The problem of animal consciousness

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "The problem of animal consciousness"

Transcription

1 1 The problem of animal consciousness Peter Carruthers University of Maryland Romanell lecture delivered at the ninety-second Pacific Division meeting of the American Philosophical Association in San Diego, CA, on March 29, I. THE TARGET QUESTION The kind of consciousness that forms our topic is so-called phenomenal consciousness. This is the sort of consciousness that is like something to undergo, or that has a distinctive subjective feel. Phenomenal consciousness is a species of mental-state consciousness. It is mental states (seeing a sunset, hearing a dog bark, smelling cinnamon) that can be phenomenally conscious. People are phenomenally conscious derivatively, by virtue of undergoing phenomenally conscious states. It is phenomenal consciousness that is thought to give rise to the hard problem of consciousness. 1 For it seems one can conceive of a zombie a creature that is like oneself in all physical, functional, and representational respects except that it lacks this feeling (the distinctive feeling of the smell of cinnamon). Likewise, there seems to be an unbridgeable explanatory gap between all physical, functional, and representational facts and one s current conscious experience. Hence many have been tempted to conclude that phenomenal consciousness involves properties (often called qualia ) that cannot be reduced to any combination of physical, functional, or representational ones. It is important to emphasize that the concept of phenomenal consciousness is a first-person one. The various locutions employed ( like something to undergo, subjective feel, qualitative character, and so on) are all intended just to draw one s attention to one s own phenomenally conscious experiences. Acquaintance with the latter is a necessary condition for grasping the concept, and no definition or third-personal explanation could confer understanding of the concept. Hence philosophical zombies

2 2 don t just lack phenomenal consciousness itself; they must also lack the concept of phenomenal consciousness. 2 Phenomenal consciousness is at least conceptually distinct from access consciousness. 3 (Whether there is any real distinction between the properties picked out by these concepts is another matter, to which we return in later sections.) Both are forms of mental-state consciousness: it is mental states that can have phenomenal properties, or that can be accessible to enter into decision making, reasoning, and verbal report. Whereas the concept of phenomenal consciousness is a first-personal one, access consciousness, in contrast, is functionally defined, and the concept could be fully understood by a zombie. A mental state is said to be access conscious if it is accessible to a wide range of other systems for further processing, specifically those involved in issuing verbal reports, in decision making, in reasoning, and in the formation of long-term memories. Mental-state consciousness (whether access or phenomenal) should be distinguished from creature consciousness, which can be either transitive or intransitive. 4 Whenever a creature (whether human or animal) is aware of some object or event in its environment or body, it can be said to be (transitively) conscious of that object or event. Put differently, a creature is transitively-conscious of an object or event when it perceives that object or event. It is debatable whether or not transitive creature consciousness requires mental-state consciousness. For it is debatable whether the perceptual states that enable a creature to be aware of its environment must be conscious ones. At any rate, it is worth noting that there are many kinds of case where one would pre-theoretically ascribe creature consciousness to an agent since the agent is displaying flexible perceptual sensitivity to the environment but where the states in virtue of which it acts as it does are not conscious ones. This point will be elaborated on in Section II. Intransitive creature consciousness, on the other hand, is a matter of being awake rather than asleep, or conscious as opposed to comatose. When the creature in question is a human person, then intransitive creature consciousness would normally implicate some or other form of mental-state consciousness. Whenever one is awake one is normally undergoing some conscious mental state or other. But the reverse need not be true. It seems that dreams are conscious mental states, even though the dreaming subject is asleep, and hence creature unconscious.

3 3 Note that both forms of creature consciousness admit of degrees. One can be more or less aware of the properties of a stimulus, and one can be more or less awake. Likewise, the concept of access consciousness allows for degrees. A mental state could be available to more, or to fewer, of the systems for reasoning, reporting, remembering, and so on. Phenomenal consciousness, in contrast, is all-ornothing. It is hard even to conceive of a case of experience that is partly like something to undergo, partly not. Indeed, even if one is only partially awake, some of the states one is in are determinately phenomenally conscious it is like something to be barely awake. And even though one s awareness of an object can be more or less detailed, or more or less rich and vivid (contrast looking at something in full light versus looking at it when so dimly lit that one can barely make it out), it is fully unequivocally like something to be looking at a dimly lit object, even if one is aware of many fewer properties of it. Our question about nonhuman animals, then, isn t whether animals can be awake, half-awake, or asleep. (Of course they can.) Nor is it about whether animals can be perceptually sensitive to the properties of their environments. (The obvious answer is that they often are.) Our question is whether the mental states of animals are ever conscious; specifically, whether they are ever phenomenally conscious. And if they are, which ones, in which species of creature? And how would we know? II. THE NEED FOR A THEORY It is natural to think that we need a theory of consciousness, or at least a theory of the neural correlates of consciousness, if we are to address the question of phenomenal consciousness in animals. But Michael Tye has recently argued that this is a mistake. 5 For provided we think conscious states play a causal role in the production of behavior, we can apply Newton s Principle: similar effects have similar causes. So when we see an animal exhibiting behavior similar to that displayed by human beings and specifically, when we see an animal showing flexible perceptually-grounded sensitivity to properties of its environment or its own body then we can conclude that it enjoys conscious experience. (At least, this is so unless we know of some additional fact that might undermine or defeat Newton s Principle in any given case. Much of Tye s book is occupied with discussion of possible defeaters, including the question whether absence of a cerebral cortex is a defeater for conscious experience.) Unfortunately, this approach is unsound. For it neglects a wide range of environmentally-sensitive forms

4 4 of behavior in humans that are at least to some degree flexible, but are caused by unconscious perceptual states. Consider, for example, a baseball batter facing a fastball traveling at 96 miles per hour. The distance between the pitching plate and the batting plate is 60 feet, hence there are about 56 feet from the point at which the pitcher releases the ball to the point of contact for the batter. The fastball will travel that distance in 400 milliseconds. In that 400-millisecond interval the batter has to estimate the trajectory of the ball (will it pass through the strike-zone or not?), initiate a swing, and then plan and execute the motor instructions for a specific type of swing, aimed at the expected location of the ball. But our best estimate of the time that elapses between presentation of a stimulus (in this case, light hitting the retina from the ball as it exits the pitcher s hand) and conscious experience is somewhere around 350 milliseconds. 6 It is almost certain, therefore, that the swing is initiated before the batter s perception of the trajectory of the ball becomes conscious, and that the execution of the swing is likewise guided by unconscious perceptual states throughout. It seems that while the batter s swing is accompanied by conscious experience, it isn t caused by it. So Newton s Principle cannot apply. This means that when we observe an animal responding to its environment in this sort of swift online manner we cannot use Newton s Principle to infer that it enjoys conscious experience. These points are vindicated and explained by the discovery of two visual systems in humans. 7 As is now familiar to many people, visual processing proceeds in two distinct cortical streams. (Similar distinctions can be drawn with respect to other sensory systems. 8 ) The ventral stream runs forward from visual cortex through the lower portions of the temporal lobes, whereas the dorsal stream runs upward through the parietal lobes. Processing within the ventral stream results in object recognition, with the relative positions of objects represented in allocentric space. Processing in the dorsal stream, in contrast, is coded in limb-centered and body-centered spatial coordinates, and is specialized for online guidance of action. Moreover, the two streams utilize distinct cellular pathways that remain distinct from one another all the way back to the retina. The ventral steam is a continuation of the parvocellular pathway, whereas the dorsal stream is a continuation of the magnocellular pathway. Notably, given the points about speed made in the previous paragraph, transmission of signals through the magnocellular (dorsal) pathway is significantly faster than through the parvocellular one. Multiple lines of evidence suggest that, while the two visual streams interact with one another in their early stages, their outputs are distinct. For example, damage to the dorsal stream can result in optic ataxia, in which visually guided action becomes halting and inaccurate while conscious experience is

5 5 fully intact; whereas damage to the ventral stream can result in agnosia (an inability to consciously identify objects), while leaving visually-guided motor control intact. Indeed, while the outputs of the ventral stream can be conscious, the outputs of the dorsal stream are inaccessible to consciousness. 9 Consider, in particular, D.F., a patient with bilateral temporal-lobe damage who has been extensively studied. 10 D.F. suffers from complete visual-form agnosia. While she can still experience colors and textures (and hence might be able to guess at the identity of a banana from its distinctive yellow color and mottled texture), she can no longer experience the shapes or orientations of objects. For example, she cannot recognize a banana from a line drawing of one, she is at chance when judging the orientation of a pencil (whether upright or horizontal), and she is at chance when judging whether a block of wood is square or oblong. But her reaching-and-grasping behavior is indistinguishable from normal. She will orient her hand appropriately when grasping a horizontally-held or vertically-held pencil, using a normal finger grip (but without being able to report the pencil s orientation in advance). And she is just as accurate as neurotypical people when posting a letter through a letter box arranged at various angles (while remaining at chance when consciously judging those angles). It is also thought to be the dorsal visual stream that underlies the well-known phenomenon of blindsight, in which people with damage to primary visual cortex become blind (that is to say: incapable of conscious experience) in a portion of their visual field, while being well above chance in identifying simple letters and patterns of movement presented in their blind field. 11 For there are projections from the retina to parietal cortex via the superior colliculus (bypassing primary visual cortex), whereas there are no such subcortical projections direct to temporal cortex. Moreover, we know that the monkey Helen, who had the whole of primary visual cortex surgically removed, could nevertheless move around and pick up objects normally, while being unable to identify objects except by touch or taste. 12 It appears to be the dorsal stream, too, that underlies habitual sensorimotor action. There is good reason to think that habitual behavior can occur without being initiated or guided by conscious experience, and we know that there are projections from the dorsal visual stream to dorsolateral striatum, which is the locus of sensorimotor control in habitual responding. 13 Indeed, as control of behavior shifts during learning from goal-oriented to habitual responding, one can trace a corresponding shift in the networks involved from those centered on the ventral striatum to those involving the dorsolateral striatum. 14 This comports well with one s everyday experience. One can engage in routine

6 6 activities (like driving a car along a well-known route) without conscious awareness of the stimuli involved in the activity, and while one s conscious mind is wholly engaged with other matters. It seems likely that sleepwalking implicates a similar dorsal route. While there are a number of different kinds of motor-involving sleep disorder, sleepwalking is the sort that takes place during the two deepest forms of sleep, in the absence of any of the rapid eye-movements (REMs) that would normally indicate the presence of dreaming. (That said, sleepwalkers do sometimes report dream-like experiences after waking from a sleepwalking episode. 15 ) Indeed, sleepwalking (and in some documented instances, even sleep driving) takes place with prefrontal cortex and most other regions of cortex fully suppressed (as in non-rem sleep generally). Yet the eyes are open and there is local activation of sensory cortices, the amygdala, and motor regions of cingulate cortex. 16 Finally, in this catalog of environmentally-sensitive actions that can take place in the absence of conscious experience, one should include the behavioral components of emotional states such as fear and anger. Although such emotions generally give rise to distinctive forms of conscious experience (at least in humans), the behaviors in question are initiated directly and swiftly and in the absence of conscious experience by subcortical circuits that include especially the amygdala. 17 It is these circuits that are responsible for the fight-or-flight response, setting in train a variety of physiological changes (increased heart-rate and breathing-rate, and so on), activating emotion-expressive facial expressions (the fear-face, the anger-face, and so on), and initiating adaptive forms of behavior guided by the affordances of the environment (fleeing, freezing, fighting, and more). Such emotion-expressive actions will automatically run through to completion unless inhibited by executive commands. Emotionally arousing stimuli will attract one s attention, of course; hence one will soon undergo conscious experiences of the relevant events. No doubt such experiences play a role in sustaining and/or modulating one s on-going emotions. But they aren t necessary (indeed, they aren t present) at the outset. There are thus a wide variety of actions in the human case that display perceptual sensitivity to the environment, that may sometimes be accompanied by conscious experience, but are actually caused by perceptual states that are deeply unconscious. However, what about actions of the sort that are caused by conscious experience in humans? Would it be possible to apply Newton s Principle if we could find the same or similar behavior in animals? In the absence of a good theory of consciousness, however, it is

7 7 impossible to know which those actions actually are. For consider an act such as the deliberate choice of one alternative over another, which is reliably preceded by conscious experience in ourselves. How are we to know (in the absence of a good theory of consciousness) whether the underlying neural or functional factors that make the accompanying experience conscious are among those that cause the choice? Conscious experience and reflective decision making might be common effects of the same underlying cause. Or it could be that only a subset of the factors that render experience conscious are actually involved causing the choice (and it might be that only the latter subset is involved in reflective choosing in other animals). Indeed, it might be the case that consciousness is epiphenomenal, not in general, but in respect of the type of behavior in question. It is plain that Tye is mistaken. In order to apply Newton s Principle correctly, we need a theory of the difference between conscious and unconscious forms of perception. Armed with such a theory, we can then raise (and investigate) the question whether both forms of perception are manifested in animals. This is our topic going forward. We will focus on the set of theories that have the resources to account for the distinction between conscious and unconscious mental states (setting aside theories such as panpsychism, 18 as well as those that draw on subatomic quantum indeterminacies, 19 which seem incapable of doing so). There are four such theories that are taken seriously in the current literature. One is integrated-information theory, proposed initially by Giulio Tononi. 20 Another identifies phenomenally conscious experience with the contents of iconic memory, proposed by Ned Block. 21 A third is higher-order thought theory, defended (in different forms) by David Rosenthal and the present author. 22 Finally, there is global workspace theory, which has been proposed and elaborated by Bernard Baars, Michael Tye, Stanislas Dehaene, Jesse Prinz, and others. 23 We will consider and briefly evaluate these four kinds of account in turn, noting their implications for the question of animal consciousness as we go. III. INTEGRATED INFORMATION According to integrated-information theory, consciousness can be measured by the extent to which information is integrated in the brain via complex reverberating feedback loops. 24 My discussion of this view will be brief. One immediate problem with it is that integrated information is a matter of degree, whereas (as we noted above), phenomenal consciousness is either categorically present or categorically

8 8 absent. This suggests that the theory might better serve as an account of creature consciousness (whether transitive, intransitive, or both), which likewise admits of degrees. Moreover, since information integration is a graded notion, and is present at all different levels of cognition, the theory implies a limited form of panpsychism, as Tononi and Koch themselves note. 25 For even paradigmatically unconscious blindsight-like states will contain some degree of informational integration, as will the states of one s cerebellum and spinal cord. Indeed, even a single neuron will be to some degree phenomenally conscious, on this view, since it serves to integrate the information received via its dendrites. But these claims are wholly unmotivated. Why would anyone want to claim that activity in one s spinal cord is a little bit phenomenally conscious, except when dictated by a theory? For there are no first-person facts here that we know of that need to be explained. Integrated-information theory can capture the first-person distinction between conscious and unconscious mental states, however, at least up to a point. The first-personally available difference between conscious and unconscious perception will reduce to the distinction between states that are highly informationally integrated (because globally broadcast, involving reverberating information integration among a number of different regions of prefrontal, temporal, and parietal cortices, as well primary sensory cortical regions) and those that are much less so (because they have only local or specialized effects). But then it is the global broadcasting, not the informational integration as such, that explains why conscious states are available to be remembered and reported, as well as entering into planning, whereas unconscious states are not. So to the extent that the theory can account for mentalstate consciousness, it only does so by piggy-backing off the global workspace view. Yet at the same time the theory entails a kind of panpsychism that is theoretically unmotivated, and does no explanatory work. What integrated-information theory does do, is imply that phenomenal consciousness will be widespread across the animal kingdom. All creatures will be to some degree phenomenally conscious (as will many of their parts), including not only insects like ants and bees, but also bacteria. This may match some people s pre-theoretical intuitions. But notice that the claim is not just that all creatures have a few phenomenally conscious states, or are phenomenally conscious infrequently. Rather, it is that the states that exist in a bee when it detects the scent of nectar, for example, are to some small degree phenomenally conscious, and are like something for the bee to undergo to some small extent. Such

9 9 claims are hard to make sense of. For as we noted earlier, our concept of phenomenal consciousness is all-or-nothing. One wants to insist: granted the bee s discriminatory capacities may be crude, and its representation of the world highly fragmentary and indeterminate, but either the mental states of the bee when detecting nectar have feel and are like something, or they aren t. They surely can t be one percent like something. IV. ICONIC MEMORY Ned Block identifies phenomenal consciousness with the contents of iconic memory (as well as with the contents of the equivalent early sensory memory buffers in non-visual modalities). 26 These contents are said to be richer than those accessible for planning or reporting. Indeed, the main evidence offered in support of the iconic-memory view is that people claim to see more details in a briefly presented stimulus than they can thereafter report. 27 As a result, Block thinks that phenomenal consciousness should be identified with the contents of iconic memory, whereas access consciousness and reportability comprise the contents of working memory. Critics have replied that people s intuition that they see the stimulus in rich detail can be explained away, in part by appealing to background scene statistics that are known to be swiftly computed by the visual system. 28 What is consciously experienced, on this view, isn t the complete detailed display of letters in the stimulus. Rather, it comprises a statistical distillation of the scene, with a content somewhat along the lines of a bunch of letter-like shapes. In support of such a view, we know that the statistical properties of background scenes in change-blindness experiments require very little in the way of attentional resources to be consciously experienced, in contrast with focal objects. 29 Moreover, there is evidence that people can only report about four items even when the cue for reporting coincides with stimulus offset, obviating any need for memory. 30 People can be shown an array of colored squares for a full second, whereupon just one of the squares remains illuminated. But that square is now divided into two colored halves, one of which is the original color of the square and the other of which is drawn from elsewhere in the display. The task is just to indicate which is the original color. Participants still show the standard four-item limit (two in each hemisphere), which is also present in their neural EEG signatures that flatten off at that four-item limit. These findings seem plainly inconsistent with the iconic-memory view. If one s perception of a colored square were already

10 10 conscious, then one would think that one would immediately know which side of the square had changed when half of it is replaced by a differently-colored rectangle. In addition, there is recent evidence from a number of different retro-cuing paradigms that seems inconsistent with the iconic-memory account of consciousness. 31 According to the latter, conscious experience should be time-locked to the occurrence of the stimulus, emerging swiftly through a feedforward sweep of sensory processing, and be independent of attention. Indeed, attention is merely the gateway to access consciousness, on this view. Moreover, the reason why a cue that follows stimulus offset only enables one to access a subset of one s comparatively rich conscious experience is said to derive from strict limits on the scope of attention and working memory. But in the experiments in question there was just a single stimulus a faint set of oriented lines (a Gabor patch) set near the limits of visual detection occurring in one of two possible locations whose location could either be pre-cued or post-cued, either validly or invalidly. The finding was that valid post-cues increased conscious detection, as well as improving people s discrimination of the orientation of the lines. But why, on an iconic-memory account, would a post-cue improve conscious detection? It should already be conscious (contained in iconic memory), in which case post-cue attention should be irrelevant; or it was too faint to make it into iconic memory, in which case it won t be available to be targeted by attention. The data suggest quite strongly that, in contrast with the iconic-memory theory, conscious experience is attention-dependent. It seems there are no good reasons for thinking that the iconic-memory account of phenomenal consciousness is true, whereas there are good reasons for taking it to be false. But what would such a view imply about the distribution of consciousness across the animal kingdom? This question is by no means easy to answer, although Block himself takes for granted that all mammals, at any rate, would qualify. 32 This is because it is left unclear which facts about iconic memory are supposed to carry the explanatory burden. Taken in one way, the implications of the account for animal consciousness become essentially the same as those of the global-workspace theory (see Section VII), since iconic memory is partly individuated through its functional relationship with working memory, and hence with reasoning, decision making, and verbal report. (There are multiple reverberating memory stores in the human mind that don t qualify for consciousness, on Block s account. What is distinctive of iconic memory is that people report awareness of its contents, even if they can t describe them fully.) But taken in other ways, the implications of the iconic-memory account might be highly restrictive (if something about the neural

11 11 realization of iconic memory in humans and/or apes is what explains the properties of conscious experience) or quite liberal (if the neural realizations that do the explaining are widely shared). At this point the question of the distribution of phenomenal consciousness in the animal kingdom is wide open, on an iconic-memory account. V. HIGHER-ORDER THOUGHT THEORY We now consider the class of higher-order theories of consciousness. These come in two basic varieties. The first claims that it is the actual presence of a higher-order thought about a perceptual state that renders that state phenomenally conscious. 33 This view faces a number of severe difficulties. One is that it is hard to know what one should say when the content of perception and the content of the higherorder thought don t align with one another. 34 What happens to one s phenomenally conscious experience if one undergoes a perception of red but believes that one is perceiving orange? Another difficulty is to explain how higher-order thoughts (which are fully conceptual states, note) can give rise to the distinctive fine-grained character of phenomenally conscious experience. 35 And yet another problem is to explain why we should be entertaining multiple higher-order thoughts about our perceptual states at every moment of our waking lives. 36 On a global workspace account, it is easy to explain why we should always be subject to some or other phenomenally conscious state. This is because the central workspace serves to focus the entire organism on the most relevant stimuli or the most relevant activities whenever one is awake. 37 But what could possibly be the point of continually entertaining higher-order thoughts about (some subset of) our current perceptual states? And notice that the answer to this question cannot be: to provide flexibility in responding. For it is the first-order contents that guide planning and decision making, not generally the higher-order knowledge that one has such contents. The other main variety of higher-order approach to consciousness is dual-content theory, once defended by the present author. 38 On this view, every globally broadcast perceptual or percept-like state is both a first-order representation of the world or one s own body and a higher-order nonconceptual representation of the first-order percept. Each globally broadcast percept with the content red, for example, will at the same time have the content seeming red or experience of red. This is said to be a byproduct of the fact that globally broadcast contents are available to a higher-order thought system (or mindreading faculty) that is capable of entertaining thoughts about one s own

12 12 mental states, combined with the truth of some or other kind of consumer semantics. (According to the latter, the content of a given representation depends not just on its normal causes but also on what the consumer systems for that representation are apt to do with it.) Dual-content theory avoids all the difficulties that attend its actualist cousin. But it requires us to buy into a specific theory of contentdetermination, and there is little or no direct evidence to favor it over a first-order global workspace view. Moreover, the arguments that might be thought to support dual-content theory over the latter do not, in reality, do so, as has recently been argued. 39 Hence it is rational to prefer the simpler form of first-order account. The implications of higher-order thought theory for the question of consciousness in animals are likely to be quite restrictive. Even if one takes the most generous interpretation of the evidence for higherorder self-directed thought in non-human creatures, such thoughts are likely limited to other primates, as well as perhaps a few other highly social mammals and birds. 40 But arguably this interpretation is much too generous, and the data that are often taken to show self-monitoring abilities in animals are better explained in first-order terms, as I have argued elsewhere. 41 It may be that only humans, or perhaps humans and other species of great ape, are phenomenally conscious, if either of these forms of higher-order thought approach are correct. VI. THE GLOBAL WORKSPACE A global workspace account of consciousness was first developed in detail by Bernard Baars, and was originally formulated in cognitive (rather than neural-network) terms. 42 A close relative of Baars theory (published subsequently but independently) is Michael Tye s PANIC theory. 43 (PANIC stands for Poised Abstract Nonconceptual Intentional Content.) The basic idea of both approaches is that some perceptual and perception-like contents (including visual and auditory imagery) are globally broadcast and received by a wide range of other systems in the mind, whereas others have more specialized or local uses. Conscious states are those that are broadcast to systems for reporting, planning, reasoning, decision making, and remembering, whereas unconscious states are those that are not so broadcast, although they can have a variety of other roles or effects. Subsequent work has expanded the evidence-base for global workspace theory to include especially the neural networks involved. Much of this work has used minimal contrasts between conscious and

13 13 unconscious conditions in combination with EEG, MEG, and/or fmri. 44 Minimal contrasts are ones where the stimuli remain fixed but where consciousness is sometimes present, sometimes absent. One such case is binocular rivalry, where distinct images are presented to the two eyes, only one of which is conscious at any one time. A close relative of binocular rivalry is continuous flash suppression, where an image (of a face, say) can be presented continuously to one eye while the other eye is presented with a flashing Mondrian-type stimulus. The latter dominates initially, while the other stimulus emerges into consciousness from the noise. Briefly presented stimuli can also be backward masked to render them unconscious, while nevertheless being processed quite deeply, extracting high-level content that can prime subsequent behavior. If the intensity and timing parameters are set correctly, it can be arranged so that a backward-masked stimulus of a given intensity and duration is only visible on fifty percent of the trials. (The so-called attentional blink can be arranged similarly.) The general finding in such experiments is that unconscious stimuli give rise to local reverberations in visual cortex and some higher-level association areas of temporal cortex, whereas stimuli that are consciously experienced give rise to much more wide-spread coordinated activity, involving both prefrontal and parietal cortices as well. 45 Note that the prefrontal cortex is thought to house the main hubs of the networks responsible for decision making, reasoning, and verbal report, and that it interacts heavily with the hippocampus and medial temporal cortex in the formation of long-term memories. 46 So we appear to have a neural-network-based account of all of the main components of access consciousness, at least. Critics have sometimes objected that the minimal-contrast methodology controls for stimulus factors but not for behavioral or downstream cognitive ones. 47 For in order to report that a stimulus is visible on a given trial, participants need to say so, or press a button to indicate so, or respond in some other way that differs from how they respond when the stimulus remains unconscious. Hence there is ongoing debate over the question whether prefrontal cortex is specifically involved in consciousness itself, as opposed to its causes and effects. 48 All sides in these debates should accept that specific regions of occipital, temporal, and parietal cortices are critically involved in processing and representing particular sensory contents, of course, such as faces, colors, sounds, touch, and so on (that is, everyone should accept a role for iconic memory and its equivalent in nonvisual sense modalities). But according to global workspace theory, these contents

14 14 need to be broadcast more broadly and to prefrontal cortex, in particular in order to become conscious. Notice, however, that since these contents are thought to be broadcast quite widely, their representation in prefrontal cortex is likely to be diffuse and distributed. As a result, one can explain why prefrontal content-related activity sometimes doesn t show up in brain-imaging studies, as has recently been pointed out. 49 Likewise, the same observation can explain why the prefrontal MEG response to a briefly presented stimulus should be less predictive of conscious experience than the MEG signal emanating from visual areas. 50 For visual processing of the stimulus is concentrated in visual cortex, of course, whereas (when conscious) the resulting contents will be broadcast to multiple cortical sites, distributed in a variety of functionally-distinct regions. Moreover, studies using cellular recording techniques together with binocular flash suppression have shown that the content of a stimulus is represented in neuronal activity in prefrontal cortex, even under passive viewing conditions (but not when that stimulus is perceptually suppressed). 51 Although this study was conducted with monkeys, and so cannot provide direct evidence of prefrontal involvement in phenomenal consciousness, it does imply that the prefrontal activity observed in instances of conscious experience in humans can t just be a matter of action-preparation. For in this study no actions were required. In addition, a recent set of experiments attempted to control for both behavioral and attentional factors. 52 Participants were first trained to use all eight fingers when indicating the spatial position of a stimulus on a clock-face, with a unique finger used for each position. They were then presented with the same stimuli under conditions of backward masking that rendered the stimulus invisible on about fifty per cent of the trials, but they were nevertheless required to guess at a location on every trial. Since these guesses on invisible trials were accurate at levels well above chance, one can infer that something like blindsight was involved. The investigators then trained pattern classifiers on the resulting EEG and MEG data to determine where in the brain the information about the specific location of the stimulus was represented. The finding was that during consciously-seen trials the spatial content reached much further into prefrontal cortex, and was processed much more deeply, than in blindsight cases that shared the same motor response. Now, it is important to notice that global broadcasting in humans appears to be an all-or-nothing phenomenon. There is a step-function underlying the global workspace. Either activation levels in the neural populations in question remain below threshold, in which case no global broadcasting occurs (although there can be some additional local or specialized effects); or those activation levels hit

15 15 threshold, and full global broadcasting results. 53 This means that the workspace account can explain the all-or-nothing character of phenomenal consciousness. (In contrast, iconic-memory theory can t, except by stipulating that there is a particular level of activity in the neural systems that realize iconic memory that provide a threshold for consciousness.) In this respect too, then, there is a good mesh between the explaining theory and the target to be explained. In what follows I will be assuming that global workspace theory provides the most promising account of the neural correlates of phenomenal consciousness, at least, and will be investigating its implications for the question of consciousness in nonhuman animals. VII. NEURAL CORRELATE OR REDUCTIVE EXPLANATION? Notice, first, that although global broadcasting is all-or-nothing in humans, it will admit of degrees across species. Or more accurately (since the term global workspace was introduced in the first instance for the human case), processes in the minds of animals will more or less closely resemble human global broadcasting. Recall that globally broadcast contents are made available to a wide range of cognitive systems. They are made available for verbal reporting, to give rise to higher-order awareness, to participate in executive functions of reasoning, planning, and decision making, as well as to long-term memory-forming systems. Availability for verbal report is unique to human beings, of course. And it seems likely that there can only be higher-order awareness of one s own mental states in a relatively small class of nonhuman creatures (perhaps only great apes, or perhaps primates more generally; or maybe extending to some other social creatures such as dolphins and elephants). 54 Moreover, what we refer to collectively as executive function is really a set of different capacities that are at least partly independent of one another. 55 These functions include: selecting from among competing action-schemata, mentally rehearsing actions, inhibiting actions, forming intentions for the future, implementing intentions, switching between tasks, directing attention, searching memory, and modulating emotion. It seems quite likely that some of these capacities will be present in some creatures, but absent in others. In addition, all of the receiver systems for globally broadcast information in humans will admit of degrees of internal complexity across species, and will likewise involve differing degrees of conceptual richness and sophistication. Moreover, given the numbers, complexity, and complex relationships among the set of systems to which

16 16 phenomenally conscious states are broadcast in humans, it seems almost inevitable that similarities and differences in those systems across species will be complex, multifaceted, and cross-cutting. Indeed, it seems quite unlikely that there is an objective linearly-ordered similarity-space waiting to be discovered. On the contrary, there will be a multidimensional similarity network, with the minds of some species resembling a global broadcasting architecture in some respects, whereas others resemble it in others. What implications does all this have for the distribution of phenomenal consciousness across the animal kingdom? Much depends on whether one is a realist or an irrealist about qualia. Suppose, first, that one is a qualia realist. In that case one thinks that global broadcasting is a theory of the neural correlates of consciousness (in humans), not an explanatory theory of phenomenal consciousness itself. On the contrary, one thinks that globally broadcast representations have properties (qualia) that cannot be reduced to any combination of functional and representational ones. And in that case there will be a fact of the matter about which animal species (if any) are phenomenally conscious with minds that contain qualia-properties and which (if any) are not. However, it becomes impossible to know which species these are. Before developing these points, let me emphasize that I am now and henceforward in this discussion construing qualia realism rather more weakly than many people do. In particular, qualia realism is intended to encompass the views of someone like Ned Block, who denies that phenomenal properties can be reduced to any combination of functional and representational ones, while holding open that they might be reductively explained by some set of physical or neural properties. So qualia realism, as herein understood, is compatible with physicalism. The intended contrast is just with the claim that phenomenal consciousness reduces to globally broadcast nonconceptual content. On a qualia realist account, then, phenomenal consciousness doesn t reduce to globally broadcast nonconceptual content. Rather, there is an additional kind of property that attaches to such states, and it is this that is responsible for their phenomenal properties what they are like, their feel, and so on. One possibility is that these properties only attach to a state in the presence of the full suite of consumer systems for global broadcasting in humans (including capacities for higher-order thought and verbal reporting). In that case phenomenal consciousness will be unique to humans. Alternatively, states might acquire phenomenal properties whenever broadcast to some specific subset of those systems,

17 17 thereby fixing the set of animal species that qualify as phenomenally conscious. Since qualia are real, and really attach to some states but not others, there will be a fact of the matter. How could we learn what those facts are, however? Recall that phenomenal consciousness is firstpersonal. We can only really know of its presence by acquaintance in ourselves, or by report from others. So we know that other humans have phenomenally conscious states, but only because they can tell us about them, become puzzled, like us, by the nature of the properties involved, and so on. We can learn, on this basis, that some of the receiver systems for global broadcasting in humans aren t necessary for consciousness. Specifically, we can learn that long-term memory is inessential, since even severely amnesic patients can talk to us about their experiences and reflect on them in the required first-personal way. But once capacities for language and higher-order thought are removed from the picture (the former uniquely human, the latter likely quite restricted in distribution across species) we inevitably lack the kind of first-person evidence to warrant belief in the presence or absence of qualia. What if we could completely knock out capacities for language and higher-order thought on a temporary basis (perhaps using some future and more effective form of transcranial magnetic stimulation, or using some kind of invasive neural enervation of the systems involved)? If, on recovery, people reported that they continued to enjoy phenomenally-conscious experience, then wouldn t that demonstrate that language and reflective thought aren t necessary for consciousness? No, it would not. For these reports would, of course, be retrospective ones, grounded in memory of one s experiences while capacities for reporting were knocked out. But in order to report the contents of a memory, that memory needs to be activated and globally broadcast. It thereby becomes available to linguistic report and higher-order thought. So on the hypothesis that it is these, specifically, that are necessary for a content to acquire the properties of qualia, those memory-contents will thereby become phenomenally conscious, even if they hadn t been when originally experienced. Notice that we can t resolve these issues by appeal to Newton s Principle, either. Identifying behavior that is caused by conscious experience in ourselves, and observing exactly that behavior in another animal, we cannot conclude that the animal, too, has conscious experience. For one can t tell by introspection whether it is specifically the qualia properties that play the relevant causal role in ourselves, or rather the globally broadcast nonconceptual contents to which they attach. Nor can we tell which specific components of the latter are responsible for both the behavior and the presence of

18 18 qualia. It may be that one subset of the components of human global broadcasting is shared with the animal in question and causes the behavior, whereas it is another subset that is responsible for the state in question acquiring qualia. I conclude that if one is a qualia realist, while maintaining that global-workspace theory is the best account of the neural correlates of consciousness, then the question of animal consciousness becomes intractable. For there is no way to know which components of the workspace are sufficient for the presence of qualia. What, then, if one is a qualia irrealist? What if one believes that phenomenally conscious experience just is globally broadcast nonconceptual content? The most plausible way to develop such a view is to combine it with the phenomenal concept strategy for dealing with the hard problem thought experiments. If one maintains that phenomenal concepts are higher-order acquaintance-based indexicals, grounded in one s access to the nonconceptual contents in question, then one can explain why phenomenal consciousness should seem so puzzling. For in that case one will be able to think, There could be a being like me in all physical, functional, and representational respects who nevertheless lacks this sort of state. Likewise, no amount of physical, functional, or representational information about someone will entail or otherwise warrant a judgment that embeds the concept this sort of state, thus giving rise to an apparent explanatory gap. And so on. 56 Suppose, then, that phenomenal consciousness reduces to globally broadcast nonconceptual content. That leaves intact, of course, the claim that the concept of phenomenal consciousness is a first-person one. (Indeed, this is a critical component in the phenomenal concept strategy.) So consider a particular phenomenal concept this-r, employed while one thinks about a visual experience of redness. The truthcondition for the claim that a species of animal capable of color vision also undergoes phenomenal experience of red, is then of the form: Species X undergoes perceptual states of the same sort as this-r. If one is a realist about color qualia then it is clear what same sort here amounts to: it means that the same qualia-property is present in the mind of the animal in question. But if one is a qualia irrealist, then same sort here can only mean: a perceptual state with the same nonconceptual content entering into the same global broadcasting relation as this-r. And then the problem is: what counts as sameness of global broadcasting? In order for another animal s attended and broadcast perceptual representations

19 19 to qualify as the same, how similar must the set of consuming systems be to those involved in human global broadcasting? It is unclear that this question admits of a factual answer. Recall that the similarities and differences between human global broadcasting and global-broadcastinglike activity in other species of animal are likely to be complex, multifaceted, and cross-cutting. How could the question whether any of these qualify as the same be settled through anything other than stipulation? Someone might answer by claiming that global broadcasting of a certain sort is a natural kind, providing a core set of components underlying the manifest differences across species. Indeed, there is some reason to think that top-down attention, and its role in providing a coordinating center around which human and animal cognition is organized, constitutes just such a kind. For it seems to be deeply preserved and largely homologous across multiple vertebrate species, at least. 57 But why should one think that phenomenal consciousness tracks such a kind? For if there is one thing that everyone has agreed on, at least since Saul Kripke s famous work on the topic, 58 it is that terms referring to conscious mental states aren t used as natural-kind terms. In contrast, it is generally agreed that our concepts for substances like water are natural-kind ones. Even before we knew anything about chemistry, we used the concept water to refer to the underlying nature or essence of the recognizable stuff that fills our lakes and rivers (H 2O). But our concepts for the felt qualities of our conscious experiences aren t like that. We don t use them with the intention of referring to whatever natural kind underlies those experiences, whatever that might turn out to be, and however that kind might be presented in other creatures. On the contrary, we mean to refer just to those felt qualities themselves. Another possibility would be to introduce a categorical, ungraded, concept of global broadcasting, stipulating that an animal s percepts will count as globally broadcast if the processes involved are more similar to human global broadcasting than they are to any form of human unconscious perceptual state. But why should we think that phenomenal consciousness tracks the extension of this concept, rather than coinciding with full-blown human global broadcasting (or something in between, come to that)? For it isn t this property (nor the natural-kind property sketched in the previous paragraph) that figures in the explanation of the conscious/unconscious divide among human percepts, nor in the reductive explanation of our ensnarement by hard problem type thought-experiments. Recall, however, that we are supposing that globally broadcast nonconceptual content is what phenomenal consciousness is. Hence there is no special property that gets added when a perceptual

BLOCK S OVERFLOW ARGUMENT

BLOCK S OVERFLOW ARGUMENT BLOCK S OVERFLOW ARGUMENT BY PETER CARRUTHERS Abstract: This article challenges Block s overflow argument for the conclusion that phenomenal consciousness and access-consciousness are distinct. It shows

More information

Phil 490: Consciousness and the Self Handout [16] Jesse Prinz: Mental Pointing Phenomenal Knowledge Without Concepts

Phil 490: Consciousness and the Self Handout [16] Jesse Prinz: Mental Pointing Phenomenal Knowledge Without Concepts Phil 490: Consciousness and the Self Handout [16] Jesse Prinz: Mental Pointing Phenomenal Knowledge Without Concepts Main Goals of this Paper: Professor JeeLoo Liu 1. To present an account of phenomenal

More information

Comments on David Rosenthal s Consciousness, Content, and Metacognitive Judgments

Comments on David Rosenthal s Consciousness, Content, and Metacognitive Judgments Consciousness and Cognition 9, 215 219 (2000) doi:10.1006/ccog.2000.0438, available online at http://www.idealibrary.com on Comments on David Rosenthal s Consciousness, Content, and Metacognitive Judgments

More information

On A Distinction Between Access and Phenomenal Consciousness

On A Distinction Between Access and Phenomenal Consciousness On A Distinction Between Access and Phenomenal Consciousness By BRENT SILBY Department of Philosophy University of Canterbury New Zealand Copyright (c) Brent Silby 1998 www.def-logic.com/articles In his

More information

A conversation with Professor David Chalmers, May 20, 2016 Participants

A conversation with Professor David Chalmers, May 20, 2016 Participants A conversation with Professor David Chalmers, May 20, 2016 Participants Professor David Chalmers Professor of Philosophy, New York University (NYU) Luke Muehlhauser Research Analyst, Open Philanthropy

More information

24.500/Phil253 topics in philosophy of mind/perceptual experience

24.500/Phil253 topics in philosophy of mind/perceptual experience 24.500/Phil253 topics in philosophy of mind/perceptual experience session 10 24.500/Phil253 S07 1 plan tea @ 2.30 Block on consciousness, accessibility, FFA VWFA 24.500/Phil253 S07 2 phenomenal consciousness

More information

Our previous accounts of perceptual experience accepted the phenomenal principle:

Our previous accounts of perceptual experience accepted the phenomenal principle: PHL340 Handout 3: Representationalism 1 Representationalism and the Phenomenal Principle An experience s representational content is the way the world must be if the experience is to be veridical. Representationalism

More information

Consciousness and Intrinsic Higher- Order Content

Consciousness and Intrinsic Higher- Order Content 1 Consciousness and Intrinsic Higher- Order Content David Rosenthal City University of New York Graduate Center http://web.gc.cuny.edu/cogsci Tucson VII, April 7, 2006 OVERVIEW (Some slides were skipped

More information

CONSCIOUSNESS. Phil/Psych 256. Chris Eliasmith

CONSCIOUSNESS. Phil/Psych 256. Chris Eliasmith CONSCIOUSNESS Phil/Psych 256 Chris Eliasmith The C Word One main difficulty with consciousness is defining what we are talking about: Do we mean awareness (e.g., awake vs. asleep)? Qualia (what-it-is-like)?

More information

Fundamentals of Cognitive Psychology, 3e by Ronald T. Kellogg Chapter 2. Multiple Choice

Fundamentals of Cognitive Psychology, 3e by Ronald T. Kellogg Chapter 2. Multiple Choice Multiple Choice 1. Which structure is not part of the visual pathway in the brain? a. occipital lobe b. optic chiasm c. lateral geniculate nucleus *d. frontal lobe Answer location: Visual Pathways 2. Which

More information

Representational Content and Phenomenal Character

Representational Content and Phenomenal Character By David Hilbert, Unversity of Illinois at Chicago, Forthcoming in Sage Encyclopedia of Perception QUALIA Perception and thought are often, although not exclusively, concerned with information about the

More information

Empty Thoughts: An Explanatory Problem for Higher-Order Theories of Consciousness

Empty Thoughts: An Explanatory Problem for Higher-Order Theories of Consciousness Empty Thoughts: An Explanatory Problem for Higher-Order Theories of Consciousness word count: 2,420 Abstract Block (2011) has recently argued that empty higher-order representations raise a problem for

More information

Psychology, Neuroscience, and the Consciousness Dilemma. Katalin Balog

Psychology, Neuroscience, and the Consciousness Dilemma. Katalin Balog Psychology, Neuroscience, and the Consciousness Dilemma Katalin Balog In this paper, I present a dilemma for theorizing about the connection between phenomenality (the what it s like character of mental

More information

Papineau on the Actualist HOT Theory of Consciousness

Papineau on the Actualist HOT Theory of Consciousness Papineau on the Actualist HOT Theory of Consciousness Rocco J. Gennaro Indiana State University [final version in Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 2003] In his wonderful book Thinking About Consciousness,

More information

Consciousness Gleitman et al. (2011), Chapter 6, Part 1

Consciousness Gleitman et al. (2011), Chapter 6, Part 1 Consciousness Gleitman et al. (2011), Chapter 6, Part 1 Mike D Zmura Department of Cognitive Sciences, UCI Psych 9A / Psy Beh 11A March 11, 2014 T. M. D'Zmura 1 Consciousness Moment-by-moment awareness

More information

The Standard Theory of Conscious Perception

The Standard Theory of Conscious Perception The Standard Theory of Conscious Perception C. D. Jennings Department of Philosophy Boston University Pacific APA 2012 Outline 1 Introduction Motivation Background 2 Setting up the Problem Working Definitions

More information

(Visual) Attention. October 3, PSY Visual Attention 1

(Visual) Attention. October 3, PSY Visual Attention 1 (Visual) Attention Perception and awareness of a visual object seems to involve attending to the object. Do we have to attend to an object to perceive it? Some tasks seem to proceed with little or no attention

More information

A Healthy Brain. An Injured Brain

A Healthy Brain. An Injured Brain A Healthy Brain Before we can understand what happens when a brain is injured, we must realize what a healthy brain is made of and what it does. The brain is enclosed inside the skull. The skull acts as

More information

Commentary on The Erotetic Theory of Attention by Philipp Koralus. Sebastian Watzl

Commentary on The Erotetic Theory of Attention by Philipp Koralus. Sebastian Watzl Commentary on The Erotetic Theory of Attention by Philipp Koralus A. Introduction Sebastian Watzl The study of visual search is one of the experimental paradigms for the study of attention. Visual search

More information

H.O.T. Theory, Concepts, and Synesthesia: A Reply to Adams and Shreve

H.O.T. Theory, Concepts, and Synesthesia: A Reply to Adams and Shreve H.O.T. Theory, Concepts, and Synesthesia: A Reply to Adams and Shreve Rocco J. Gennaro Abstract: In response to Fred Adams and Charlotte Shreve s (2016) paper entitled What Can Synesthesia Teach Us about

More information

Chapter 6. Attention. Attention

Chapter 6. Attention. Attention Chapter 6 Attention Attention William James, in 1890, wrote Everyone knows what attention is. Attention is the taking possession of the mind, in clear and vivid form, of one out of what seem several simultaneously

More information

David Chalmers, The hard problem of consciousness

David Chalmers, The hard problem of consciousness 24.09x Minds and Machines David Chalmers, The hard problem of consciousness Excerpts from David Chalmers, The hard problem of consciousness, in The Norton Introduction to Philosophy, edited by Gideon Rosen,

More information

Skepticism about perceptual content

Skepticism about perceptual content Skepticism about perceptual content phil 93515 Jeff Speaks March 29, 2007 1 Contents v. objects of perception The view that perceptual experiences have contents is the view that perceptual experiences

More information

PSYCHOLOGICAL CONSCIOUSNESS AND PHENOMENAL CONSCIOUSNESS. Overview

PSYCHOLOGICAL CONSCIOUSNESS AND PHENOMENAL CONSCIOUSNESS. Overview Lecture 28-29 PSYCHOLOGICAL CONSCIOUSNESS AND PHENOMENAL CONSCIOUSNESS Overview David J. Chalmers in his famous book The Conscious Mind 1 tries to establish that the problem of consciousness as the hard

More information

Review of Tim Bayne s The Unity of Consciousness

Review of Tim Bayne s The Unity of Consciousness Review of Tim Bayne s The Unity of Consciousness Angela Mendelovici amendel5@uwo.ca July 21, 2011 Tim Bayne, The Unity of Consciousness, Oxford University Press, 2010, 341pp., $55.00 (hbk), ISBN 9780199215386.

More information

Effective Intentions: The Power of Conscious Will

Effective Intentions: The Power of Conscious Will Book Review Effective Intentions: The Power of Conscious Will Alfred R. Mele Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2009 Marco Fenici* fenici@unisi.it Mele s book is a concise analysis of much research in neurophysiology

More information

Consciousness and Theory of Mind: a Common Theory?

Consciousness and Theory of Mind: a Common Theory? Consciousness and Theory of Mind: a Common Theory? Keywords: Consciousness, Higher-Order Theories, Theory of Mind, Mind-reading, Metacognition. 1 Introduction Many of our mental states are phenomenally

More information

A Direct Object of Perception

A Direct Object of Perception E-LOGOS Electronic Journal for Philosophy 2015, Vol. 22(1) 28 36 ISSN 1211-0442 (DOI 10.18267/j.e-logos.411),Peer-reviewed article Journal homepage: e-logos.vse.cz A Direct Object of Perception Mika Suojanen

More information

Consciousness (Response to the Hard Problem)

Consciousness (Response to the Hard Problem) Indiana Undergraduate Journal of Cognitive Science 3 (2008) 21-27 Copyright 2008 IUJCS. All rights reserved Consciousness (Response to the Hard Problem) Artem Tsvetkov Cognitive Science and Biological

More information

Psychology, Neuroscience, and the Consciousness Dilemma. Katalin Balog. Draft (comments welcome)

Psychology, Neuroscience, and the Consciousness Dilemma. Katalin Balog. Draft (comments welcome) Psychology, Neuroscience, and the Consciousness Dilemma Katalin Balog Draft (comments welcome) In this paper, I present a dilemma for theorizing about the connection between phenomenality (the what it

More information

Phenomenal content. PHIL April 15, 2012

Phenomenal content. PHIL April 15, 2012 Phenomenal content PHIL 93507 April 15, 2012 1. The phenomenal content thesis... 1 2. The problem of phenomenally silent contents... 2 3. Phenomenally sneaky contents... 3 3.1. Phenomenal content and phenomenal

More information

Consciousness II. Mechanical Consciousness. Carlotta Pavese

Consciousness II. Mechanical Consciousness. Carlotta Pavese Consciousness II Mechanical Consciousness Carlotta Pavese 11.19.13 Outline 1 The Consciousness Debate 2 Outline 1 The Consciousness Debate 2 What is Consciousness? Some Things are Not So Baffling or Hard

More information

Functionalist theories of content

Functionalist theories of content Functionalist theories of content PHIL 93507 April 22, 2012 Let s assume that there is a certain stable dependence relation between the physical internal states of subjects and the phenomenal characters

More information

The Rationality of Perception rewrites perception s rational role and its rational standing. This

The Rationality of Perception rewrites perception s rational role and its rational standing. This The Philosophical Review, 2018 Susanna Siegel, The Rationality of Perception. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017. xxv + 220 pp. The Rationality of Perception rewrites perception s rational role and

More information

Consciousness and Metacognition

Consciousness and Metacognition 1 Consciousness and Metacognition David Rosenthal ASSC 20, Buenos Aires CUNY Graduate Center 15 June 2016 Philosophy and Cognitive Science http://tinyurl.com/dr-cuny/ I. Consciousness and Misrepresentation

More information

Spectrum inversion and intentionalism

Spectrum inversion and intentionalism Spectrum inversion and intentionalism phil 93507 Jeff Speaks September 15, 2009 1 What is a spectrum inversion scenario?..................... 1 2 Intentionalism is false because inverts could have in common.........

More information

Explaining an Explanatory Gap Gilbert Harman Princeton University

Explaining an Explanatory Gap Gilbert Harman Princeton University Explaining an Explanatory Gap Gilbert Harman Princeton University Discussions of the mind-body problem often refer to an explanatory gap (Levine 1983) between some aspect of our conscious mental life and

More information

Naturalizing the Mind, by Fred Dretske. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, Pp. 208.

Naturalizing the Mind, by Fred Dretske. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, Pp. 208. Page 1 Naturalizing the Mind, by Fred Dretske. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1995. Pp. 208. In this important book Fred Dretske defends a version of externalism which he calls representational naturalism.

More information

Agnosia, Epilepsy, Sleep Walking, and DID. D. Kiper

Agnosia, Epilepsy, Sleep Walking, and DID. D. Kiper Agnosia, Epilepsy, Sleep Walking, and DID D. Kiper 6.12.2018 Agnosia A-gnosis (absence of knowledge); Seelenblindheit; agnosia (Freud) Akinetopsia Achromatopsia Capgras syndrome DF: A Visual Agnostic DF

More information

Taken From The Brain Top to Bottom //

Taken From The Brain Top to Bottom // Taken From The Brain Top to Bottom // http://thebrain.mcgill.ca/flash/d/d_03/d_03_cl/d_03_cl_que/d_03_cl_que.html THE EVOLUTIONARY LAYERS OF THE HUMAN BRAIN The first time you observe the anatomy of the

More information

The scope of perceptual content, II: properties

The scope of perceptual content, II: properties The scope of perceptual content, II: properties Jeff Speaks November 16, 2009 1 What are the candidates?............................ 1 2 Arguments for inclusion............................. 2 2.1 From

More information

Perception LECTURE FOUR MICHAELMAS Dr Maarten Steenhagen

Perception LECTURE FOUR MICHAELMAS Dr Maarten Steenhagen Perception LECTURE FOUR MICHAELMAS 2017 Dr Maarten Steenhagen ms2416@cam.ac.uk Last week Lecture 1: Naive Realism Lecture 2: The Argument from Hallucination Lecture 3: Representationalism Lecture 4: Disjunctivism

More information

Cerebral Cortex: Association Areas and Memory Tutis Vilis

Cerebral Cortex: Association Areas and Memory Tutis Vilis 97 Cerebral Cortex: Association Areas and Memory Tutis Vilis a) Name the 5 main subdivisions of the cerebral cortex. Frontal, temporal, occipital, parietal, and limbic (on the medial side) b) Locate the

More information

U. T. Place, Is consciousness a brain process?

U. T. Place, Is consciousness a brain process? 24.09x Minds and Machines U. T. Place, Is consciousness a brain process? Excerpts from U.T. Place, Is consciousness a brain process?, British Journal of Psychology 47: 44-50, 1956. Place begins by noting

More information

The Concept of Simulation in Control-Theoretic Accounts of Motor Control and Action Perception

The Concept of Simulation in Control-Theoretic Accounts of Motor Control and Action Perception The Concept of Simulation in Control-Theoretic Accounts of Motor Control and Action Perception Mitchell Herschbach (mherschb@ucsd.edu) Department of Philosophy, University of California, San Diego, 9500

More information

Neural codes PSY 310 Greg Francis. Lecture 12. COC illusion

Neural codes PSY 310 Greg Francis. Lecture 12. COC illusion Neural codes PSY 310 Greg Francis Lecture 12 Is 100 billion neurons enough? COC illusion The COC illusion looks like real squares because the neural responses are similar True squares COC squares Ganglion

More information

Bernard Baars. Excerpts from Conversation on Consciousness (by Susan Blackmore) Consciousness is a real working theatre. Studies Psychology at UCLA

Bernard Baars. Excerpts from Conversation on Consciousness (by Susan Blackmore) Consciousness is a real working theatre. Studies Psychology at UCLA Excerpts from Conversation on Consciousness (by Susan Blackmore) Consciousness is a real working theatre Studies Psychology at UCLA Rejected behaviorism Bernard Baars Psycholinguistics Cognitive Neuroscience

More information

Neuroscience Tutorial

Neuroscience Tutorial Neuroscience Tutorial Brain Organization : cortex, basal ganglia, limbic lobe : thalamus, hypothal., pituitary gland : medulla oblongata, midbrain, pons, cerebellum Cortical Organization Cortical Organization

More information

Learning Objectives.

Learning Objectives. Emilie O Neill, class of 2016 Learning Objectives 1. Describe the types of deficits that occur with lesions in association areas including: prosopagnosia, neglect, aphasias, agnosia, apraxia 2. Discuss

More information

The Nature of Consciousness Handout [6] William Lycan: Consciousness as Internal Monitoring

The Nature of Consciousness Handout [6] William Lycan: Consciousness as Internal Monitoring The Nature of Consciousness Handout [6] William Lycan: Consciousness as Internal Monitoring JeeLoo Liu The Goal: 1. To argue that what distinguishes conscious mental activity from un- and subconscious

More information

Eliminative materialism

Eliminative materialism Michael Lacewing Eliminative materialism Eliminative materialism (also known as eliminativism) argues that future scientific developments will show that the way we think and talk about the mind is fundamentally

More information

A Difference that Makes a Difference: Welfare and the Equality of Consideration

A Difference that Makes a Difference: Welfare and the Equality of Consideration 84 A Difference that Makes a Difference: Welfare and the Equality of Consideration Abstract Elijah Weber Philosophy Department Bowling Green State University eliweber1980@gmail.com In Welfare, Happiness,

More information

WHAT CONSCIOUS STATES ARE LIKE

WHAT CONSCIOUS STATES ARE LIKE WHAT CONSCIOUS STATES ARE LIKE Thomas Nagel: Consciousness is what makes the mind-body problem really intractable [F]undamentally an organism has conscious mental states if and only if there is something

More information

Dynamics and Modeling in Cognitive Science - I

Dynamics and Modeling in Cognitive Science - I Dynamics and Modeling in Cognitive Science - I Narayanan Srinivasan Centre of Behavioural and Cognitive Sciences University of Allahabad, India Outline General introduction to Cognitive Science Problem

More information

Introduction. Chapter The Perceptual Process

Introduction. Chapter The Perceptual Process Chapter 1 Introduction Most of us take for granted our ability to perceive the external world. However, this is no simple deed at all. Imagine being given a task of designing a machine that can perceive,

More information

FAILURES OF OBJECT RECOGNITION. Dr. Walter S. Marcantoni

FAILURES OF OBJECT RECOGNITION. Dr. Walter S. Marcantoni FAILURES OF OBJECT RECOGNITION Dr. Walter S. Marcantoni VISUAL AGNOSIA -damage to the extrastriate visual regions (occipital, parietal and temporal lobes) disrupts recognition of complex visual stimuli

More information

Why the question of animal consciousness might not matter very much

Why the question of animal consciousness might not matter very much Why the question of animal consciousness might not matter very much Peter Carruthers ABSTRACT: According to higher-order thought accounts of phenomenal consciousness (e.g. Carruthers, 2000) it is unlikely

More information

Neuroscience and Generalized Empirical Method Go Three Rounds

Neuroscience and Generalized Empirical Method Go Three Rounds Bruce Anderson, Neuroscience and Generalized Empirical Method Go Three Rounds: Review of Robert Henman s Global Collaboration: Neuroscience as Paradigmatic Journal of Macrodynamic Analysis 9 (2016): 74-78.

More information

To understand AD, it is important to

To understand AD, it is important to To understand AD, it is important to know a bit about the brain. This part of Unraveling the Mystery gives an inside view of the normal brain, how it works, and what happens during aging. The brain is

More information

Recording Transcript Wendy Down Shift #9 Practice Time August 2018

Recording Transcript Wendy Down Shift #9 Practice Time August 2018 Recording Transcript Wendy Down Shift #9 Practice Time August 2018 Hi there. This is Wendy Down and this recording is Shift #9 in our 6 month coaching program. [Excuse that I referred to this in the recording

More information

COGS 101A: Sensation and Perception

COGS 101A: Sensation and Perception COGS 101A: Sensation and Perception 1 Virginia R. de Sa Department of Cognitive Science UCSD Lecture 6: Beyond V1 - Extrastriate cortex Chapter 4 Course Information 2 Class web page: http://cogsci.ucsd.edu/

More information

Representation 1. Discussion Question. Roskies: Downplaying the Similarities of Neuroimages to Photographs

Representation 1. Discussion Question. Roskies: Downplaying the Similarities of Neuroimages to Photographs Representation 1 Discussion Question In what way are photographs more reliable than paintings? A. They aren t B. The image in the photograph directly reflects what is before the lens C. The image in the

More information

Myers Psychology for AP*

Myers Psychology for AP* Myers Psychology for AP* David G. Myers PowerPoint Presentation Slides by Kent Korek Germantown High School Worth Publishers, 2010 *AP is a trademark registered and/or owned by the College Board, which

More information

Over the years, philosophers, psychoanalysts, psychologists, psychiatrists,

Over the years, philosophers, psychoanalysts, psychologists, psychiatrists, DEVELOPING A SELF: A GENERAL SEMANTICS WAY MILTON DAWES Over the years, philosophers, psychoanalysts, psychologists, psychiatrists, and others have asked: Is there such a thing as a self? Does the self

More information

Neuroscience of Consciousness II

Neuroscience of Consciousness II 1 C83MAB: Mind and Brain Neuroscience of Consciousness II Tobias Bast, School of Psychology, University of Nottingham 2 Consciousness State of consciousness - Being awake/alert/attentive/responsive Contents

More information

V71LAR: Locke, Appearance and Reality. TOPIC 2: WHAT IS IT TO PERCEIVE AN OBJECT? Continued...

V71LAR: Locke, Appearance and Reality. TOPIC 2: WHAT IS IT TO PERCEIVE AN OBJECT? Continued... V71LAR: Locke, Appearance and Reality TOPIC 2: WHAT IS IT TO PERCEIVE AN OBJECT? Continued... Are you getting this? Yes No Summary of theories of perception Type of theory Things we are directly aware

More information

Importance of Deficits

Importance of Deficits Importance of Deficits In complex systems the parts are often so integrated that they cannot be detected in normal operation Need to break the system to discover the components not just physical components

More information

Competing Frameworks in Perception

Competing Frameworks in Perception Competing Frameworks in Perception Lesson II: Perception module 08 Perception.08. 1 Views on perception Perception as a cascade of information processing stages From sensation to percept Template vs. feature

More information

Competing Frameworks in Perception

Competing Frameworks in Perception Competing Frameworks in Perception Lesson II: Perception module 08 Perception.08. 1 Views on perception Perception as a cascade of information processing stages From sensation to percept Template vs. feature

More information

The Wellbeing Course. Resource: Mental Skills. The Wellbeing Course was written by Professor Nick Titov and Dr Blake Dear

The Wellbeing Course. Resource: Mental Skills. The Wellbeing Course was written by Professor Nick Titov and Dr Blake Dear The Wellbeing Course Resource: Mental Skills The Wellbeing Course was written by Professor Nick Titov and Dr Blake Dear About Mental Skills This resource introduces three mental skills which people find

More information

5th Mini-Symposium on Cognition, Decision-making and Social Function: In Memory of Kang Cheng

5th Mini-Symposium on Cognition, Decision-making and Social Function: In Memory of Kang Cheng 5th Mini-Symposium on Cognition, Decision-making and Social Function: In Memory of Kang Cheng 13:30-13:35 Opening 13:30 17:30 13:35-14:00 Metacognition in Value-based Decision-making Dr. Xiaohong Wan (Beijing

More information

Physiological Mechanisms of Lucid Dreaming. Stephen LaBerge Sleep Research Center Stanford University

Physiological Mechanisms of Lucid Dreaming. Stephen LaBerge Sleep Research Center Stanford University Physiological Mechanisms of Lucid Dreaming Stephen LaBerge Sleep Research Center Stanford University For those of you here who aren t familiar with the general approach we have been using in our research

More information

The Scientific Method

The Scientific Method The Scientific Method Prelab Thoroughly explore the website Understanding Science: How Science Really Works at http://undsci.berkeley.edu. Answer the following five questions based on your textbook and

More information

SEARLE AND FUNCTIONALISM. Is the mind software?

SEARLE AND FUNCTIONALISM. Is the mind software? SEARLE AND FUNCTIONALISM Is the mind software? 1 Materialist Theories of the Mind The Identity Theory Each type of mental property is identical to a certain type of physical property. (E.g. pain is just

More information

Psych 333, Winter 2008, Instructor Boynton, Exam 2

Psych 333, Winter 2008, Instructor Boynton, Exam 2 Name: ID # ID: A Psych 333, Winter 2008, Instructor Boynton, Exam 2 Multiple Choice (38 questions, 1 point each) Identify the letter of the choice that best completes the statement or answers the question.

More information

Higher Cortical Function

Higher Cortical Function Emilie O Neill, class of 2016 Higher Cortical Function Objectives Describe the association cortical areas processing sensory, motor, executive, language, and emotion/memory information (know general location

More information

(SAT). d) inhibiting automatized responses.

(SAT). d) inhibiting automatized responses. Which of the following findings does NOT support the existence of task-specific mental resources? 1. a) It is more difficult to combine two verbal tasks than one verbal task and one spatial task. 2. b)

More information

Human Nervous System

Human Nervous System Human Nervous System A network of interconnected parts that controls behavior & connects us to the world Central Nervous System consists of the brain and spinal cord Peripheral Nervous System consists

More information

Neuroimaging of high-level visual functions. Visual awareness

Neuroimaging of high-level visual functions. Visual awareness Neuroimaging of high-level visual functions Visual awareness Phylosphy of mind Art AI Normal and abnormal states Coma Drugs Hypnosis Religion Cosciousness 2 Unconscious processes Normal and abnormal contents

More information

Functionalism. (1) Machine Functionalism

Functionalism. (1) Machine Functionalism Functionalism As Levine indicates, from a functionalist viewpoint, the status of a mental state is not given by its internal constitution but by its function. For instance, a thought or a pain depends

More information

Comensana, McGrath Perceptual Reasons

Comensana, McGrath Perceptual Reasons Comensana, McGrath Perceptual Reasons Brian T. Miller September 20, 2017 1 Interested specifically in perceptual evidence. Two main theories Phenomenalism perceptual reasons are facts about experiences

More information

Book Information Jakob Hohwy, The Predictive Mind, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013, ix+288, 60.00,

Book Information Jakob Hohwy, The Predictive Mind, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013, ix+288, 60.00, 1 Book Information Jakob Hohwy, The Predictive Mind, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013, ix+288, 60.00, 978-0-19-968273-7. Review Body The Predictive Mind by Jakob Hohwy is the first monograph to address

More information

Computational Explorations in Cognitive Neuroscience Chapter 7: Large-Scale Brain Area Functional Organization

Computational Explorations in Cognitive Neuroscience Chapter 7: Large-Scale Brain Area Functional Organization Computational Explorations in Cognitive Neuroscience Chapter 7: Large-Scale Brain Area Functional Organization 1 7.1 Overview This chapter aims to provide a framework for modeling cognitive phenomena based

More information

SENSATION AND PERCEPTION KEY TERMS

SENSATION AND PERCEPTION KEY TERMS SENSATION AND PERCEPTION KEY TERMS BOTTOM-UP PROCESSING BOTTOM-UP PROCESSING refers to processing sensory information as it is coming in. In other words, if I flash a random picture on the screen, your

More information

What is the relationship between the mind and the brain?

What is the relationship between the mind and the brain? What is the relationship between the mind and the brain? Ben White 05.02.2019 Mental Consciousness Belief Desire Thought Memory Sensation Perception Emotion Imagination Rationality What distinguishes the

More information

Why do we need vision? We need vision for two quite different but complementary reasons We need vision to give us detailed knowledge of the world beyo

Why do we need vision? We need vision for two quite different but complementary reasons We need vision to give us detailed knowledge of the world beyo So, What Has Vision Done For Me Lately? Prepared for ICBO Ontario, CA By: R. A. Hohendorf OD April 2010 Why do we need vision? We need vision for two quite different but complementary reasons We need vision

More information

Modules 7. Consciousness and Attention. sleep/hypnosis 1

Modules 7. Consciousness and Attention. sleep/hypnosis 1 Modules 7 Consciousness and Attention sleep/hypnosis 1 Consciousness Our awareness of ourselves and our environments. sleep/hypnosis 2 Dual Processing Our perceptual neural pathways have two routes. The

More information

Zen and the Art of Explaining the Mind

Zen and the Art of Explaining the Mind Harnad, S. (2011) Zen and the Art of Explaining the Mind. International Journal of Machine Consciousness (IJMC) (forthcming). [Review of Shanahan M. (2010) Embodiment and the Inner Life: Cognition and

More information

Why is dispersion of memory important*

Why is dispersion of memory important* What is memory* It is a web of connections Research has shown that people who lose their memory also lose the ability to connect things to each other in their mind It is these connections that let us understand

More information

HARRISON ASSESSMENTS DEBRIEF GUIDE 1. OVERVIEW OF HARRISON ASSESSMENT

HARRISON ASSESSMENTS DEBRIEF GUIDE 1. OVERVIEW OF HARRISON ASSESSMENT HARRISON ASSESSMENTS HARRISON ASSESSMENTS DEBRIEF GUIDE 1. OVERVIEW OF HARRISON ASSESSMENT Have you put aside an hour and do you have a hard copy of your report? Get a quick take on their initial reactions

More information

Why the Question of Animal Consciousness Might Not Matter Very Much

Why the Question of Animal Consciousness Might Not Matter Very Much T&F (2005 Style) [23.3.2005 5:21pm] [83 102] [Page No. 83] Philosophical Psychology Vol. 18, No. 1, February 2005, pp. 83 102 Why the Question of Animal Consciousness Might Not Matter Very Much Peter Carruthers

More information

The Brain. Its major systems, How we study them, How they make the mind

The Brain. Its major systems, How we study them, How they make the mind The Brain Its major systems, How we study them, How they make the mind 9.00 Introduction to Psychology Joanne s Recitation Section Friday, February 11, 2011 Outline 1. Syllabus: Course Requirements, Exams,

More information

Unit 3: EXPLORING YOUR LIMITING BELIEFS

Unit 3: EXPLORING YOUR LIMITING BELIEFS Unit 3: EXPLORING YOUR LIMITING BELIEFS Beliefs and Emotions Bring to mind a negative belief you hold about money. Perhaps it is I don t believe I can win with money or Money is hard to come by. While

More information

1) Drop off in the Bi 150 box outside Baxter 331 or to the head TA (jcolas).

1) Drop off in the Bi 150 box outside Baxter 331 or  to the head TA (jcolas). Bi/CNS/NB 150 Problem Set 5 Due: Tuesday, Nov. 24, at 4:30 pm Instructions: 1) Drop off in the Bi 150 box outside Baxter 331 or e-mail to the head TA (jcolas). 2) Submit with this cover page. 3) Use a

More information

The 6 Vital Keys to Turn Visualization Into Manifestation

The 6 Vital Keys to Turn Visualization Into Manifestation The 6 Vital Keys to Turn Visualization Into Manifestation Tom Nicoli, BCH, CI, CPC Master Visionary If you find something of value in this report, instead of passing on the PDF, would you be so kind as

More information

Difficult Conversations

Difficult Conversations Difficult Conversations Corban Sanchez Academic Advisor NACADA Conference 2011 Douglas Stone, Bruce Patton, and Sheila Heen of the Harvard Negotiation Project Moving Toward a Learning Conversation Normal

More information

IAT 814 Knowledge Visualization. Visual Attention. Lyn Bartram

IAT 814 Knowledge Visualization. Visual Attention. Lyn Bartram IAT 814 Knowledge Visualization Visual Attention Lyn Bartram Why we care in an information-rich world, the wealth of information means a dearth of something else: a scarcity of whatever it is that information

More information

Psychology Perception

Psychology Perception Psychology 343 - Perception James R. Sawusch, 360 Park Hall jsawusch@buffalo.edu 645-0238 TA is Timothy Pruitt, 312 Park tapruitt@buffalo.edu Text is Sensation & Perception by Goldstein (8th edition) PSY

More information

How Many Colors Can You Remember? Capacity is about Conscious vs unconscious memories

How Many Colors Can You Remember? Capacity is about Conscious vs unconscious memories Science B44 Lecture 18 Visual Memory Memory 1. Afterimage, persistence, iconic sensory memory 2. Conscious vs unconscious memories 3. Short and long term memories 4. Where are memories seen 5. Flashbulb

More information

Rules of apparent motion: The shortest-path constraint: objects will take the shortest path between flashed positions.

Rules of apparent motion: The shortest-path constraint: objects will take the shortest path between flashed positions. Rules of apparent motion: The shortest-path constraint: objects will take the shortest path between flashed positions. The box interrupts the apparent motion. The box interrupts the apparent motion.

More information