demonstration that fairness can be incorporated into Dee s utility in a parsimonious way and still lead to vast improvements in the ability to accommodate observed behavior. Others have followed with different ideas how agents incorporate a concern for others (e.g., Charness and Rabin, 2002, incorporate a concern for efficiency and Kirchsteiger, 1994, incorporates envy). A common feature of these approaches is that they rely on the idea that people s utility u(x) is defined over an outcome x that not only includes Dee s own resources but also those of the other people. If Dee cares sufficiently about the consumption of the other people, she may give up some of her own resources to increase the consumption of the others. Hence, giving up money can be interpreted as buying a social good consisting of the resources that others get. These models then rely on expected utility theory to deal with the uncertainty that is typically associated with the payoff-relevant decisions. 2 In contrast to these approaches, we argue that there is a basic difficulty in incorporating fairness directly into Dee s utility function. We argue that expected utility theory may not fully capture Dee s concerns for fairness and, in addition, the basic limitation of expected utility extends to any utilitarian theory of choice, no matter how the idea of fairness is built into Dee s utility function. Before proceeding, it may be useful to define precisely what we mean by an utilitarian framework. The utilitarian approach assumes that risky prospects can be evaluated by the utilities arising from final outcomes. The most well-known utilitarian model is expected utility theory. After Allais s critique, alternative models, like non-expected utility theory, were produced (for a survey see e.g. Starmer, 2000, Machina, 1987, and Weber and Camerer, 1987). Non-expected utility theory is more flexible than expected utility theory. It can accommodate choices like in the Allais (1953) paradox, but usually satisfies, among other properties, a weak dominance property that we call Property U: a lottery l can never be preferred over getting the best of its deterministic outcomes (x 1,x 2,..,x n ) for sure, i.e. U(l) max u(x i). 3 i=1,...,n (U) Property U is a minimalistic requirement for the utilitarian approach, because the right hand side 1 We abstract from the usual exceptions made to relatives and closely related groups. 2 For example, Fehr and Schmidt (1999) propose that 60% of the agents are much less fairness-motivated than the other 40%. In nearly all game-theoretic laboratory settings that they analyse this introduces uncertainty over the actions of the other players, and thus over the final allocation of resources. 3 Gneezy et al. (2006) refer to a similar property as the internality axiom. 1

4 captures the revealed choice over final outcomes without uncertainty. This property is weaker than the monotonicity axiom in Dekel (1986) which is itself a weaker version of first order stochastic dominance, and it is weaker than the betweenness axioms in Chew (1983) and Dekel (1986). 4 Hence, we define the utilitarian approach as models of decisions such that risky prospects can be evaluated by the utilities arising from final outcomes with the additional minimal requirement that Property U holds. When the decision involves whether or not to buy a regular good like a coffee mug, Property U seems so intuitive that it is difficult to see how it could not apply to most consumers. If Dee likes the mug, she buys it. If she does not like it, she does not. This seems to be consistent with our intuition about private goods. It might not, however, be consistent with our intuition about social goods. Our argument is based on the idea that, when decisions affect other people as well, Dee may care not only about final outcomes, but also about the means by which the outcomes were produced. This argument is far from original and can be traced back at least to the following thought experiment proposed by Machina (1989). 5 Assume that Dee has two children and one indivisible toy. Dee can decide which of her children gets the toy or she can flip a fair coin to make this determination. It is plausible that Dee strictly prefers the coin flip if it seems (to her) that this is a less partial procedure than giving the toy to either child deterministically. So, a coin flip may be desirable if it is seen as fair. Yet, this directly violates Property U, no matter how the utility of each outcome is defined. Hence, one cannot accommodate the behavior described by Machina by incorporating fairness concerns in the utility u(x i ) of each outcome. Whether this behavior is present in real life is a question of empirical investigation: It could be that the mother thinks that the decision is too important to leave it to the whim of a coin-flip, or she could indeed find the coin-flip particularly attractive. Even though Machina s thought experiment is so well-known, empirical research on this idea is rather sparse. 6 This may be due to the unusual feature that Dee makes the decision over the outcome of two other people and that there are no direct monetary consequences for her. This may raise the concern that violations of dominance occur in the rather special circumstances in which Dee is indifferent over the lottery s outcomes. But consider a related environment in which Dee is one of the two recipients and, therefore, Dee is directly involved in the lottery s outcomes. This makes the possibility of indifference, though theoretically possible, rather implausible because it would entail an accidental choice of the exact values that produce subjects indifference. 7 The basic idea is that concerns for fairness might 4 It is weaker than the monotonicity axiom as it only refers to outcomes in the support of the lottery (i.e. elementary lotteries are considered) and not any other outcome. It is weaker than the betweenness axiom because it does not involve compound lotteries. To compare with first order stochastic dominance, the underlying space x first needs an order, which naturally arises by ordering outcomes by the utility u(x) of their certain outcome. Such a notion is present for example in the ordinal first order stochastic dominance approach in Spector, Leshno and Ben Horin (1996) and in the approach to dominance in probabilities in Karni and Zafra (2002). 5 The basis of Machina s thought experiment is Diamond s (1967) critique of the EU model for social choice (in particular the independence axiom) due to interpersonal fairness. 6 We included hypothetical versions of Machina s parental example in our experiments. We asked 56 participants to imagine they are a mother with 2 kids and to have only 1 candy. They had to decide whether to give kid 1 or kid 2 the candy or let a coin toss decide. About 95% chose the coin toss. 101 participants faced a modified version, in which we try to break indifference: the mother has a green candy and kid 1 likes green candies, while kid 2 likes red candies. Here, still 67% choose the coin toss and the remainder to give the candy to kid 1. 7 This also corresponds to many experimental settings in which the decision-maker himself bears some of the material 2

5 induce Dee to randomize rather than to allocate deterministically to any party. As we argued above, randomization as a fair procedure (or, more generally, any form of strict preference for randomization) cannot be captured by an utilitarian framework. We test this idea in a controlled laboratory experiment. In the experiment Dee has the choice between two alternatives 1 and 2, and she can also choose a lottery by which either alternative is equally likely. In alternative 1 she obtains more money than in alternative 2, but some other subject obtains less money in alternative 1 than in alternative 2. Choosing 2 over 1 can thus be interpreted as buying a social good at private expense. Like in other experiments, we observe that some subjects (30% of the population) prefer to sacrifice resources and choose 2. In itself, this is not a violation of the utilitarian model and can simply be interpreted as Dee having greater utility from buying the social good. However, we also observe that a substantial fraction of the subjects (30% of the population) chooses to randomize between the two alternatives. A 30% fraction is arguably of economically significant magnitude. It is also statistically significantly larger than randomization for standard goods like a mug (which we discuss in detail below) for which randomization is negligible. The use of randomization devices may be appealing because it is perceived as a fair procedure to share resources. Yet, other explanations are possible. However, independently of its interpretation, strict preferences for randomization cannot be accommodated in an utilitarian framework. 8 We explicitly do not intend a general challenge of either the utilitarian framework or expected utility theory in particular. Rather, our results cast doubt on the applicability of the utilitarian framework to social settings. While the suitability of expected utility theory can be questioned even for standard consumption choices, these difficulties often involve complex compound lotteries (as e.g. in Kahneman and Tversky, 1979, and the followup literature). Here we use a very simple lottery that assigns equal probabilities to two events. This specification is arguably familiar to most subjects. Thus, the social component of the outcomes seems to be the driving force of our experimental results. To check this, we also ran an alternative treatment with different subjects. Here, Dee again chooses between two alternatives, 1 and 2, or a randomization between them. But, in this treatment, the trade off is not money vs a social good. The trade off is between money and a consumption good (a coffee mug 9 ). Alternative 1 yields more money but no mug, while alternative 2 yields a mug but less money. The proportion of subjects who buy the mug turned out to be similar to the proportion of subjects who buy the social good, but the proportion of subjects who decide at random (6% of the population) is very small and statistically significantly smaller then in the case of a social good purchase. These results support the claim that fairness concerns are particularly conducive to a particular type of behavioral anomaly (i.e., a preference for randomization) that the utilitarian model cannot accommodate. Hence, there is a tension between the idea of incorporating fairness into economics and the decision-theoretic models commonly used in economics. consequences of his choice about the resource allocation. The canonical example is a dictator game. 8 We acknowledge that the unlikely scenario of a large indifference band, in which many agents are absolutely indifferent between their own consumption and that of the other person, would allow an utilitarian framework to be consistent with these observations. We find this explanation not very persuasive, and note that we did not attempt to calibrate, i.e. we did not run any other experiments with a similar setup that are not reported here. 9 In the tradition of Kahneman et al. (1990), who analyzed the endowment effect with coffee mugs, we use coffee mugs because there are no apparent norms in favor or against buying such mugs. 3

6 Related Literature There is a large literature on individual choice under uncertainty discussing the appropriateness of the expected utility model and demonstrating empirical violations of the imposed linearity in probabilities of the individual preference function or equivalently the independence axiom (for a review see e.g. Machina, 1987). Empirical violations are widespread, in particular the common consequence effect (a special case of which is the Allais paradox) and the common ratio effect. The evidence of systematic violations led to generalizations in the form of non-expected utility models where the utility of final outcomes is weighted non-linearly in the probabilities (see Starmer, 2000, Machina, 1987, and Weber and Camerer, 1987, for overviews). These generalized models are typically based on betweenness 10, a weakened form of the independence axiom but still stronger than our Property U. 11 Empirical violations of betweenness so far can mainly be traced back to violations of the much more subtle axiom of reduction of compound lotteries, see Camerer and Ho (1994) for a survey and evidence. An exception is Gneezy et al. (2006), who provide empirical evidence that people may value a lottery less than its worst possible outcome (see, however, Keren and Willemsen, 2009, and Ortmann et al., 2009, for a critical debate of Gneezy et al. s findings). This idea of randomization aversion challenges the utilitarian framework in a very different way from our study where people exhibit a preference for randomization. Their focus is very different from ours, though: In none of these studies social concerns are incorporated or considered as a possible source of the violations. Hence, comparisons between results obtained with social goods and results obtained with private goods only (a focus of our analysis) are not considered in these studies. The theoretical literature on social preferences typically assumes social preferences and postulates expected utility, e.g. Bolton and Ockenfels (2000) and Fehr and Schmidt (1999). There are some exceptions. Karni and Safra (2002) consider individuals that have two preference relations, one over the fairness of the lottery and one over the personal material well-being. Their axioms give a single utility representation over final choices that allows for a violation of Property U. Similarly, the axiomatization in Borah (2009) allows for a violation of Property U based on concerns for procedures. The theoretical work of Borah (2009) is directly relevant to our empirical findings and partially motivated by questions raised by our experiments (see also Ok and Kockesen, 2000; Neilson, 2006; Sandbu, 2008; Maccheroni et al., 2008; Trautmann, 2009; and Rohde, forthcoming; for related decision-theoretic work on otherregarding preferences). Despite a huge number of empirical studies on social preferences, only very few deal with social preferences in the presence of uncertainty although this is crucial for applying the existing theories (e.g. Bolton and Ockenfels, 2000, assume that individuals social preferences differ and therefore the outcomes in the games that they analyze are stochastic). None of these studies compares social and private goods (the key to our experiment). Among the few studies that assess social preferences under uncertainty, Bolton et al. (2005) investigate people s perceptions of fair procedures in an ultimatum game with proposers of procedures and 10 See for example prospect theory (Kahneman and Tversky, 1979), weighted utility theory (Chew, 1983), implicit expected utility (Dekel, 1986), and disappointment theory (Gul, 1991). 11 Generalizations which do not assume betweenness are those in the quadratic class (e.g. Machina, 1982) and those in the rank dependent or cumulative class (e.g. Quiggin, 1982). 4

7 responders. They focus on the responders reactions to their treatment by the proposers, in particular the acceptance rates of offers that favour the proposer. These acceptance rates of these unfair offers are the same when the proposer had the option to choose a fair procedure than if he had the option to choose a fair deterministic allocation. Moreover, if the unfair proposal is made by a fair random draw and not by a human player, acceptance rates are higher. In a study by Krawcyk and Le Lec (2008), individuals face a sequence of deterministic and stochastic dictator games in which the dictator can choose any split of the surplus (in deterministic and stochastic terms, depending on the choice situation). They find mixed evidence. In the stochastic dictator game the fraction of individuals that choose some interior probability is non-trivial, but most of these individuals choose very low probabilities at near selfish levels. The strength of their study is that subjects play a series of deterministic and stochastic dictator games of which one is randomly chosen for payment, so that giving behavior can be compared within subject. The drawback is that subjects might take the intuition from deterministic dictator games over to stochastic dictator games, 12 subjects have to compound the lottery of the stochastic offer with the lottery over the game that is chosen for payment, and the choice among a large number of interior probabilities makes interior choices more prominent in the design. Karni et al. (2008) consider 3-person dictator games and focus on whether a subject cares about the inequality and (procedural) fairness between the two other players. They find that a substantial fraction of subjects is willing to give up own probability of getting a prize to reach a fairer overall allocation procedure. Their framework is complementary but substantially more complicated and without available alternatives that give sure outcomes. Our setup was designed to be as simple as possible, without compounded lotteries, and with only a very limited number of easily understandable choices. Our setup is closely linked to the debates about the axiomatic foundations of decision theory under risk. Unlike previous empirical studies, we assess the magnitude of randomization relative to other (non-social) choice situations. This approach rules out that the idea that individuals have a general propensity to randomize, since for our standard good a revealed preference for randomization is nearly absent, identifying the social part of the experiment as a main driver behind randomization. 2 The Experiment Our experimental sessions were run at the Munich Experimental Laboratory for Economic and Social Sciences (MELESSA) in Germany in individuals (mainly students from the universities of Munich) participated in the experiment. They were randomly assigned to sessions and could take part in one session only. For the recruitment we used the software ORSEE by Greiner (2004). The experiment was programmed and conducted with the experimental software z-tree by Fischbacher (2007). The sessions lasted about half an hour. Subjects were randomly assigned an individual computer terminal in the laboratory. They could not see other subjects decisions. Individuals were handed out the instructions 13 for the experiment and had time to go through the instructions on their own and ask 12 Although the order of play is varied, subjects are informed that they play both types of games. 13 Original instructions are written in German and are available from the authors upon request. See the Appendix for translated instructions. 5

8 questions. After all individuals had finished the instructions and all remaining questions had been answered, we proceeded to the decision stage. Payoffs were expressed in the experimental currency Taler, which were converted at a known exchange rate (2 to 1) to Euros at the end of the experiment (at the time of the experiment 1e 1.57 USD). The social good treatment: To analyze whether concerns for fairness induce a preference for randomization, we conduct the following modified dictator game experiment with 92 participants. Participants are randomly matched into groups of two. In each group, one participant (Dee) has the choice between two alternatives 1 and 2, or she can choose a lottery by which either alternative is equally likely, while the other participant makes no payoff relevant decision. 14 Alternative 1 means that Dee receives 7.50eand the participant matched to her receives 0e. Alternative 2 means that both, Dee and her matched partner receive 5 e. Hence, Dee s decision is whether she wants to give up 2.50 e such that her matched participant receives 5e(i.e. to buy the social good ) or not, or whether she wants to randomize. 15 The matched partner is informed about Dee s decision problem and learns her decision in the end of the experiment. In an outcome-based view, Dee has a preference for one of the two certain outcomes alternative 1 or 2. If preferences satisfy Property U, randomization leads to lower utility than one of the two certain outcomes. Thus, utilitarian models cannot accommodate choices of the lottery except for case of indifference between alternative 1 and 2. We observe that most decision makers (46%) choose to keep the money (alternative 1), while as many choose to randomize as to buy the social good (28%). Hence, we find evidence for systematic violations of Property U and thus the utilitarian framework. Further evidence for a preference for randomization stems from donation choices that we included in other experiments (before subjects knew their payoffs): We ask 60 Participants whether they either want to receive 1 additional Euro, or to donate the Euro to the German Red Cross, or whether they want to randomize between the two alternatives. In line with the observations above we observe that most decision makers (52%) choose to keep the money. Again, a significant fraction (25%) chooses to randomize. The remainder choose to buy the social good (23%). One may wonder whether subjects who violate expected utility theory (EUT) in other situations are particularly prone to violate Property U. In the social good treatment, we therefore let subjects make the standard, hypothetical Allais-Paradox-lottery choices. The first choice is between the lotteries L 1 and L 2, where L 1 : Euros with 100%; L 2 : 2.5 million Euros with 10%, Euros with 89% and 0 Euros with 1%. The second choice is between L 1 : Euros with 11%, 0 Euros with 89% and L 2 : 2.5 million Euros with 10%, and 0 Euros with 90%. A violation of expected utility theory involves choosing L 1 in one situation but L 2 in the other. While 35% of the subjects violate EUT, this seems to be unrelated to the preference for randomization that we observe, since only one subject (8%) out of those subjects who choose to randomize violates EUT in the lottery choice. Hence, there seems to be no relation between the two phenomena, which is not surprising because the Allais Paradox relies on compounding of lotteries, which is not present in our setting. 14 The random allocation to a cubicle also determined an individual s role in the experiment. 15 The magnitude of the payments is well within the range used in other experiments to get insights into social preferences. On average, participants earned 9.4eincluding a 5eshow-up fee. 6

9 Figure 1: Social good vs mug decisions Percentage % % 0 Take money Randomize Buy social good/mug social good mug The standard good (mug) treatment: Two important questions arise in the context of the previous findings. Do people have a general propensity to randomize, for example simply due to mistakes or trembles? Or might they generally prefer to randomize even in non-social settings where normative aspects are less pronounced? To get a first insight, we conduct an experiment in which no social concerns are present but which is otherwise as similar to the social good experiment as possible. 48 other individuals were asked to decide whether to buy a regular good (a coffee mug). 16 From a 7.50eshow up fee, participants had to decide whether to give up 2.50eto get the mug (including 3 tea bags), or to keep the entire show-up fee and forgo the mug, or to randomize between both options. In the beginning of the experiment, we show subjects the mug and tell them that it is only available at the online shop of the Ludwigs-Maximilians university of Munich at a price of about 6e. In the Appendix we show a picture of the coffee mug. We observe that 54% do not buy the mug, 6% randomize and 40% buy the mug. The fraction of people randomizing is very small. Figure 2 shows the results of both experiments. A Fisher exact test indicates that the fractions of subjects that choose to randomize or not (i.e. bundling those who do not randomize) differ significantly across experiments (p = 0.006, two-sided). 17 The observation that people do not randomize is robust across additional sessions that we run with different prices for the mug. 18 We take this as initial indication that neither a propensity to tremble nor a general preference 16 Since the mug choice is so trivial, individuals made in addition a decision in an unrelated voting experiment in which they could earn 0,7, or 10 Euro. They made the mug choice before they knew their earnings. We kept the personal cost of the mug at 2.50e, which corresponds to the 2.50epersonal cost of the social good before. The complete (translated) instructions are in the Appendix. 17 Given the small number of subjects that randomize in the mug experiment, a Fisher exact test seems more appropriate than a Pearson chi-square test. The latter however yields a similar result (p = 0.005). Instead of bundling those who take the money or buy the good, we can test for a relation between treatments using all three choice options (randomization, take the money, or buy the good). Again, both tests indicate a significant treatment difference (Fisher exact test: p = 0.016; Pearson chi-square test p = 0.017). 18 We conducted sessions without the tea and at prices of 1.50e and 2.50e for the mug. In no treatment did more than 10% of the individuals randomize. Without the tea and at price of 2.50, very few people bought the mug (83% did not buy, 8% randomize), at 1.50 without the tea the fractions of people buying or not buying the mug is comparable to the 7

10 for randomization can explain the choices in the social goods treatment Conclusion Fairness concerns have attracted increasing interest in the economics literature in recent years. Among other areas, they are important in family economics, in charitable giving, and in political economy models about transfers. An important part of this agenda is to find preference specifications that allow a parsimonious representation for social concerns that captures main social concerns. In this study we challenge the view that utilitarian choice-theoretic models provide the right framework to accommodate social concerns. When a social good is present, we find a violation of a very basic dominance property and thus also the independence axiom and first order stochastic dominance. These violations may have gone relatively unnoticed for long perhaps because they are much harder to find for standard consumption goods, which was the focus of most economic analysis until recently. Several factors may underlie preferences for randomization in social situations. They include procedural fairness and a desire to avoid responsibility. Whatever the psychological underpinnings, this study highlights that observed choice behavior does display a revealed preference for randomization in social settings. This result challenges the basic utilitarian approach and motivates additional empirical research on the economic relevance of this phenomenon. References [1] Allais, M. (1953), Le Comportement de L homme Rationnel Devant le Risque: Critique des Postulats et Axiomes de L ecole Americane, Econometrica, 21, [2] Bell, D. E. (1982), Regret in Decision Making under Uncertainty, Operations Research, XXX, [3] Bolton, G. and A. Ockenfels (2000), ERC A Theory of Equity, Reciprocity and Competition, American Economic Review, 90 (1), [4] Bolton, G., Brandts, J. and A. Ockenfels (2005), Fair procedures: Evidence from games involving lotteries, The Economic Journal 115, [5] Borah, A. (2009), Other regarding preferences in environments of risk, mimeo, University of Pennsylvania. [6] Charness, G. and M. Rabin (2002), Understanding social preferences with simple tests, The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 117, [7] Dekel, E. (1986), An axiomatic characterization of preference under uncertainty: Weakening the independence axiom, Journal of Economic Theory 40, setting reported (35% buy, 10% randomize). 19 Subjects again make the aforementioned Allais-Paradox-lottery choice. None of the few subjects who choose to randomize violates EUT in the lottery choice. 8

11 [8] Diamond, P. A. (1967), Cardinal welfare, individualistic ethics, and intertemporal comparisons of utility: Comment, Journal of Political Economy 75, [9] Fehr, E., and K. Schmidt (1999), A theory of fairness, competition, and cooperation, The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 114, [10] Gneezy, U., List, J.A., and G. Wu (2006), The uncertainty effect: When a risky prospect is valued less than its worst outcome, The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 121 (4), [11] Gul, F. (1991), A theory of disappointment in decision making under uncertainty, Econometrica, LIX, [12] Kahneman, D. and A. Tversky (1979), Prospect theory: An analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica, 47, [13] Kahneman, D., Knetsch, J., and R. Thaler (1990), Experimental tests of the endowment effect and the Coase theorem. Journal of Political Economy, 98(6), [14] Karni, E., and Z. Safra (2002), Individual sense of justice: a utility representation, Econometrica, 70, [15] Karni, E., Salmon, T. and B. Sopher (2008), Individual sense of fairness: An experimental study, Experimental Economics, 11(2), [16] Keren G., and M.C. Willemsen (2009), Decision anomalies, experimenter assumptions, and participants comprehension: Revaluating the uncertainty effect, Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 22(3), [17] Kirchsteiger, G. (1994), The role of envy in ultimatum games, Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 25, [18] Krawcyk, M. and F. Le Lec (2008), Social decisions under risk. Evidence from the probabilistic dictator game, mimeo, University of Amsterdam. [19] Loomes, G., and R. Sugden, (1982), Regret theory: An alternative theory of rational choice under uncertainty, The Economic Journal, XCII [20] Maccheroni, F., Marinacci, M. and A. Rustichini (2008) Social decision theory: choosing within and between groups, mimeo. [21] Machina, M. (1982), Expected utility analysis without the independenee axiom, Econometrica, 50, [22] Machina, M. (1987), Choice under uncertainty: problems solved and unsolved, Journal of Economic Perspectives, 1, [23] Machina, M. (1989), Dynamic consistency and non-expected utility models of choice under uncertainty, Journal of Economic Literature, XXVII,

12 [24] Neilson. W. (2006) Axiomatic reference-dependence in behavior toward others and toward risk, Economic Theory, 28, [25] Ok, E. and L. Kockesen (2000) Negatively Interdependent Preferences, Social Choice and Welfare, 17, [26] Ortmann, A., Prokosheva, S., Rydval, O., and R. Hertwig (2009), How certain is the uncertainty effect?, Experimental Economics, 12(4), [27] Quiggin, J. (1982), A theory of anticipated utility, Joumal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 3, [28] Rohde, K., A preference foundation for Fehr and Schmidt s model of inequity aversion, Social Choice and Welfare, forthcoming. [29] Sandbu, M. (2008) Axiomatic foundations for fairness-motivated preferences, Social Choice and Welfare, 31(4), [30] Spector, Y., Leshno, M., and M. Ben Horin (1996), Stochastic dominance in an ordinal world, European Journal of Operational Research, 93/3, [31] Starmer, C. (2000), Developments in non-expected utility theory: the hunt for a descriptive theory of choice under risk, Journal of Economic Literature, XXXVIII, [32] Trautmann, S. (2009), Fehr-Schmidt process fairness and dynamic consistency, Journal of Economic Psychology 30, [33] Weber, M. and C. Camerer (1987), Recent developments in modelling preferences under risk, OR Spektrum, 9,

13 Appendix - Instructions for the experiment Welcome to this experiment. You can earn money in this experiment. At the end of the experiment you will be paid in cash according to your decisions and the decisions of the other participants. Each participant receives a payment of 5 Euro. Your additional payments are explained in these instructions. During the whole experiment you are not allowed to speak to other participants, to use cell phones, or to start any other program on the computer. If you have questions, please raise your hand. An instructor of the experiment will then come to your seat to answer your questions. During the experiment we do not speak of Euros but of the ficticious currency Taler. At the end of the experiment your actual amount of Taler will be converted into Euro according to the following exchange rate: 1 Taler = 0,50 Euro. The payment at the end of the experiment is anonymous. This means, no participant is informed about the payment of the other participants. In this experiment half of the participants are in role A the other half in role B. The roles have been assigned randomly. Course of the experiment: In the beginning of the experiment, each participant in role A (participant A) is randomly matched with another participant B. No participant learns during or after the experiment which other participant was matched with him. Participant A decides, which payment he himself and his matched participant B receive in this experiment. There are the following options: Participant A receives 15 Taler and participant B receives 0 Taler. Participant A receives 10 Taler and participant B receives 10 Taler. The computer chooses randomly one of the two aforementioned options. Both options are equally likely. Participant B does not make a decision which affects his own or participant A s payment. He answers several hypothetical questions. His answers are irrelavant for the payment and are not told other participants. Participant A also answers several hypothetical questions after his decision. His answers are irrelavant for the payment and are not told other participants. End: Finally, each participant B is informed which of the three aforementioned options participant A has chosen. In addition, all participants are informed about their payment in the experiment. This ends the experiment. 11

14 Appendix - Instructions for the mug treatment The introductory part of the instructions is exactly as in the social good treatment besides two changes: The show up fee is not mentioned and instead of half of the participants are in role A the other half in role B, we say some of the participants are in role A and some in role B. Below we give the remaining part of the instructions. Those parts that are related to the voting experiment, which is not in our interest here, are in small italic fonts. Course of the experiment: In the beginning of the experiment, groups consisting of six participants are formed. Each group consists of five randomly chosen participants A and one participant B. No participant learns during or after the experiment which other participant was matched with him. Each participant A has an endowment of 20 Taler; each participant B has an endowment of 0 Taler. In each group, the participants A vote on the following two alternatives. The alternative that gets the majority of votes in a group, determines the payoffs of all participants in this group. Alternative 1: Each participant A gives up 6 Taler. For each participant A the payoff reduces to 14 Taler, but the payoff of participant B increases to 14 Taler. Alternative 2: Each participant A gives up 0 Taler. For each participant A the payoff remains 20 Taler, and the payoff of participant B remains 0 Taler. Each participant A has one vote. The alternative which receives most of the votes is implemented for the group. Participant B makes a hypothetical decision which is not payoff relevant. All participants answers several hypothetical questions[...]. In addition, each participant receives a fixed payment. He can choose between the following three options: He can choose to receive 15 Taler or to receive 10 Taler and a mug (including tea), or that the computer randomly chooses one of the two aforementioned options. Both options are equally likely. End: Finally, each participant is informed which alternative is implemented for his group and his payment in the experiment. This ends the experiment. Appendix - The coffee mug in the mug treatment 12

On the difference between social and private goods

On the difference between social and private goods On the difference between social and private goods Philipp Kircher, Sandra Ludwig and Alvaro Sandroni August 4, 2011 Abstract Standard economic models have long been applied to choices over private consumption

More information

Paradoxes and Violations of Normative Decision Theory. Jay Simon Defense Resources Management Institute, Naval Postgraduate School

Paradoxes and Violations of Normative Decision Theory. Jay Simon Defense Resources Management Institute, Naval Postgraduate School Paradoxes and Violations of Normative Decision Theory Jay Simon Defense Resources Management Institute, Naval Postgraduate School Yitong Wang University of California, Irvine L. Robin Keller University

More information

Fairness and Reciprocity in the Hawk-Dove game

Fairness and Reciprocity in the Hawk-Dove game Fairness and Reciprocity in the Hawk-Dove game Tibor Neugebauer*, Anders Poulsen**, and Arthur Schram*** Abstract We study fairness and reciprocity in a Hawk-Dove game. This allows us to test various models

More information

Effects of Sequential Context on Judgments and Decisions in the Prisoner s Dilemma Game

Effects of Sequential Context on Judgments and Decisions in the Prisoner s Dilemma Game Effects of Sequential Context on Judgments and Decisions in the Prisoner s Dilemma Game Ivaylo Vlaev (ivaylo.vlaev@psy.ox.ac.uk) Department of Experimental Psychology, University of Oxford, Oxford, OX1

More information

Jakub Steiner The University of Edinburgh. Abstract

Jakub Steiner The University of Edinburgh. Abstract A trace of anger is enough: on the enforcement of social norms Jakub Steiner The University of Edinburgh Abstract It is well documented that the possibility of punishing free-riders increases contributions

More information

An Experimental Comparison of the Fairness Models by Bolton and Ockenfels and by Fehr and Schmidt

An Experimental Comparison of the Fairness Models by Bolton and Ockenfels and by Fehr and Schmidt An Experimental Comparison of the Fairness Models by Bolton and Ockenfels and by Fehr and Schmidt Dirk Engelmann y and Martin Strobel z Humboldt-Universität zu Berlin January 29, 2000 Abstract In this

More information

Veronika Grimm, Friederike Mengel. Let me sleep on it: Delay reduces rejection rates in Ultimatum Games RM/10/017

Veronika Grimm, Friederike Mengel. Let me sleep on it: Delay reduces rejection rates in Ultimatum Games RM/10/017 Veronika Grimm, Friederike Mengel Let me sleep on it: Delay reduces rejection rates in Ultimatum Games RM/10/017 Let me sleep on it: Delay reduces rejection rates in Ultimatum Games Veronika Grimm Friederike

More information

The Game Prisoners Really Play: Preference Elicitation and the Impact of Communication

The Game Prisoners Really Play: Preference Elicitation and the Impact of Communication The Game Prisoners Really Play: Preference Elicitation and the Impact of Communication Michael Kosfeld University of Zurich Ernst Fehr University of Zurich October 10, 2003 Unfinished version: Please do

More information

HOT VS. COLD: SEQUENTIAL RESPONSES AND PREFERENCE STABILITY IN EXPERIMENTAL GAMES * August 1998

HOT VS. COLD: SEQUENTIAL RESPONSES AND PREFERENCE STABILITY IN EXPERIMENTAL GAMES * August 1998 HOT VS. COLD: SEQUENTIAL RESPONSES AND PREFERENCE STABILITY IN EXPERIMENTAL GAMES * August 1998 Jordi Brandts Instituto de Análisis Económico (CSIC) Barcelona and University of California Berkeley (jbrandts@econ.berkeley.edu)

More information

WILL HOMO ECONOMICUS SURVIVE?

WILL HOMO ECONOMICUS SURVIVE? WILL HOMO ECONOMICUS SURVIVE? PHILIPP DOERRENBERG Erasmus Student In this essay, Philipp Doerrenberg highlights recent experimental work that has proven the shaky foundations of the concept of the rational,

More information

Accepting Zero in the Ultimatum Game Does Not Reflect Selfish. preferences

Accepting Zero in the Ultimatum Game Does Not Reflect Selfish. preferences Accepting Zero in the Ultimatum Game Does Not Reflect Selfish Preferences Gianandrea Staffiero a, Filippos Exadaktylos b* & Antonio M. Espín c a. Universitat Pompeu Fabra, Spain. Department of Economics

More information

Alternative Payoff Mechanisms for Choice under Risk. by James C. Cox, Vjollca Sadiraj Ulrich Schmidt

Alternative Payoff Mechanisms for Choice under Risk. by James C. Cox, Vjollca Sadiraj Ulrich Schmidt Alternative Payoff Mechanisms for Choice under Risk by James C. Cox, Vjollca Sadiraj Ulrich Schmidt No. 1932 June 2014 Kiel Institute for the World Economy, Kiellinie 66, 24105 Kiel, Germany Kiel Working

More information

It is Whether You Win or Lose: The Importance of the Overall Probabilities of Winning or Losing in Risky Choice

It is Whether You Win or Lose: The Importance of the Overall Probabilities of Winning or Losing in Risky Choice The Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 30:1; 5 19, 2005 c 2005 Springer Science + Business Media, Inc. Manufactured in The Netherlands. It is Whether You Win or Lose: The Importance of the Overall Probabilities

More information

Shifting the blame to a powerless intermediary

Shifting the blame to a powerless intermediary Exp Econ (2013) 16:306 312 DOI 10.1007/s10683-012-9335-7 MANUSCRIPT Shifting the blame to a powerless intermediary Regine Oexl Zachary J. Grossman Received: 10 September 2011 / Accepted: 17 July 2012 /

More information

behavioural economics and game theory

behavioural economics and game theory behavioural economics and game theory In traditional economic analysis, as well as in much of behavioural economics, the individual s motivations are summarized by a utility function (or a preference relation)

More information

Author's personal copy

Author's personal copy Erkenn DOI 10.1007/s10670-013-9543-3 ORIGINAL ARTICLE Brad Armendt Received: 2 October 2013 / Accepted: 2 October 2013 Ó Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2013 Abstract It is widely held that the

More information

Today s lecture. A thought experiment. Topic 3: Social preferences and fairness. Overview readings: Fehr and Fischbacher (2002) Sobel (2005)

Today s lecture. A thought experiment. Topic 3: Social preferences and fairness. Overview readings: Fehr and Fischbacher (2002) Sobel (2005) Topic 3: Social preferences and fairness Are we perfectly selfish? If not, does it affect economic analysis? How to take it into account? Overview readings: Fehr and Fischbacher (2002) Sobel (2005) Today

More information

Assessment and Estimation of Risk Preferences (Outline and Pre-summary)

Assessment and Estimation of Risk Preferences (Outline and Pre-summary) Assessment and Estimation of Risk Preferences (Outline and Pre-summary) Charles A. Holt and Susan K. Laury 1 In press (2013) for the Handbook of the Economics of Risk and Uncertainty, Chapter 4, M. Machina

More information

SUBJECTIVE PROBABILITY WEIGHTING AND THE DISCOVERED PREFERENCE HYPOTHESIS

SUBJECTIVE PROBABILITY WEIGHTING AND THE DISCOVERED PREFERENCE HYPOTHESIS Theory and Decision (2009) 67:1 22 Springer 2007 DOI 10.1007/s11238-007-9080-0 GIJS VAN DE KUILEN SUBJECTIVE PROBABILITY WEIGHTING AND THE DISCOVERED PREFERENCE HYPOTHESIS ABSTRACT. Numerous studies have

More information

How financial incentives and cognitive abilities. affect task performance in laboratory settings: an illustration

How financial incentives and cognitive abilities. affect task performance in laboratory settings: an illustration How financial incentives and cognitive abilities affect task performance in laboratory settings: an illustration Ondrej Rydval, Andreas Ortmann CERGE-EI, Prague, Czech Republic April 2004 Abstract Drawing

More information

SUPPLEMENTARY INFORMATION

SUPPLEMENTARY INFORMATION Supplementary Statistics and Results This file contains supplementary statistical information and a discussion of the interpretation of the belief effect on the basis of additional data. We also present

More information

Choice set options affect the valuation of risky prospects

Choice set options affect the valuation of risky prospects Choice set options affect the valuation of risky prospects Stian Reimers (stian.reimers@warwick.ac.uk) Neil Stewart (neil.stewart@warwick.ac.uk) Nick Chater (nick.chater@warwick.ac.uk) Department of Psychology,

More information

7 Action. 7.1 Choice. Todd Davies, Decision Behavior: Theory and Evidence (Spring 2010) Version: June 4, 2010, 2:40 pm

7 Action. 7.1 Choice. Todd Davies, Decision Behavior: Theory and Evidence (Spring 2010) Version: June 4, 2010, 2:40 pm 7 Action Todd Davies, Decision Behavior: Theory and Evidence (Spring 2010) We can now apply beliefs, preferences, and confidence to choices between different possible actions or options. 7.1 Choice DEFINITION

More information

Some Thoughts on the Principle of Revealed Preference 1

Some Thoughts on the Principle of Revealed Preference 1 Some Thoughts on the Principle of Revealed Preference 1 Ariel Rubinstein School of Economics, Tel Aviv University and Department of Economics, New York University and Yuval Salant Graduate School of Business,

More information

The effects of losses and event splitting on the Allais paradox

The effects of losses and event splitting on the Allais paradox Judgment and Decision Making, Vol. 2, No. 2, April 2007, pp. 115 125 The effects of losses and event splitting on the Allais paradox Bethany J. Weber Brain Imaging and Analysis Center Duke University Abstract

More information

Social Preferences of Young Adults in Japan: The Roles of Age and Gender

Social Preferences of Young Adults in Japan: The Roles of Age and Gender Social Preferences of Young Adults in Japan: The Roles of Age and Gender Akihiro Kawase Faculty of Economics, Toyo University, Japan November 26, 2014 E-mail address: kawase@toyo.jp Postal address: Faculty

More information

Hedging and Ambiguity

Hedging and Ambiguity Hedging and Ambiguity Jörg Oechssler University of Heidelberg Alex Roomets Franklin and Marshall College September 21, 2016 Hannes Rau University of Heidelberg Abstract We run an experiment that gives

More information

CeDEx Discussion Paper Series ISSN

CeDEx Discussion Paper Series ISSN Discussion Paper No. 2009 10 Klaus Abbink and Benedikt Herrmann June 2009 The Moral Costs of Nastiness CeDEx Discussion Paper Series ISSN 1749 3293 The Centre for Decision Research and Experimental Economics

More information

Leadership with Individual Rewards and Punishments

Leadership with Individual Rewards and Punishments MPRA Munich Personal RePEc Archive Leadership with Individual Rewards and Punishments Özgür Gürerk and Thomas Lauer and Martin Scheuermann RWTH Aachen University, University of Cologne 17. July 2015 Online

More information

The Foundations of Behavioral. Economic Analysis SANJIT DHAMI

The Foundations of Behavioral. Economic Analysis SANJIT DHAMI The Foundations of Behavioral Economic Analysis SANJIT DHAMI OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS CONTENTS List offigures ListofTables %xi xxxi Introduction 1 1 The antecedents of behavioral economics 3 2 On methodology

More information

On the How and Why of Decision Theory. Joint confusions with Bart Lipman

On the How and Why of Decision Theory. Joint confusions with Bart Lipman On the How and Why of Decision Theory Joint confusions with Bart Lipman Caveats Owes much to many people with whom we have benefitted from discussing decision theory over the years. These include Larry

More information

Size of Ellsberg Urn. Emel Filiz-Ozbay, Huseyin Gulen, Yusufcan Masatlioglu, Erkut Ozbay. University of Maryland

Size of Ellsberg Urn. Emel Filiz-Ozbay, Huseyin Gulen, Yusufcan Masatlioglu, Erkut Ozbay. University of Maryland Size of Ellsberg Urn Emel Filiz-Ozbay, Huseyin Gulen, Yusufcan Masatlioglu, Erkut Ozbay University of Maryland behavior fundamentally changes when the uncertainty is explicitly specified and vaguely described

More information

Mini-Course in Behavioral Economics Leeat Yariv. Behavioral Economics - Course Outline

Mini-Course in Behavioral Economics Leeat Yariv. Behavioral Economics - Course Outline Mini-Course in Behavioral Economics Leeat Yariv The goal of this mini-course is to give an overview of the state of the art of behavioral economics. I hope to trigger some research in the field and will

More information

The effects of payout and probability magnitude on the Allais paradox

The effects of payout and probability magnitude on the Allais paradox Memory & Cognition 2008, 36 (5), 1013-1023 doi: 10.3758/MC.36.5.1013 The effects of payout and probability magnitude on the Allais paradox BETHANY Y J. WEBER Rutgers University, New Brunswick, New Jersey

More information

Behavioral Game Theory

Behavioral Game Theory Outline (September 3, 2007) Outline (September 3, 2007) Introduction Outline (September 3, 2007) Introduction Examples of laboratory experiments Outline (September 3, 2007) Introduction Examples of laboratory

More information

Testing and Modeling Fairness Motives *

Testing and Modeling Fairness Motives * RMM Vol. 0, Perspectives in Moral Science, ed. by M. Baurmann & B. Lahno, 2009, 199 206 http://www.rmm-journal.de/ Gary E. Bolton and Axel Ockenfels Testing and Modeling Fairness Motives * Abstract: The

More information

Gender specific attitudes towards risk and ambiguity an experimental investigation

Gender specific attitudes towards risk and ambiguity an experimental investigation Research Collection Working Paper Gender specific attitudes towards risk and ambiguity an experimental investigation Author(s): Schubert, Renate; Gysler, Matthias; Brown, Martin; Brachinger, Hans Wolfgang

More information

EXPERIMENTAL ECONOMICS INTRODUCTION. Ernesto Reuben

EXPERIMENTAL ECONOMICS INTRODUCTION. Ernesto Reuben EXPERIMENTAL ECONOMICS INTRODUCTION Ernesto Reuben WHAT IS EXPERIMENTAL ECONOMICS? 2 WHAT IS AN ECONOMICS EXPERIMENT? A method of collecting data in controlled environments with the purpose of furthering

More information

Economic Computation and Economic Cybernetics Studies and Research, Issue 4/2015

Economic Computation and Economic Cybernetics Studies and Research, Issue 4/2015 Economic Computation and Economic Cybernetics Studies and Research, Issue 4/205 Assistant Professor Sigifredo LAENGLE, PhD Department of Management Control, Universidad de Chile E-mail: slaengle@fen.uchile.cl

More information

Identifying Social Norms Using Coordination Games: Spectators vs. Stakeholders. CeDEx Discussion Paper Series ISSN

Identifying Social Norms Using Coordination Games: Spectators vs. Stakeholders. CeDEx Discussion Paper Series ISSN Discussion Paper No. 2014-16 Hande Erkut, Daniele Nosenzo and Martin Sefton November 2014 Identifying Social Norms Using Coordination Games: Spectators vs. Stakeholders CeDEx Discussion Paper Series ISSN

More information

Rational Choice Theory I: The Foundations of the Theory

Rational Choice Theory I: The Foundations of the Theory Rational Choice Theory I: The Foundations of the Theory Benjamin Ferguson Administrative Keep in mind that your second papers are due this coming Friday at midnight. They should be emailed to me, roughly

More information

Sequential Decision and Strategy Vector Methods in Ultimatum Bargaining: Evidence on the Strength of Other- Regarding Behavior

Sequential Decision and Strategy Vector Methods in Ultimatum Bargaining: Evidence on the Strength of Other- Regarding Behavior Department of Economics Discussion Paper 2004-04 Sequential Decision and Strategy Vector Methods in Ultimatum Bargaining: Evidence on the Strength of Other- Regarding Behavior Robert J. Oxoby University

More information

Inequity and Risk Aversion. in Sequential Public Good Games

Inequity and Risk Aversion. in Sequential Public Good Games Inequity and Risk Aversion in Sequential Public Good Games Sabrina Teyssier INRA-ALISS, 65 boulevard de Brandebourg, 94205 Ivry-sur-Seine Cedex, France. Email: Sabrina.Teyssier@ivry.inra.fr. September

More information

Comparative Ignorance and the Ellsberg Paradox

Comparative Ignorance and the Ellsberg Paradox The Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 22:2; 129 139, 2001 2001 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Manufactured in The Netherlands. Comparative Ignorance and the Ellsberg Paradox CLARE CHUA CHOW National University

More information

Experimental Testing of Intrinsic Preferences for NonInstrumental Information

Experimental Testing of Intrinsic Preferences for NonInstrumental Information Experimental Testing of Intrinsic Preferences for NonInstrumental Information By Kfir Eliaz and Andrew Schotter* The classical model of decision making under uncertainty assumes that decision makers care

More information

PREFERENCE REVERSAL: AN EXPERIMENTAL INVESTIGATION OF ECONOMIC AND PSYCHOLOGICAL HYPOTHESES*

PREFERENCE REVERSAL: AN EXPERIMENTAL INVESTIGATION OF ECONOMIC AND PSYCHOLOGICAL HYPOTHESES* PREFERENCE REVERSAL: AN EXPERIMENTAL INVESTIGATION OF ECONOMIC AND PSYCHOLOGICAL HYPOTHESES* by Robin Cubitt** Alistair Munro** Chris Starmer*** * Research for this paper was funded by the Economic and

More information

Insensitivity to Unethical Behavior in Dictator Game When Indirectly Intermediated-Implications of Indirect Blindness for Safety Management

Insensitivity to Unethical Behavior in Dictator Game When Indirectly Intermediated-Implications of Indirect Blindness for Safety Management Journal of Behavioral and Brain Science, 2016, 6, 199-208 Published Online May 2016 in SciRes. http://www.scirp.org/journal/jbbs http://dx.doi.org/10.4236/jbbs.2016.65020 Insensitivity to Unethical Behavior

More information

Gender Differences in Giving in the Dictator Game: The Role of Reluctant Altruism

Gender Differences in Giving in the Dictator Game: The Role of Reluctant Altruism Gender Differences in Giving in the Dictator Game: The Role of Reluctant Altruism David Klinowski Santiago Centre for Experimental Social Sciences Nuffield College, University of Oxford; and Universidad

More information

Topic 3: Social preferences and fairness

Topic 3: Social preferences and fairness Topic 3: Social preferences and fairness Are we perfectly selfish and self-centered? If not, does it affect economic analysis? How to take it into account? Focus: Descriptive analysis Examples Will monitoring

More information

Supporting Information

Supporting Information Supporting Information Burton-Chellew and West 10.1073/pnas.1210960110 SI Results Fig. S4 A and B shows the percentage of free riders and cooperators over time for each treatment. Although Fig. S4A shows

More information

A Note On the Design of Experiments Involving Public Goods

A Note On the Design of Experiments Involving Public Goods University of Colorado From the SelectedWorks of PHILIP E GRAVES 2009 A Note On the Design of Experiments Involving Public Goods PHILIP E GRAVES, University of Colorado at Boulder Available at: https://works.bepress.com/philip_graves/40/

More information

Emanuela Carbonara. 31 January University of Bologna - Department of Economics

Emanuela Carbonara. 31 January University of Bologna - Department of Economics Game Theory, Behavior and The Law - I A brief introduction to game theory. Rules of the game and equilibrium concepts. Behavioral Games: Ultimatum and Dictator Games. Entitlement and Framing effects. Emanuela

More information

On the diversity principle and local falsifiability

On the diversity principle and local falsifiability On the diversity principle and local falsifiability Uriel Feige October 22, 2012 1 Introduction This manuscript concerns the methodology of evaluating one particular aspect of TCS (theoretical computer

More information

How to identify trust and reciprocity

How to identify trust and reciprocity Games and Economic Behavior 46 (2004) 260 281 www.elsevier.com/locate/geb How to identify trust and reciprocity JamesC.Cox Department of Economics, 401 McClelland Hall, University of Arizona, Tucson, AZ

More information

Correlation Neglect in Belief Formation

Correlation Neglect in Belief Formation Correlation Neglect in Belief Formation Benjamin Enke Florian Zimmermann Bonn Graduate School of Economics University of Zurich NYU Bounded Rationality in Choice Conference May 31, 2015 Benjamin Enke (Bonn)

More information

A shocking experiment: New evidence on probability weighting and common ratio violations

A shocking experiment: New evidence on probability weighting and common ratio violations Judgment and Decision Making, Vol. 2, No. 4, August 2007, pp. 234 242 A shocking experiment: New evidence on probability weighting and common ratio violations Gregory S. Berns 1, C. Monica Capra 2, Sara

More information

A cash effect in ultimatum game experiments

A cash effect in ultimatum game experiments A cash effect in ultimatum game experiments JUNYI SHEN * Research Institute for Economics & Business Administration, Kobe University, Japan and HIROMASA TAKAHASHI Faculty of International Studies, Hiroshima

More information

Positive reciprocity and intentions in trust games

Positive reciprocity and intentions in trust games Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization Vol. 52 (2003) 267 275 Positive reciprocity and intentions in trust games Kevin A. McCabe a, Mary L. Rigdon b,, Vernon L. Smith a a Interdisciplinary Center

More information

Effect of Choice Set on Valuation of Risky Prospects

Effect of Choice Set on Valuation of Risky Prospects Effect of Choice Set on Valuation of Risky Prospects Neil Stewart (neil.stewart@warwick.ac.uk) Nick Chater (nick.chater@warwick.ac.uk) Henry P. Stott (hstott@owc.com) Department of Psychology, University

More information

Adaptive Theory: Limited Neural Resource, Attention and Risk Taking

Adaptive Theory: Limited Neural Resource, Attention and Risk Taking Adaptive Theory: Limited Neural Resource, Attention and Risk Taking By CHENG Qiqi Draft: December 31, 2018 This paper presents a new descriptive theory for decision making under risk, called adaptive theory,

More information

Team Reasoning and a Rank-Based Function of Team s Interests

Team Reasoning and a Rank-Based Function of Team s Interests Team Reasoning and a Rank-Based Function of Team s Interests Jurgis Karpus Mantas Radzvilas April 2015 Abstract Orthodox game theory is sometimes criticized for its failure to single out intuitively compelling

More information

Tests of Difference Aversion to Explain Anomalies in Simple Bargaining Games 1. John H. Kagel Department of Economics Ohio State University.

Tests of Difference Aversion to Explain Anomalies in Simple Bargaining Games 1. John H. Kagel Department of Economics Ohio State University. Tests of Difference Aversion to Explain Anomalies in Simple Bargaining Games 1 John H. Kagel Department of Economics Ohio State University and Katherine Wolfe Department of Economics University of Pittsburgh

More information

Koji Kotani International University of Japan. Abstract

Koji Kotani International University of Japan. Abstract Further investigations of framing effects on cooperative choices in a provision point mechanism Koji Kotani International University of Japan Shunsuke Managi Yokohama National University Kenta Tanaka Yokohama

More information

An Introduction to Behavioral Economics

An Introduction to Behavioral Economics An Introduction to Behavioral Economics Nick Wilkinson > Richmond, The American International University in London :w t '

More information

Responsibility Effects in Decision Making under Risk

Responsibility Effects in Decision Making under Risk Julius Pahlke Sebastian Strasser Ferdinand M. Vieider Responsibility Effects in Decision Making under Risk Discussion Paper SP II 2012 402 October 2012 Social Science Research Center Berlin (WZB) Research

More information

Department of Economics Working Paper Series

Department of Economics Working Paper Series Department of Economics Working Paper Series The Common Ratio Effect in Choice, Pricing, and Happiness Tasks by Mark Schneider Chapman University Mikhael Shor University of Connecticut Working Paper 2016-29

More information

Methods of eliciting time preferences for health A pilot study

Methods of eliciting time preferences for health A pilot study Methods of eliciting time preferences for health A pilot study Dorte Gyrd-Hansen Health Economics Papers 2000:1 Methods of eliciting time preferences for health A pilot study Dorte Gyrd-Hansen Contents

More information

Appendix: Instructions for Treatment Index B (Human Opponents, With Recommendations)

Appendix: Instructions for Treatment Index B (Human Opponents, With Recommendations) Appendix: Instructions for Treatment Index B (Human Opponents, With Recommendations) This is an experiment in the economics of strategic decision making. Various agencies have provided funds for this research.

More information

Contributions and Beliefs in Liner Public Goods Experiment: Difference between Partners and Strangers Design

Contributions and Beliefs in Liner Public Goods Experiment: Difference between Partners and Strangers Design Working Paper Contributions and Beliefs in Liner Public Goods Experiment: Difference between Partners and Strangers Design Tsuyoshi Nihonsugi 1, 2 1 Research Fellow of the Japan Society for the Promotion

More information

Homo economicus is dead! How do we know how the mind works? How the mind works

Homo economicus is dead! How do we know how the mind works? How the mind works Some facts about social preferences, or why we're sometimes nice and sometimes not Karthik Panchanathan buddha@ucla.edu Homo economicus is dead! It was a mistake to believe that individuals and institutions

More information

JENA ECONOMIC RESEARCH PAPERS

JENA ECONOMIC RESEARCH PAPERS JENA ECONOMIC RESEARCH PAPERS # 2014 001 Social comparison and risk taking behavior by Astrid Gamba Elena Manzoni www.jenecon.de ISSN 1864-7057 The JENA ECONOMIC RESEARCH PAPERS is a joint publication

More information

A Theory of Reference Point Formation

A Theory of Reference Point Formation A Theory of Reference Point Formation Ozgur Kibris Yusufcan Masatlioglu Elchin Suleymanov Sabanci Maryland Michigan Motivation Model Examples Behavioral Foundation Identification PC-SER References 0/47

More information

Eye-image in Experiments: Social Cue or Experimenter Demand Effect? by Subhasish M. Chowdhury* Joo Young Jeon** Bibhas Saha***

Eye-image in Experiments: Social Cue or Experimenter Demand Effect? by Subhasish M. Chowdhury* Joo Young Jeon** Bibhas Saha*** CBESS Discussion Paper 14-13 Eye-image in Experiments: Social Cue or Experimenter Demand Effect? by Subhasish M. Chowdhury* Joo Young Jeon** Bibhas Saha*** *CBESS and School of Economics, University of

More information

Introduction to Behavioral Economics Like the subject matter of behavioral economics, this course is divided into two parts:

Introduction to Behavioral Economics Like the subject matter of behavioral economics, this course is divided into two parts: Economics 142: Behavioral Economics Spring 2008 Vincent Crawford (with very large debts to Colin Camerer of Caltech, David Laibson of Harvard, and especially Botond Koszegi and Matthew Rabin of UC Berkeley)

More information

ULTIMATUM GAME. An Empirical Evidence. Presented By: SHAHID RAZZAQUE

ULTIMATUM GAME. An Empirical Evidence. Presented By: SHAHID RAZZAQUE 1 ULTIMATUM GAME An Empirical Evidence Presented By: SHAHID RAZZAQUE 2 Difference Between Self-Interest, Preference & Social Preference Preference refers to the choices people make & particularly to tradeoffs

More information

JENA ECONOMIC RESEARCH PAPERS

JENA ECONOMIC RESEARCH PAPERS JENA ECONOMIC RESEARCH PAPERS # 2009 074 On the Independence of Observations between Experiments by Astrid Matthey Tobias Regner www.jenecon.de ISSN 1864-7057 The JENA ECONOMIC RESEARCH PAPERS is a joint

More information

Behavioral Models of Decision Making under Risk. Michael H. Birnbaum. California State University, Fullerton. Mailing Address:

Behavioral Models of Decision Making under Risk. Michael H. Birnbaum. California State University, Fullerton. Mailing Address: Behavioral Models of Decision Making under Risk Michael H. Birnbaum California State University, Fullerton Mailing Address: Dept. of Psychology California State University H- 830M Box 6846 Fullerton, CA

More information

Subjects are motivated not only by their own payoffs but also by those of others and the relationship between the payoffs of the players of the game

Subjects are motivated not only by their own payoffs but also by those of others and the relationship between the payoffs of the players of the game Subjects are motivated not only by their own payoffs but also by those of others and the relationship between the payoffs of the players of the game ultimatum games resistance to unfairness dictator games

More information

Liberal Resourcism: Problems and Possibilities. Bertil Tungodden, Norwegian School of Economics. Peter Vallentyne, University of Missouri

Liberal Resourcism: Problems and Possibilities. Bertil Tungodden, Norwegian School of Economics. Peter Vallentyne, University of Missouri Liberal Resourcism: Problems and Possibilities Bertil Tungodden, Norwegian School of Economics Peter Vallentyne, University of Missouri 1. Resources... 3 2. Wellbeing... 4 3. Advantage... 8 4. Liberal

More information

Self-Serving Assessments of Fairness and Pretrial Bargaining

Self-Serving Assessments of Fairness and Pretrial Bargaining Self-Serving Assessments of Fairness and Pretrial Bargaining George Loewenstein Samuel Issacharoff Colin Camerer and Linda Babcock Journal of Legal Studies 1993 報告人 : 高培儒 20091028 1 1. Introduction Why

More information

AREC 815: Experimental and Behavioral Economics. Experiments Testing Prospect Theory. Professor: Pamela Jakiela

AREC 815: Experimental and Behavioral Economics. Experiments Testing Prospect Theory. Professor: Pamela Jakiela AREC 815: Experimental and Behavioral Economics Experiments Testing Prospect Theory Professor: Pamela Jakiela Department of Agricultural and Resource Economics University of Maryland, College Park Risk

More information

Individual Sense of Fairness: An Experimental Study

Individual Sense of Fairness: An Experimental Study Individual Sense of Fairness: An Experimental Study Edi Karni Johns Hopkins University Tim Salmon Florida State University February 2007 Barry Sopher Rutgers University Abstract Many prior studies have

More information

Which determines Dictating the Risk, risk preference or social image? Experimental evidence-

Which determines Dictating the Risk, risk preference or social image? Experimental evidence- Which determines Dictating the Risk, risk preference or social image? Experimental evidence- Tetsuya Kawamura a, Kazuhito Ogawa a,b and Yusuke Osaki a,c a Center for Experimental Economics, Kansai University

More information

Behavioral Economics - Syllabus

Behavioral Economics - Syllabus Behavioral Economics - Syllabus 1 st Term - Academic Year 2016/2017 Professor Luigi Mittone luigi.mittone@unitn.it Teaching Assistant Viola Saredi violaluisa.saredi@unitn.it Course Overview The course

More information

ELICITING RISK PREFERENCES USING CHOICE LISTS

ELICITING RISK PREFERENCES USING CHOICE LISTS ELICITING RISK PREFERENCES USING CHOICE LISTS DAVID J. FREEMAN, YORAM HALEVY AND TERRI KNEELAND Abstract. We study the effect of embedding pairwise choices between lotteries within a choice list on measured

More information

Social Norms and Reciprocity*

Social Norms and Reciprocity* Social Norms and Reciprocity* Andreas Diekmann Institut für Soziologie Universität Bern Thomas Voss Institut für Soziologie Universität Leipzig [ March 2003 ] Paper presented on the session Solidarity

More information

Recognizing Ambiguity

Recognizing Ambiguity Recognizing Ambiguity How Lack of Information Scares Us Mark Clements Columbia University I. Abstract In this paper, I will examine two different approaches to an experimental decision problem posed by

More information

Area Conferences 2012

Area Conferences 2012 A joint initiative of Ludwig-Maximilians University s Center for Economic Studies and the Ifo Institute CESifo Conference Centre, Munich Area Conferences 2012 CESifo Area Conference on Behavioural Economics

More information

Social Responsibility in Market Interaction

Social Responsibility in Market Interaction DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES IZA DP No. 9240 Social Responsibility in Market Interaction Bernd Irlenbusch David Saxler July 2015 Forschungsinstitut zur Zukunft der Arbeit Institute for the Study of Labor Social

More information

Entitlement in a Real Effort Ultimatum Game

Entitlement in a Real Effort Ultimatum Game Entitlement in a Real Effort Ultimatum Game Michael D. Carr and Phil Mellizo WORKING PAPER 2013-01 DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS UNIVERSITY OF MASSACHUSETTS BOSTON 1 Entitlement in a Real Effort Ultimatum Game

More information

Giving Feedback to Clients

Giving Feedback to Clients Giving Feedback to Clients Teck-Hua Ho and Catherine Yeung 1 August 23, 2013 1 Authors are listed in alphabetical order. We thank the editor, the associate editor, and the three anonymous reviewers for

More information

DIFFERENCES IN THE ECONOMIC DECISIONS OF MEN AND WOMEN: EXPERIMENTAL EVIDENCE*

DIFFERENCES IN THE ECONOMIC DECISIONS OF MEN AND WOMEN: EXPERIMENTAL EVIDENCE* DIFFERENCES IN THE ECONOMIC DECISIONS OF MEN AND WOMEN: EXPERIMENTAL EVIDENCE* Catherine C. Eckel Department of Economics Virginia Tech Blacksburg, VA 24061-0316 Philip J. Grossman Department of Economics

More information

Clicker quiz: Should the cocaine trade be legalized? (either answer will tell us if you are here or not) 1. yes 2. no

Clicker quiz: Should the cocaine trade be legalized? (either answer will tell us if you are here or not) 1. yes 2. no Clicker quiz: Should the cocaine trade be legalized? (either answer will tell us if you are here or not) 1. yes 2. no Economic Liberalism Summary: Assumptions: self-interest, rationality, individual freedom

More information

Social comparisons in ultimatum bargaining. Iris Bohnet and Richard Zeckhauser *

Social comparisons in ultimatum bargaining. Iris Bohnet and Richard Zeckhauser * Social comparisons in ultimatum bargaining Iris Bohnet and Richard Zeckhauser * This paper experimentally examines the effect of social comparisons in ultimatum bargaining. While previous experiments and

More information

Giving, taking, and gender in dictator games

Giving, taking, and gender in dictator games CBESS Discussion Paper 14-09 Giving, taking, and gender in dictator games by Subhasish M. Chowdhury*, Joo Young Jeon*, and Bibhas Saha** * School of Economics, University of East Anglia ** Economics in

More information

Prior Dispositions and Actual Behavior in Dictator and Ultimatum Games. Abstract

Prior Dispositions and Actual Behavior in Dictator and Ultimatum Games. Abstract Prior Dispositions and Actual Behavior in Dictator and Ultimatum Games Hermann Brandstätter, University of Linz Werner Güth, Humboldt-University, Berlin Judith Himmelbauer, University of Linz Willy Kriz,

More information

Multiple Switching Behavior in Multiple Price Lists

Multiple Switching Behavior in Multiple Price Lists Multiple Switching Behavior in Multiple Price Lists David M. Bruner This version: September 2007 Abstract A common mechanism to elicit risk preferences requires a respondent to make a series of dichotomous

More information

Unlike standard economics, BE is (most of the time) not based on rst principles, but on observed behavior of real people.

Unlike standard economics, BE is (most of the time) not based on rst principles, but on observed behavior of real people. Behavioral Economics Lecture 1. Introduction and the Methodology of Experimental Economics 1. Introduction Characteristica of Behavioral Economics (BE) Unlike standard economics, BE is (most of the time)

More information

Take it or leave it: experimental evidence on the effect of time-limited offers on consumer behaviour Robert Sugden* Mengjie Wang* Daniel John Zizzo**

Take it or leave it: experimental evidence on the effect of time-limited offers on consumer behaviour Robert Sugden* Mengjie Wang* Daniel John Zizzo** CBESS Discussion Paper 15-19 Take it or leave it: experimental evidence on the effect of time-limited offers on consumer behaviour by Robert Sugden* Mengjie Wang* Daniel John Zizzo** *School of Economics,

More information

By Olivia Smith and Steven van de Put Third Year, Second Prize

By Olivia Smith and Steven van de Put Third Year, Second Prize Are humans always the rational, self-interested agents that mainstream economics assumes them to be? Discuss, using ideas of reciprocity, altruism and fairness By Olivia Smith and Steven van de Put Third

More information