Theories of categorical reasoning and extended syllogisms

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Theories of categorical reasoning and extended syllogisms"

Transcription

1 THINKING & REASONING, 2006, 12 (4), Theories of categorical reasoning and extended syllogisms David E. Copeland University of Southern Mississippi, Hattiesburg, MS, USA The aim of this study was to examine the predictions of three theories of human logical reasoning, (a) mental model theory, (b) formal rules theory (e.g., PSYCOP), and (c) the probability heuristics model, regarding the inferences people make for extended categorical syllogisms. Most research with extended syllogisms has been restricted to the quantifier All and to an asymmetrical presentation. This study used three-premise syllogisms with the additional quantifiers that are used for traditional categorical syllogisms as well as additional syllogistic figures. The predictions of the theories were examined using overall accuracy as well as a multinomial tree modelling technique. The results demonstrated that all three theories were able to predict response selections at high levels. However, the modelling analyses showed that the probability heuristics model did the best in both Experiments 1 and 2. The goal of this study was to examine inference making in an extended categorical syllogism task. Extended categorical syllogisms are logical arguments that relate entities, or groups, and consist of more than two premises, or categorical statements. Here is an example: All W are X (premise 1) All X are Y (premise 2) No Y are Z (premise 3) Therefore, no W are Z (conclusion) Correspondence should be addressed to David E. Copeland, Department of Psychology, Box 5025, University of Southern Mississippi, Hattiesburg, MS USA. David.Copeland@usm.edu I would like to thank Seth Allen for his assistance in collecting the data. I also wish to thank Steve Boker, Darcia Narvaez, Mike Oaksford, Michael Wenger, two anonymous reviewers, and especially G. A. Radvansky, for their insightful comments throughout this research project. Portions of this research were supported in part by a grant from the Army Research Institute, ARMY-DASW01-99-K Ó 2006 Psychology Press, an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business DOI: /

2 380 COPELAND There are many explanations for how people who are not experienced with logic make categorical inferences. These explanations include the use of rules, both superficial heuristics (e.g., Woodworth & Sells, 1935) and formal logic rules (e.g., Rips, 1994), probabilistic thinking (e.g., Chater & Oaksford, 1999), and representations such as mental models (e.g., Johnson-Laird & Bara, 1984). Research has supported some of these theories more than others, but no definitive answer has yet emerged for how people reason categorically. The current study examined these various theories of categorical reasoning in an extended categorical syllogism task. This is a highly constrained type of inference making, and thus easy to study. Most studies that have examined extended categorical syllogisms (e.g., Frase, 1969) have considered them in the context of a paragraph, rather than in syllogism format (however, see Griggs 1976a). Moreover, previous studies have been limited to the use of a single quantifier, All. This paper considers extended categorical syllogisms in syllogistic format along with some additional elements neglected by past research. This includes additional quantifiers and syllogistic figure differences. CATEGORICAL LOGIC Categorical logic is a type of deductive logic and is typically expressed in the form of a syllogism. In a categorical syllogism, a specific conclusion is inferred from general statements. For example, if it is known that all men are mortal and that Socrates is a man, then it can be inferred that Socrates is mortal. Traditional categorical syllogisms contain two premises, or statements, that describe a relation among three entities. Two entities (e.g., X and Z) are mentioned in different premises and are linked by another entity (e.g., Y) that is mentioned in both of the premises. There are four orders, or syllogistic figures, in which these terms can be expressed in the two premises: (1) XY-YZ (2) YX-ZY (3) XY-ZY (4) YX-YZ Each premise uses a quantifier to describe the relation among the entities. The quantifiers are listed below along with their traditional abbreviations: (1) All (A) (2) No (E) (3) Some (I) (4) Some... not (O) The combination of the syllogistic figures with the four quantifiers leads to a total of 64 traditional categorical syllogisms. Of this total, only 27 have valid conclusions.

3 EXTENDED SYLLOGISMS 381 Extended syllogisms (also referred to as sorites or set inclusions; see Evans, Newstead, & Byrne, 1993) differ from traditional categorical syllogisms in that they have at least three premises that describe the relations between at least four entities. Because of this, there is no upper limit on the number of extended syllogisms with valid conclusions. It should be noted that if none of the premises has the quantifier, All, there cannot be a valid conclusion. However, just because the quantifier All is present does not mean that there is a valid conclusion. For the current study, extended syllogisms were limited to three premises. Also, syllogistic figure was only manipulated for the first two premises. Using these restrictions creates a well-defined and manageable set for studying extended syllogisms. EXTENDED CATEGORICAL SYLLOGISMS Most studies (e.g., Frase, 1969) that have examined extended categorical syllogisms have only used a single extended syllogism: All V are W! All W are X! All X are Y! All Y are Z Studies investigating extended syllogisms have been restricted in that they have only used the quantifier All. However, they have used a number of different tasks to test performance, including having people recall information, verify the truth of statements, or verify whether statements were old or new, presenting the information in the format of a syllogism, and presenting the information as part of a text. There have been mixed results as to how good people are at accurately drawing inferences for extended syllogisms. Studies that have used a recall test (Favrel & Barrouillet, 2000; Frase, 1969, 1970; Griggs, 1977) have shown that people were more likely to report relationships that were explicitly mentioned rather than relationships that required inferences. Also, studies have shown that people are less likely to accurately identify inferences when more premises are involved (Barrouillet, 1996; Favrel & Barrouillet, 2000). Other studies, however, have supported the idea that people can accurately draw inferences from extended syllogisms. First, a study by Griggs (1976b) asked whether statements were old or new. He found that people rated inferences as old at a similar rate as statements that were in the text. Second, when people have a goal of making inferences, they spend more time reading (Carlson, Lundy, & Yaure, 1992). Finally, the format in which extended syllogisms are presented affects performance. Performance improves dramatically when extended syllogisms are presented in the form of a syllogism (Griggs & Warner, 1982) or when they

4 382 COPELAND are re-phrased using the word in (e.g., All X are in Y) (Mynatt & Smith, 1979). These studies suggest that people are capable of drawing inferences, particularly when using a presentation format such as a syllogism. However, these studies have not considered extended syllogisms in the context of current theories of categorical reasoning. Thus, a closer examination of extended syllogisms is necessary. The next section examines three theories of categorical reasoning that have been used to explain performance in different reasoning tasks. THEORIES OF HUMAN SYLLOGISTIC REASONING There are many different theories of how people solve categorical reasoning problems. The following section examines the most prominent of these ideas: mental model theory, formal rules theory, and the probability heuristics model. For the most part, these theories have not been applied to the domain of extended categorical syllogisms (although see Favrel & Barrouillet, 2000, for a consideration of mental models). This section reviews the explanations of traditional categorical reasoning proposed by these theories. There is also a discussion of how these theories can be used to explain performance on an extended categorical syllogism task. Examples of how each theory applies to extended syllogisms are discussed in a later section. Mental model theory The basic idea of mental model theory (Johnson-Laird, 1999) is that people construct mental representations of the situation described, of the state-ofaffairs in the world (Johnson-Laird, 1983; Johnson-Laird & Bara, 1984; Johnson-Laird & Byrne, 1991). These mental representations simulate the possible ways that the terms can relate to one another. These mental models that are constructed can be compared to one another to contrast different situations that might be possible based on the premises. According to mental model theory, people go through a series of stages. First, a model is constructed for the first premise. Next, people add the information from the second premise. In the third stage, people make an inference from their integrated model. This conclusion expresses a relationship that is not explicitly stated in the premises. The final stage consists of testing the conclusion. People search for counter-examples by constructing alternative models (if possible). These alternative models represent different situations from the original. Once these alternative models are constructed, people can determine whether their conclusion is true for all of the models. If not, people can draw a new conclusion and test it with their models.

5 EXTENDED SYLLOGISMS 383 Finally, if there is no conclusion that is true for all of their models, they respond that there is no valid conclusion. According to mental model theory, syllogisms vary as to whether one, two, or three models can be constructed. The more models that can be constructed, the more difficult the syllogism. One-model syllogisms are the easiest because most people should be able to construct a single representation and draw a conclusion from it. Multiple-model syllogisms tend to be more difficult because people might not consider all possible models, there is more opportunity for error when dealing with more models, and because coordinating multiple models is very taxing for working memory (e.g., Copeland & Radvansky, 2004). Syllogistic figure effects The syllogistic figure effect (Johnson-Laird & Bara, 1984) is the finding that people prefer X-Z conclusions for syllogistic figure 1 (XY-YZ), and Z-X conclusions syllogistic figure 2 (YX-ZY). The explanation for this is that for syllogistic figure 1, people can construct a model of the first premise in the order X-Y. Then, the model for the second premise Y-Z can link onto the Y from the first model. When the integrated model is considered, people can interpret it in that order (i.e., X-Y-Z), which leads to an X-Z conclusion. Syllogistic figure 2 is similar to syllogistic figure 1, except that the model of the first premise, Y-X, gets linked to the end of the model for the second premise, Z-Y. For the symmetrical syllogistic figures, 3 (XY- ZY) and 4 (YX-YZ), there is a slight preference for X-Z conclusions. This is based on the idea of a first-in first-out principle (Johnson-Laird & Bara, 1984). To reduce the load on working memory, people interpret terms from the model in the same order in which they were constructed. The conclusion then uses the terms in this order. Mental model theory and extended syllogisms For mental model theory, people begin to solve syllogisms by constructing a mental representation of the first premise. Then, they expand their model by adding information from the second premise. For extended syllogisms it is assumed that people will simply expand their model a second time by adding the information from the third premise to their model. If there are additional premises, the model will continue to expand to include the new information. Formal rules Formal rule theories consider human reasoning to be based on an internal set of formal inference rules (Braine, 1978; Johnson-Laird, 1975; Osherson,

6 384 COPELAND 1976; Rips, 1983). Different versions of formal rule theories have existed over the years, and they consider reasoning to be a process of constructing mental proofs. These proofs manipulate propositions through the use of rules to reach a conclusion. This section focuses exclusively on Rips (1994) psychology of proof model, typically abbreviated as PSYCOP, because it accounts for the use of quantifiers, as in categorical reasoning. This model is designed to test, or verify, given conclusions. To do this, PSYCOP can use rules that work in a forward direction, backward direction, or both. When moving forward, the model uses rules to generate conclusions. Then it can compare these conclusions to the given conclusion. If this is not successful, then the model can work backward. When it moves in a backward direction, the model begins with the given conclusion and attempts to prove the premises. If a predetermined number of steps is reached by the model, or if no new conclusions are reached, then the model gives up, assuming that there is no valid conclusion. However, conclusions are not always provided with a set of premises. Many studies (e.g., Johnson-Laird & Bara, 1984) require people to generate their own conclusion. Rips outlined a procedure that people follow under these circumstances. The first step that people take is that they apply forward rules in an attempt to generate a conclusion. If this is successful, that is the response. However, if it is not successful, people will employ a strategy, referred to as a dominating heuristic, which is very similar to the matching heuristic (Gilhooly, Logie, Wetherick, & Wynn, 1993). The matching heuristic states that people prefer to use the most conservative quantifier from the premises in the conclusion. The quantifiers rank from most to least conservative, as follows: No, Some... not, Some, and All. Once a conclusion is created, people can try to use both forward and backward rules to verify it. If it is verified, it is the response. If it is not verified, then people can either stick with that conclusion, in the hope that there is some way in which it could be proven, or respond that there is no valid conclusion. Formal rules theory and extended syllogisms In terms of formal rules, research using a propositional reasoning task with multiple premises has suggested that people work through the task in stages (Braine et al., 1995; O Brien, Braine, & Yang, 1994). Braine and his colleagues had people write down inferences as they worked through propositional reasoning problems. The results showed that people not only reached a conclusion, but they were also drawing inferences as they progressed through the premises. That is, people would draw an inference from the first two premises, then they would use that inference, along with the third premise, to draw another inference. After all of the premises were used, the final inference was the conclusion. Thus, according to formal rules

7 EXTENDED SYLLOGISMS 385 theory, people only work with two premises, or one inference and a premise, at a time. While this assumption of serial processing is not a direct prediction of Rips (1994) PSYCOP model, it has been made for this study to allow for predictions in an extended syllogism task. Probability heuristics model The probability heuristics model (Chater & Oaksford, 1999) proposes that people do not reason logically, but instead rely on heuristics. According to this model, people progress through several stages. In the first stage, people use heuristics to generate a conclusion. After this is completed, people move to the second stage, where they test their conclusion. When presented with a syllogism, the first step is to quickly generate a conclusion. To accomplish this, people apply the min heuristic. This heuristic ranks the quantifiers from most to least informative: All, Some, No, and Some... not. The theory states that people prefer to use the least informative of the two quantifiers from the premises, because it is more likely to be true. The premise that is less informative is referred to as the min premise, while the other is the max premise. After the min heuristic is applied, people have the option of applying a second heuristic, called p-entailments, for probabilistic entailments. According to this heuristic, people draw a simple inference that is probably true, based on the initial conclusion. For example, if the initial conclusion was Some X are Z, it is probably true that Some X are not Z as well. Next, people use a third heuristic, attachment, to determine the order of the terms. This heuristic states that if the subject term (i.e., first position) in the min premise (i.e., less informative) is used in the conclusion, then the quantifier in the conclusion attaches to it. In other words, that term will also be the subject of the conclusion. If, however, this does not apply, then the other term (i.e., from the other premise) will be the subject of the conclusion. After a conclusion is generated, people can test, or reconsider the conclusion by using two more heuristics. The first is the max heuristic. According to this heuristic, people should vary as to how confident they are in their conclusion according to the informativeness of the premises. Specifically, the more informative the max premise, the more confidence there is in the conclusion. The less confident a person is, the more likely the person will respond that there is no valid conclusion. The second test heuristic, the o-heuristic (i.e., Some... not heuristic; term O from the A, I, E, O labelling), states that people should avoid conclusions with the quantifier Some... not, because that quantifier is so uninformative. Instead of using this quantifier in the conclusion, people will respond that there is no valid conclusion.

8 386 COPELAND Probability heuristics model and extended syllogisms Because all of these heuristics are only applicable to pairs of premises, it is assumed that they are applied in the same manner as with formal rules theory. That is, they are first applied to premise one and two, and then to the intermediate inference (from the first two premises) and the third premise, for a final conclusion. Formal rules theory and the probability heuristics model are similar in that rules and heuristics are applied to a propositional representation. EXTENDED SYLLOGISMS AND THEORIES OF SYLLOGISTIC REASONING To test predictions made by these theories, two experiments were conducted in which people were presented with three-premise extended syllogisms. In Experiment 1 the extended syllogisms were presented in a format similar to the syllogistic figure 1, and in Experiment 2 they were presented in different syllogistic figures. The specific predictions of each theory were tested by determining the percentage of accurately predicted responses. These values were then adjusted to compute weighted scores, which take into account the number of predicted responses made by each theory. The predictions were also tested by constructing parameterised-computational models (Batchelder & Riefer, 1999), an approach similar to that taken by Oaksford and Chater (1998) and Rips (1994). EXPERIMENT 1 People were presented with a set of 32 extended syllogisms. These syllogisms consisted of three premises and used the following quantifiers: All, Some, No, and Some... not. Nine of them had valid conclusions. All of the syllogisms used in Experiment 1 were presented in a format consistent with syllogistic figure 1: WX-XY-YZ. This is the same format as has been used in previous work with extended syllogisms. The purpose of Experiment 1 was to determine how well people solve extended syllogisms that use quantifiers other than All. In addition, Experiment 1 tested the predictions of three theories for these extended syllogisms. This was done by examining the percentage of responses that corresponded to the responses predicted by each theory. Also, multinomial processing tree model representations were constructed to inspect the response predictions more closely, as well as to examine the probability that certain procedures occur while solving a problem. This is an important test for the theories because it calculates the probability of each response for every extended syllogism, which can be compared with the actual percentages of responses.

9 EXTENDED SYLLOGISMS 387 The models were constructed by taking the steps that occur, according to each theory, and making them parameters in the model. Steps that always occur have parameter values equal to 1, and steps that are probabilistic have values between and For example, consider a three-model extended syllogism explained in terms of mental model theory. According to this theory, people always construct the first model (based on all of the premises). Then, they may or may not construct the second model (i.e., an alternative representation of the premises). If a second model was constructed, people may or may not construct the third model (i.e., another alternative representation of the premises). Finally, the person can provide a conclusion with a W-Z or Z-W order. For this example, the probability that someone responds with an W-Z conclusion from the second model is equal to: P(1 st model) * P(2 nd model) * (1 7 P(3 rd model)) * (P(W-Z)). An example, based on a specific extended syllogism, for each of the theories can be found in Appendix A. The next section examines the predictions made by mental model theory, formal rules theory, and the probability heuristics model. Predictions Mental model theory. According to mental model theory, people construct a mental model of a premise and then integrate additional information into that representation. The predictions for mental model theory were derived from the Syllog program (Johnson-Laird, 1992). The Syllog program assumes an initial interpretation of each of the quantifiers, and this forms the basis for the initial models that people construct. Because Syllog only constructs models for pairs of premises, an additional term, from the third premise, had to be added to models that Syllog originally constructed from the first two premises. For example, consider the following syllogism: Some W are X All X are Y No Y are Z According to Syllog, the following model would be constructed for the first two premises: WXY W XY Again, each line represents an occurrence of an individual (e.g., the second line represents a W that is not an X or Y ). When adding the third premise it is clear that every Y is not a Z, but it is unclear where a

10 388 COPELAND Z, or multiple Z s, can be placed. Thus, the following models are possible: WXYØZ W X Y ØZ W X Y ØZ W W Z W Z XYØZ X Y ØZ X Y ØZ Z Z The first model would predict a possible response of No W are Z or No Z are W. If the second model is considered, there could be a W that is a Z, but this is not certain. The only things that are definitively known are that Some W are not Z and Some Z are not W. Finally, the last model supports the conclusion Some W are not Z. There is a difference if considering the model in a backward direction. In this last model, there is no longer a Z that is not a W. This conflicts with the previous models. So, if someone was reading the model backwards, he or she might respond that there is no valid conclusion. In the above example there are three possible models that can be constructed. While it may be possible that people could construct the third model as their initial model, hence changing their initial conclusion, the Syllog program describes a specific ordering for model construction based on a basic interpretation of the quantifiers. Alternative (i.e., second and third) models, according to Syllog, are attempts to falsify the initial model and its resulting conclusion. The predictions for mental model theory in the current study, in an attempt to stay as true as possible to the original theory, are based on the ordering described in the Syllog Program. 1 For the parameterised computational model, some of the parameters, (i.e., the probability of constructing one, two, and three models) are dependent on each other. That is, the probability that someone constructs a third model can never be greater than the probability that someone constructs the second model. In order to build a third model, you must have already constructed the second one. The parameters for constructing models reflect this dependency: (1) The probability of constructing the first model. (2) The probability of constructing the second model, given that the first was constructed. (3) The probability of constructing the third model, given that the second was constructed. 1 The construction of mental models can be interpreted as being much more complex than the simple idea of constructing one versus two versus three models. However, the fleshing out of the specific aspects of model construction is beyond the scope of this paper. There is a parameterised computational version of mental model theory that is currently being developed which considers the processes involved with constructing mental models in detail (see Copeland & Radvansky, 2005).

11 EXTENDED SYLLOGISMS 389 It is important to note that this does not mean that it is always more likely that people only construct one model, as opposed to two models. For example, if the probabilities that someone constructs the first and second models are 1.00 and 0.60, respectively, then the probability that someone constructs two models would be 0.60 [i.e., P(1 st model) * P(2 nd model j 1 st model)] while the probability of only constructing one would be 0.40 [i.e., 1 7 (P(1 st model) * P(2 nd model j 1 st model))]. Thus, the probabilities of constructing one versus two models are not restricted, only the probabilities of constructing the first versus the second model. The same idea is true concerning a third model. Mental model theory predicts that there should be a high probability that people give W-Z conclusions. The reason is that the order of the terms in syllogistic figure 1 are easy to link up (i.e., W-X! X-Y! Y-Z) in the same order that they are presented. Because of this, the parameter for conclusion direction is restricted to values at or above Formal rules. The predictions of formal rules theory are based on the rules that people have available to use. However, as Rips (1994) points out, and as later emphasised by Johnson-Laird (1997), individuals can differ in the rules that they possess. Because the current study is not investigating individual differences, a standard set of predictions is tested. Rips (1994) specifies that for any pair of premises, the responses should consist of (a) conclusions that follow from the application of forward rules, (b) conclusions that use the dominant quantifier from the premises, when guessing or using backward rules, (c) no valid conclusion, and (d) a small number of correct conclusions with nondominant quantifiers, based on backward processing by the persistent subjects (p. 247). In a footnote (p. 409), Rips explains that conclusions that result from the application of forward rules use the dominant quantifier from the premises. Because the dominant quantifier is not always the correct conclusion, and there is a possibility that people are persistent, there are always three, and sometimes four, conclusions predicted for every pair of premises: (1) The dominant quantifier in a forward direction (i.e., X-Z). (2) The dominant quantifier in a backward direction (i.e., Z-X). (3) No valid conclusion. (4) The correct conclusion when it differs from the dominant quantifier. Here, it is assumed that people draw an intermediate, or temporary, conclusion from the first two premises. Then, that conclusion is used as a premise, along with the third real premise to draw a final conclusion. Thus, it is possible for there to be more than four predicted conclusions for

12 390 COPELAND an extended syllogism. This is because three or four temporary conclusions are possible for the first two premises, and then each one of those is matched with the third premise. For PSYCOP, the probability of successfully using forward rules, if applicable, should be high. This set of rules is simple and the parameter value for it was fairly high in a study conducted by Schank and Rips (as reported in Rips, 1994). The probability of successfully using backward rules is expected to be lower. There are more of them and they are more complex than forward rules. Rips (1994) explained that approximately 32% of subjects from Johnson-Laird and Bara s (1984) study produced conclusions that would have been obtained by using backward rules. In the parameterised computational model, the value for using forward rules is set at or higher, which makes it unnecessary to restrict the parameter for backward rules. The probability that someone would be persistent that is, prove a conclusion was true even though that conclusion would not have been initially proposed as a tentative conclusion should be very low, so this parameter is restricted to a value less than In addition to using rules to solve syllogisms, PSYCOP states that people might guess. In the study conducted by Schank and Rips (as reported in Rips, 1994), the probability of guessing was quite low, ranging from 8% for guessing All and No to 31% for guessing Some and Some... not. One reason why these values were so low is that people were warned that most categorical syllogisms have no valid conclusion. This probably reduced the likelihood that people would guess. Because the current study does not warn people about the number of extended syllogisms with no valid conclusion, people might be more likely to guess. Thus, the parameter values for guessing are only restricted in that the values for guessing All and No must be smaller than the values for guessing Some and Some... not. There are two additional parameters that are listed, but do not vary. The first refers to producing a tentative conclusion to test. It is assumed that this always occurs because the experiments in this study do not use a verification task. The second is labelled NVC Reverse. This parameter refers to situations in which a person encounters no valid conclusion when considering the terms in one direction (e.g., A-D). When this occurs, it is assumed that people then try the reverse ordering (e.g., D-A). Probability heuristics model. The predictions for the probability heuristics model were derived by first applying the heuristic rules to the first two premises. This led to four different conclusions, two obtained by using the min heuristic and the others by also applying the p-entailment heuristic (the ordering of the terms in each conclusion depends on whether the attachment heuristic is applied). Then, separately, these four conclusions

13 EXTENDED SYLLOGISMS 391 were used as a premise along with the third premise to draw final conclusions. To illustrate these steps, consider the following extended syllogism: Some W are X All X are Y No Y are Z If the min heuristic were applied to the first two premises, the conclusions would be Some W are Y (attachment heuristic is applied) and Some Y are W (attachment is not applied). If the p-entailment heuristics were applied to the first two premises, the conclusions would be Some W are Y (attachment) and Some W are not Y (no attachment). Before continuing to the third premise, it is possible that people might not be confident with their temporary conclusion if they apply the max heuristic or the o-heuristic. If so, people would decide that there was no valid conclusion and stop. However, if people are confident in their temporary conclusion then they can continue to the step of pairing the temporary conclusion with the third premise, as shown below: Some W are Y Some Y are W Some W are not Y Some Y are not W No Y are Z No Y are Z No Y are Z No Y are Z Again, the min and p-entailment heuristics can be applied. For the first pair of premises, the conclusions are No W are Z, No Z are W, Some W are not Z, and Some Z are not W. For the second pair, the conclusions are the same as for the first pair. For the third pair, the conclusions are Some W are not Z, Some Z are not W, Some W are Z, and Some Z are W, and for the fourth pair, Some Z are not W, Some W are not Z, Some Z are W, and Some W are Z. Therefore, based on the application of the min and p-entailment heuristics, there are six possible conclusions: Some W are Z, Some Z are W, No W are Z, No Z are W, Some W are not Z, and Some Z are not W. In addition, the response of no valid conclusion is always possible, because it depends on a person s confidence in their response. Thus, the probability heuristics model predicts seven possible responses to this extended syllogism. For the probability heuristics model, the probability of applying the min heuristic is set at 1.000, meaning that it is always applied. The probability heuristics model does not specify any differences in probability for the probabilistic entailments (e.g., All! Some), but it does state that it is the next most preferred conclusion after the min conclusion. This suggests that the parameter values for the probabilistic entailments should be less than The value for the attachment heuristic is allowed to vary.

14 392 COPELAND The max heuristic states that a person should be confident in the generated conclusion in proportion to the informativeness of the most informative premise (i.e., the max premise). Thus, it is expected that people are the most confident for the max quantifiers in the following order: All! NVC, Some! NVC, No! NVC, Some... not! NVC. For the current study, the parameter values were restricted so that the values observed this order (except for a small addition discussed in the next paragraph). Finally, the o-heuristic states that people should avoid producing or accepting Some... not conclusions because they are so uninformative. This means that most of the time, people should respond that there is no valid conclusion rather than using the quantifier Some... not. Because this heuristic is very similar to the one for Some... not! NVC discussed in the previous paragraph, the ordering in the previous paragraph included the addition of value of the o-heuristic to the Some... not! NVC heuristic. Method Participants. A total of 47 undergraduates from the University of Notre Dame participated in exchange for class credit. The only restriction was that participants must not have taken a course in logic. The data from two participants were excluded for having multiple response times less than 1 second (13 trials for the first and 3 trials for the second), leaving a total of 45 participants. Materials and procedure. A set of 32 extended categorical syllogisms was used in Experiment 1 (see Appendix B). These extended syllogisms were selected based on three ideas. First, it was attempted to represent all of the quantifiers. Second, there should be a low percentage of valid extended syllogisms. Finally, all extended syllogisms were based on syllogistic figure 1 because this is what has traditionally been used in studies examining extended syllogisms. The terms used in each syllogism were based on occupations, hobbies, or interests (e.g., joggers, cyclists, coffee drinkers, etc.). These terms were randomly assigned to each syllogism for each participant. An example of a possible syllogism is: All joggers are students All students are coffee drinkers No coffee drinkers are smokers In addition, people were instructed that each extended syllogism was referring to a room full of 100 people who were randomly selected. This method was used to ensure that each of the situations that were described was plausible to the reader.

15 EXTENDED SYLLOGISMS 393 Before the task, it was explained what an extended syllogism was, and people were instructed to select a conclusion that was definitely true, not simply possible. The premises of each syllogism were presented on the computer screen along with nine possible conclusions. Eight of the choices were created by making two choices of each form (i.e., A, E, I, and O); one with the subject term first and one with the reference term first (e.g., All chefs are bikers, and All bikers are chefs). The ninth choice was No valid conclusion. The premises and the choices were presented on the screen together and people had an unlimited amount of time to select their response. The choices were always presented in the same order. Results Overall, people were able to solve extended syllogisms (M ¼ 39%, SD ¼ 17) at a level comparable to performance for traditional syllogisms in other studies (e.g., M ¼ 43%, SD ¼ 10 for Copeland & Radvansky, 2004). In Experiment 1, the numbers of responses that corresponded to each theory were calculated (see Table 1). However, because there are differences between the theories in the number of predicted responses for each extended syllogism, weighted scores were calculated for each of the theories (see Table 2). This was done because a theory is more likely to predict a response accurately if it makes more predictions than another theory. Weighted scores were calculated using the following formula (note: if a prediction is incorrect, that particular syllogism contributes zero to the total weighted score): weighted score ¼ S (1 7 (# of predicted responses for an extended syllogism/9)). For example, if a theory made 5 predictions for a particular extended syllogism and successfully predicted a response for it, then 4/9 (i.e., 1 7 (5/9)) would be added to the weighted score for that theory for that person. The probability heuristics model had a weighted score smaller than both mental model theory, t(44) ¼ 13.31, p 5.001, and PSYCOP, t(44) ¼ 11.35, p 5.001, which did not differ from one another, t 5 1. TABLE 1 The percentage of responses that corresponded to the predictions made by mental model theory, PSYCOP, and the probability heuristics model in Experiments 1 and 2 (standard deviations are in parentheses) Experiment 1 Experiment 2 Overall Overall Syl Fig 1 Syl Fig 2 Syl Fig 3 Syl Fig 4 MMT 80% (13) 88% (10) 91% (12) 87% (14) 87% (14) 88% (13) PSYCOP 75% (13) 88% (10) 87% (13) 87% (12) 87% (14) 89% (14) PHM 97% (3) 98% (4) 98% (5) 98% (5) 97% (9) 97% (6)

16 394 COPELAND TABLE 2 Weighted scores for mental model theory, PSYCOP, and the probability heuristics model in Experiments 1 and 2 (standard deviations are in parentheses) Experiment 1 Experiment 2 Overall Overall Syl Fig 1 Syl Fig 2 Syl Fig 3 Syl Fig 4 MMT 14.4 (2.3) 15.2 (1.8) 4.0 (0.5) 3.7 (0.6) 3.6 (0.6) 3.9 (0.6) PSYCOP 14.3 (2.6) 16.4 (1.8) 4.2 (0.6) 4.0 (0.6) 4.3 (0.7) 3.9 (0.6) PHM 9.9 (0.4) 9.5 (0.5) 2.4 (0.1) 2.4 (0.2) 2.3 (0.3) 2.3 (0.2) Parameterised computational models. The third way in which the predictions were compared was by constructing a parameterised computational model for each theory. Each model was constructed using the proportions of responses from all participants (i.e., models were not created for each person). Parameters were fixed, allowed to vary from to 0.999, or restricted to a more specific range as discussed earlier. For each theory, a parameter only had one value (e.g., for the probability heuristics model, the parameter value for Attachment was the same for each extended syllogism). Comparisons of the parameterised computational models were made using a corrected version (for smaller samples) of Akaike s Information Criterion (AIC C ; Akaike, 1974; Hurvich & Tsai, 1989) as described by Burnham and Anderson (2004): AIC C ¼ 2lnLþ 2v þ½ð2vðv þ 1ÞÞ=ðn v 1ÞŠ where L is the model s best likelihood and v represents the number of estimated parameters. The formula for the model s best likelihood is given below: lnðlþ ¼S f ij ln½pðr j js i ÞŠ where f ij is the observed frequency where the response, R j, was given when a particular stimulus, S i, was presented (as described by Thomas, 2001). The AIC C score is useful because it determines the best fit while also taking into account the number of parameters used in a model. A lower AIC C score indicates a better fit. The parameters for each model were estimated by using the Solver Program in Microsoft Excel. The computed AIC C for the probability heuristics model (AIC C ¼ ) was smaller than for mental model theory (AIC C ¼ ), which was smaller than for PSYCOP (AIC C ¼ ). The probability heuristics model had the best fit even when considering the number of parameters.

17 EXTENDED SYLLOGISMS 395 In addition to the AIC C scores, there were some parameters (see Tables 3, 4, and 5) that were different from those reported in past studies (Rips, 1994). 2 These were the guessing parameters in PSYCOP. In this experiment, the values were much higher than those described by Rips (1994). These higher values may be a result of the fact that people were not warned that most problems had no valid conclusion and so were more likely to guess. Discussion While the probability heuristics model predicted a larger percentage of responses, the weighted scores suggested that mental model theory and PSYCOP did a better job than the probability heuristics model. Specifically, it seemed as if the probability heuristics model was simply benefiting from predicting a large number of responses relative to the other two theories. However, the parameterised computational models showed that the probability heuristics model, while making a large number of predictions, is able to do a good job of accounting for the probability of each predicted response. Thus, based on the modelling results, the probability heuristics model outperformed mental model theory and PSYCOP in Experiment 1. However, it should be noted that only syllogistic figure 1 extended syllogisms were tested in Experiment 1. The aim of Experiment 2 was to go beyond this. EXPERIMENT 2 People were presented with a set of 36 extended syllogisms. These syllogisms consisted of the nine valid syllogisms from Experiment 1 and their corresponding syllogisms in syllogistic figures 2, 3, and 4. Below are examples of an extended syllogism from each: (1) All W are X (2) All X are W (3) All W are X (4) All X are W All X are Y All Y are X All Y are X All X are Y All Y are Z All Y are Z All Y are Z All Y are Z The purpose of this experiment was to examine whether manipulating the order of the terms affected performance. As in Experiment 1, predictions of mental model theory, formal rules theory, and the probability heuristics model were tested. 2 Some people may find it confusing that for mental model theory, the P(3 rd model j 2 nd model) was larger than the P(2 nd model j 1 st model). However, as explained earlier, these are conditional probabilities, not simply the probabilities of constructing a third versus a second model. The actual probability of constructing a third model is equal to P(1 st model) * P(2 nd model j 1 st model) * P(3 rd model j 2 nd model).

18 396 COPELAND For the parameterised computational models, the only change from Experiment 1 is that here mental model theory has an additional parameter. Specifically, mental model theory predicts that people should have a slight preference for W-Z over Z-W conclusions in syllogistic figures 3 and 4, according to the principle of first-in, first-out (Johnson-Laird & Bara, 1984). Method Participants. A total of 54 undergraduates from the University of Notre Dame participated in exchange for class credit. They had not taken a course in logic and did not participate in Experiment 1. The data from one participant were lost due to a computer error, leaving a total of 53 participants. Materials and procedure. The extended syllogisms used in Experiment 2 are listed in Appendix B. The same procedure that was used in Experiment 1 was used here. Results and discussion The data from Experiment 2 were analysed in the same manner as in Experiment 1. Overall, people reached the correct conclusion 35% of the time (SD ¼ 17). They were more accurate for extended syllogisms in syllogistic figure 1 (M ¼ 44%, SD ¼ 17) than 2 (M ¼ 29%, SD ¼ 21), t(52) ¼ 5.30, p 5.001, 3 (M ¼ 33%, SD ¼ 24), t(52) ¼ 3.56, p 5.01, and 4 (M ¼ 34%, SD ¼ 23), t(52) ¼ 3.53, p Performance for syllogistic figure 4 was better than 2, t(52) ¼ 2.18, p 5.05, and there were no differences between 3 and 4, t 5 1, and 2 and 3, t(52) ¼ 1.53, p ¼.13. An important factor that might have influenced these patterns is that the syllogistic figures had 0, 5, 5, and 3 invalid extended syllogisms, respectively. Thus, people were most accurate for those syllogistic figures (i.e., 1 and 4) with the fewest extended syllogisms that required a response of No valid conclusion. This is consistent with studies examining traditional syllogisms (e.g., Copeland & Radvansky, 2004). That is, people have a tendency to respond with No valid conclusion less often than they should. Overall, the weighted score for PSYCOP was larger than for mental model theory, t(52) ¼ 8.45, p 5.001, and both were significantly larger than the probability heuristics model, t(52) ¼ 34.65, p 5.001, and t(52) ¼ 27.73, p 5.001, respectively (see Table 2). For syllogistic figure 1, PSYCOP had a weighted score that was larger than mental model theory, t(52) ¼ 2.70, p 5.01, and both were larger than the probability heuristics model, t(52) ¼ 22.07, p 5.001, and t(52) ¼ 25.30, p For syllogistic figure 2, PSYCOP had a larger weighted score than mental model theory,

19 EXTENDED SYLLOGISMS 397 t(52) ¼ 4.64, p 5.001, which had a larger weighted score than the probability heuristics model, t(52) ¼ 16.80, p For syllogistic figure 3, PSYCOP had a larger weighted score than mental model theory, t(52) ¼ 10.88, p 5.001, which had a larger weighted score than the probability heuristics model, t(52) ¼ 18.08, p Finally, for syllogistic figure 4, both PSYCOP and mental model theory, which did not differ, t(52) ¼ 1.00, p ¼.32, had larger weighted scores than the probability heuristics model, t(52) ¼ 22.63, p 5.001, and t(52) ¼ 22.99, p 5.001, respectively. Both mental model theory and PSYCOP did a good job of predicting responses to extended syllogisms when correcting for the number of predictions made by each theory. These results are somewhat similar to those observed in Experiment 1, where PSYCOP and mental model theory did not differ, but both did better than the probability heuristics model. To further test these theories, parameterised computational models of each theory were examined. Parameterised computational models. Listings of the parameters for each theory are in Tables 3, 4, and 5. As can be seen, these parameter values are similar to those observed in Experiment 1. The AIC C score for the probability heuristics model (AIC C ¼ ) was the smallest, indicating a better fit than mental model theory (AIC C ¼ ) and PSYCOP (AIC C ¼ ). This is the same pattern as in Experiment 1. However, all of these AIC C values were larger than those from Experiment 1, especially for the probability heuristics model. This suggests that all of the theories had more difficulty accounting for performance when more than one syllogistic figure was used. In both Experiments 1 and 2, the probability heuristics model had the best fit. However, at this point it is unclear why it did better. Thus, it is important to examine the theory predictions and the data more closely. The first, and most important, problem that both mental model theory TABLE 3 Parameter values for mental model theory from Experiments 1 and 2 Experiment 1 Experiment 2 Model Construction P(1 st model) P(2 nd model j 1 st model) P(3 rd model j 2 nd model) Model Evaluation P(W-Z order) Syl Fig Syl Figs 2, 3, & 4 n/a 0.598

20 398 COPELAND TABLE 4 Parameter values for PSYCOP from Experiments 1 and 2 Experiment 1 Experiment 2 Production P(Forward Rules) P(Tentative conclusion) P(W-Z order) P(NVC Reverse) Verify/Proof P(Backward Rules) P(Persistent) No Proof P(Guess All) P(Guess Some) P(Guess No) P(Guess Some... not) (Experiment 1: M ¼ 4.2, SD ¼ 1.0; Experiment 2: M ¼ 4.6, SD ¼ 0.8) and PSYCOP (Experiment 1: M ¼ 3.6, SD ¼ 0.8; Experiment 2: M ¼ 4.3, SD ¼ 0.7) have is that they do not make as many predictions for each syllogism as the probability heuristics model (Experiment 1: M ¼ 6.1, SD ¼ 1.0; Experiment 2: M ¼ 6.6, SD ¼ 0.8). In Experiments 1 and 2, there was a mean number of 6.69 (SD ¼ 0.93) and 7.72 (SD ¼ 0.88) different responses given per extended syllogism (there are nine possible responses for each). Thus, for each theory to adequately predict performance, they need to predict a wide variety of responses. Mental model theory and PSYCOP clearly did not do as well in this regard compared to the probability heuristics model. In Experiment 1 there were additional problems with mental model theory and PSYCOP. One problem was the lack of a specific prediction for these theories. A closer examination of Experiment 1 shows that there is a consistent pattern of predictions made only by the probability heuristics model. When the quantifier Some...not was in at least one premise (11 of 32 extended syllogisms), the probability heuristics model consistently predicted a response using the quantifier Some. Mental model theory and PSYCOP never made this prediction. For these 11 extended syllogisms, the predicted Some response was made by people almost a quarter of the time (M ¼ 22.6%, SD ¼ 13.3). Again, for these extended syllogisms, only one of the theories predicted a response that was frequently made. Both mental model theory and PSYCOP have a major flaw in that they fail to make this particular prediction involving Some...not. In defence of mental model theory and PSYCOP, a somewhat simple explanation for these results can be proposed. It is possible, and very likely

The Effect of response format on syllogistic reasoning

The Effect of response format on syllogistic reasoning Calvert Undergraduate Research Awards University Libraries Lance and Elena Calvert Award for Undergraduate Research 2011 The Effect of response format on syllogistic reasoning Adam S. Billman University

More information

An Inspection-Time Analysis of Figural Effects and Processing Direction in Syllogistic Reasoning

An Inspection-Time Analysis of Figural Effects and Processing Direction in Syllogistic Reasoning An Inspection-Time Analysis of Figural Effects and Processing Direction in Syllogistic Reasoning Edward J. N. Stupple (E.J.N.Stupple@derby.ac.uk) Department of Psychology, University of Derby Derby, DE3

More information

Negations in syllogistic reasoning: Evidence for a heuristic analytic conflict

Negations in syllogistic reasoning: Evidence for a heuristic analytic conflict Negations in syllogistic reasoning: Evidence for a heuristic analytic conflict Item type Article Authors Stupple, Edward J. N.; Waterhouse, Eleanor F. Citation Stupple, Edward J. N., Waterhouse, Eleanor

More information

Multinomial Processing Models for Syllogistic Reasoning: A Comparison

Multinomial Processing Models for Syllogistic Reasoning: A Comparison Multinomial Processing Models for Syllogistic Reasoning: A omparison Hannah Dames (damesh@cs.uni-freiburg.de), Jan Ole von Hartz (hartzj@cs.uni-freiburg.de), Mario Kantz (mario.kantz@mars.uni-freiburg.de),

More information

Necessity, possibility and belief: A study of syllogistic reasoning

Necessity, possibility and belief: A study of syllogistic reasoning THE QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF EXPERIMENTAL PSYCHOLOGY, 2001, 54A (3), 935 958 Necessity, possibility and belief: A study of syllogistic reasoning Jonathan St. B.T. Evans, Simon J. Handley, and Catherine N.J.

More information

Content and Strategy in Syllogistic Reasoning

Content and Strategy in Syllogistic Reasoning Content and Strategy in Syllogistic Reasoning Hipólito Marrero and Elena Gámez Departamento de Psicología Cognitiva, Social y Organizacional Universidad de La Laguna Abstract Syllogistic reasoning has

More information

Negations Without Not : Alternative forms of Negation and Contrast Classes in Conditional Inference. James Richard Hazlett Vance

Negations Without Not : Alternative forms of Negation and Contrast Classes in Conditional Inference. James Richard Hazlett Vance Negations Without Not : Alternative forms of Negation and Contrast Classes in Conditional Inference James Richard Hazlett Vance Doctor of Philosophy Birkbeck, University of London 2018 1 Declaration I

More information

Chapter 02 Developing and Evaluating Theories of Behavior

Chapter 02 Developing and Evaluating Theories of Behavior Chapter 02 Developing and Evaluating Theories of Behavior Multiple Choice Questions 1. A theory is a(n): A. plausible or scientifically acceptable, well-substantiated explanation of some aspect of the

More information

Evaluative feedback can improve deductive reasoning

Evaluative feedback can improve deductive reasoning Evaluative feedback can improve deductive reasoning Sangeet Khemlani 1 and Adam Moore 2 {skhemlani, adam.moore457}@gmail.com 1 Naval Center for Applied Research in Artificial Intelligence, Naval Research

More information

Is inferential reasoning just probabilistic reasoning in disguise?

Is inferential reasoning just probabilistic reasoning in disguise? Memory & Cognition 2005, 33 (7), 1315-1323 Is inferential reasoning just probabilistic reasoning in disguise? HENRY MARKOVITS and SIMON HANDLEY University of Plymouth, Plymouth, England Oaksford, Chater,

More information

Audio: In this lecture we are going to address psychology as a science. Slide #2

Audio: In this lecture we are going to address psychology as a science. Slide #2 Psychology 312: Lecture 2 Psychology as a Science Slide #1 Psychology As A Science In this lecture we are going to address psychology as a science. Slide #2 Outline Psychology is an empirical science.

More information

The shallow processing of logical negation

The shallow processing of logical negation Psychology and Behavioral Sciences 2013; 2(5): 196-201 Published online November 20, 2013 (http://www.sciencepublishinggroup.com/j/pbs) doi: 10.11648/j.pbs.20130205.15 The shallow processing of logical

More information

Wason's Cards: What is Wrong?

Wason's Cards: What is Wrong? Wason's Cards: What is Wrong? Pei Wang Computer and Information Sciences, Temple University This paper proposes a new interpretation

More information

Student Performance Q&A:

Student Performance Q&A: Student Performance Q&A: 2009 AP Statistics Free-Response Questions The following comments on the 2009 free-response questions for AP Statistics were written by the Chief Reader, Christine Franklin of

More information

PREDICTORS OF DEDUCTIVE REASONING IN PRIMARY SCHOOL CHILDREN

PREDICTORS OF DEDUCTIVE REASONING IN PRIMARY SCHOOL CHILDREN Journal of Psychological and Educational Research JPER - 2014, 22 (2), November, 45-60 PREDICTORS OF DEDUCTIVE REASONING IN PRIMARY SCHOOL CHILDREN Denisa Ardelean University of Oradea, Romania Abstract

More information

Lec 02: Estimation & Hypothesis Testing in Animal Ecology

Lec 02: Estimation & Hypothesis Testing in Animal Ecology Lec 02: Estimation & Hypothesis Testing in Animal Ecology Parameter Estimation from Samples Samples We typically observe systems incompletely, i.e., we sample according to a designed protocol. We then

More information

Does everyone love everyone? The psychology of iterative reasoning

Does everyone love everyone? The psychology of iterative reasoning THINKING & REASONING, 2004, 10 (1), 31 53 Does everyone love everyone? The psychology of iterative reasoning Paolo Cherubini Universita` di Milano-Bicocca, Italy P. N. Johnson-Laird Princeton University,

More information

At least one problem with some formal reasoning paradigms

At least one problem with some formal reasoning paradigms Memory & Cognition 2008, 36 (1), 217-229 doi: 10.3758/MC.36.1.217 At least one problem with some formal reasoning paradigms JAMES R. SCHMIDT University of Waterloo, Waterloo, Ontario, Canada AND VALERIE

More information

6. A theory that has been substantially verified is sometimes called a a. law. b. model.

6. A theory that has been substantially verified is sometimes called a a. law. b. model. Chapter 2 Multiple Choice Questions 1. A theory is a(n) a. a plausible or scientifically acceptable, well-substantiated explanation of some aspect of the natural world. b. a well-substantiated explanation

More information

Writing Reaction Papers Using the QuALMRI Framework

Writing Reaction Papers Using the QuALMRI Framework Writing Reaction Papers Using the QuALMRI Framework Modified from Organizing Scientific Thinking Using the QuALMRI Framework Written by Kevin Ochsner and modified by others. Based on a scheme devised by

More information

Inferences: What inferences about the hypotheses and questions can be made based on the results?

Inferences: What inferences about the hypotheses and questions can be made based on the results? QALMRI INSTRUCTIONS QALMRI is an acronym that stands for: Question: (a) What was the broad question being asked by this research project? (b) What was the specific question being asked by this research

More information

Content Effects in Conditional Reasoning: Evaluating the Container Schema

Content Effects in Conditional Reasoning: Evaluating the Container Schema Effects in Conditional Reasoning: Evaluating the Container Schema Amber N. Bloomfield (a-bloomfield@northwestern.edu) Department of Psychology, 2029 Sheridan Road Evanston, IL 60208 USA Lance J. Rips (rips@northwestern.edu)

More information

The Logic of Data Analysis Using Statistical Techniques M. E. Swisher, 2016

The Logic of Data Analysis Using Statistical Techniques M. E. Swisher, 2016 The Logic of Data Analysis Using Statistical Techniques M. E. Swisher, 2016 This course does not cover how to perform statistical tests on SPSS or any other computer program. There are several courses

More information

Does pure water boil, when it s heated to 100 C? : The Associative Strength of Disabling Conditions in Conditional Reasoning

Does pure water boil, when it s heated to 100 C? : The Associative Strength of Disabling Conditions in Conditional Reasoning Does pure water boil, when it s heated to 100 C? : The Associative Strength of Disabling Conditions in Conditional Reasoning Wim De Neys (Wim.Deneys@psy.kuleuven.ac.be) Department of Psychology, K.U.Leuven,

More information

Chapter 2. Knowledge Representation: Reasoning, Issues, and Acquisition. Teaching Notes

Chapter 2. Knowledge Representation: Reasoning, Issues, and Acquisition. Teaching Notes Chapter 2 Knowledge Representation: Reasoning, Issues, and Acquisition Teaching Notes This chapter explains how knowledge is represented in artificial intelligence. The topic may be launched by introducing

More information

Presentation format and syllogistic reasoning

Presentation format and syllogistic reasoning Psicológica (2013), 34, 313-326. Presentation format and syllogistic reasoning Orlando Espino * and Carlos Santamaría Universidad de La Laguna (Spain) Figural effect is a response bias that depends on

More information

Chapter 11. Experimental Design: One-Way Independent Samples Design

Chapter 11. Experimental Design: One-Way Independent Samples Design 11-1 Chapter 11. Experimental Design: One-Way Independent Samples Design Advantages and Limitations Comparing Two Groups Comparing t Test to ANOVA Independent Samples t Test Independent Samples ANOVA Comparing

More information

Knowledge is rarely absolutely certain. In expert systems we need a way to say that something is probably but not necessarily true.

Knowledge is rarely absolutely certain. In expert systems we need a way to say that something is probably but not necessarily true. CmSc310 Artificial Intelligence Expert Systems II 1. Reasoning under uncertainty Knowledge is rarely absolutely certain. In expert systems we need a way to say that something is probably but not necessarily

More information

J. St.B.T. Evans a, S. E. Newstead a, J. L. Allen b & P. Pollard c a Department of Psychology, University of Plymouth, Plymouth, UK

J. St.B.T. Evans a, S. E. Newstead a, J. L. Allen b & P. Pollard c a Department of Psychology, University of Plymouth, Plymouth, UK This article was downloaded by: [New York University] On: 27 April 2015, At: 14:56 Publisher: Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer

More information

The effect of premise order in conditional reasoning: a test of the mental model theory

The effect of premise order in conditional reasoning: a test of the mental model theory Cognition 63 (1997) 1 28 The effect of premise order in conditional reasoning: a test of the mental model theory Vittorio Girotto *, Alberto Mazzocco, Alessandra Tasso a, b b a CREPCO CNRS and University

More information

Problem representations and illusions in reasoning

Problem representations and illusions in reasoning CogSci99 3 Problem representations and illusions in reasoning Vladimir M. Sloutsky (sloutsky.@osu.edu) Center for Cognitive Science & School of Teaching & Learning; 945 N. High Street Columbus, OH 430,

More information

The Scientific Method

The Scientific Method The Scientific Method Objectives 1. To understand the central role of hypothesis testing in the modern scientific process. 2. To design and conduct an experiment using the scientific method. 3. To learn

More information

EXPERIMENTAL DESIGN Page 1 of 11. relationships between certain events in the environment and the occurrence of particular

EXPERIMENTAL DESIGN Page 1 of 11. relationships between certain events in the environment and the occurrence of particular EXPERIMENTAL DESIGN Page 1 of 11 I. Introduction to Experimentation 1. The experiment is the primary means by which we are able to establish cause-effect relationships between certain events in the environment

More information

Quality Management Guideline for Suppliers. Appendix. Instructions for the Preparation of 8D-Reports

Quality Management Guideline for Suppliers. Appendix. Instructions for the Preparation of 8D-Reports Version A Page 1 from 9 Quality Management Guideline for Suppliers Appendix Instructions for the Preparation of 8D-Reports Originator Approval Area Central QC Central QC Name Schuchardt Kaldeberg Date

More information

Chapter 2. Behavioral Variability and Research

Chapter 2. Behavioral Variability and Research Chapter 2 Behavioral Variability and Research Chapter Outline Variability and the Research Process Variance: An Index of Variability Systematic and Error Variance Effect Size: Assessing the Strength of

More information

The Belief Bias Effect Is Aptly Named: A Reply to Klauer and Kellen (2011)

The Belief Bias Effect Is Aptly Named: A Reply to Klauer and Kellen (2011) Psychological Review 2011 American Psychological Association 2011, Vol. 118, No. 1, 155 163 0033-295X/11/$12.00 DOI: 10.1037/a0021774 COMMENT The Belief Bias Effect Is Aptly Named: A Reply to Klauer and

More information

Analogical Inference

Analogical Inference Analogical Inference An Investigation of the Functioning of the Hippocampus in Relational Learning Using fmri William Gross Anthony Greene Today I am going to talk to you about a new task we designed to

More information

How to eliminate illusions in quantified reasoning

How to eliminate illusions in quantified reasoning Memory & Cognition 2000, 28 (6), 1050-1059 How to eliminate illusions in quantified reasoning YINGRUI YANG and P. N. JOHNSON-LAIRD Princeton University, Princeton, New Jersey The mental model theory postulates

More information

Chapter 1. Research : A way of thinking

Chapter 1. Research : A way of thinking Chapter 1 Research : A way of thinking Research is undertaken within most professions. More than a set of skills, research is a way of thinking: examining critically the various aspects of your day-to-day

More information

Running head: How large denominators are leading to large errors 1

Running head: How large denominators are leading to large errors 1 Running head: How large denominators are leading to large errors 1 How large denominators are leading to large errors Nathan Thomas Kent State University How large denominators are leading to large errors

More information

Chapter 1. Research : A way of thinking

Chapter 1. Research : A way of thinking Chapter 1 Research : A way of thinking Research is undertaken within most professions. More than a set of skills, research is a way of thinking: examining critically the various aspects of your day-to-day

More information

Hypothesis-Driven Research

Hypothesis-Driven Research Hypothesis-Driven Research Research types Descriptive science: observe, describe and categorize the facts Discovery science: measure variables to decide general patterns based on inductive reasoning Hypothesis-driven

More information

Guidelines for Incorporating & Strengthening Perspective-Taking & Self-Authorship into Division of Student Life Programs

Guidelines for Incorporating & Strengthening Perspective-Taking & Self-Authorship into Division of Student Life Programs Guidelines for Incorporating & Strengthening Perspective-Taking & Self-Authorship into Division of Student Life Programs Your program or service has been identified as potentially high impact in helping

More information

BIOLOGY 1408 What is Biology?

BIOLOGY 1408 What is Biology? BIOLOGY 1408 Lecture 2 Chris Doumen, Ph.D. Collin College, 2014 What is Biology? The scientific study of life Contains two important elements Scientific study Life 1 The Process Of Science The word science

More information

AN ANALYSIS or mmcumes m ABSTRACT SYLLOGESTEC gamma. Eiissertafioa éor Em fiegree 6? Pk. B MECRIGAN SMTE WVERSETY _ FRED HELSABECK, JR.

AN ANALYSIS or mmcumes m ABSTRACT SYLLOGESTEC gamma. Eiissertafioa éor Em fiegree 6? Pk. B MECRIGAN SMTE WVERSETY _ FRED HELSABECK, JR. AN ANALYSIS or mmcumes m ABSTRACT SYLLOGESTEC gamma Eiissertafioa éor Em fiegree 6? Pk. B MECRIGAN SMTE WVERSETY _ FRED HELSABECK, JR. W73 5' II n 1? HUM;! SUN? 80W. BINUERY lnc. u RARV amocns "'RI. 15552933.!.

More information

MULTIPLE LINEAR REGRESSION 24.1 INTRODUCTION AND OBJECTIVES OBJECTIVES

MULTIPLE LINEAR REGRESSION 24.1 INTRODUCTION AND OBJECTIVES OBJECTIVES 24 MULTIPLE LINEAR REGRESSION 24.1 INTRODUCTION AND OBJECTIVES In the previous chapter, simple linear regression was used when you have one independent variable and one dependent variable. This chapter

More information

Why Does Similarity Correlate With Inductive Strength?

Why Does Similarity Correlate With Inductive Strength? Why Does Similarity Correlate With Inductive Strength? Uri Hasson (uhasson@princeton.edu) Psychology Department, Princeton University Princeton, NJ 08540 USA Geoffrey P. Goodwin (ggoodwin@princeton.edu)

More information

EPSE 594: Meta-Analysis: Quantitative Research Synthesis

EPSE 594: Meta-Analysis: Quantitative Research Synthesis EPSE 594: Meta-Analysis: Quantitative Research Synthesis Ed Kroc University of British Columbia ed.kroc@ubc.ca March 14, 2019 Ed Kroc (UBC) EPSE 594 March 14, 2019 1 / 39 Last Time Synthesizing multiple

More information

Thinking 2. Dual-Process Theory. Dual-Process Theory. Can you describe the cues you use to distinguish all dogs from all cats? What is this?

Thinking 2. Dual-Process Theory. Dual-Process Theory. Can you describe the cues you use to distinguish all dogs from all cats? What is this? Dual-Process Theory Heuristics: Strategies that can be used in all kinds of directed thinking to quickly make judgments, decisions, reason, or solve problems, at the price of occasional errors. Which of

More information

Framework for Comparative Research on Relational Information Displays

Framework for Comparative Research on Relational Information Displays Framework for Comparative Research on Relational Information Displays Sung Park and Richard Catrambone 2 School of Psychology & Graphics, Visualization, and Usability Center (GVU) Georgia Institute of

More information

Necessity, Possibility and the Search for Counterexamples in Human Reasoning

Necessity, Possibility and the Search for Counterexamples in Human Reasoning University of Plymouth PEARL https://pearl.plymouth.ac.uk 04 University of Plymouth Research Theses 0 Research Theses Main Collection 20 Necessity, Possibility and the Search for Counterexamples in Human

More information

DRAFT (Final) Concept Paper On choosing appropriate estimands and defining sensitivity analyses in confirmatory clinical trials

DRAFT (Final) Concept Paper On choosing appropriate estimands and defining sensitivity analyses in confirmatory clinical trials DRAFT (Final) Concept Paper On choosing appropriate estimands and defining sensitivity analyses in confirmatory clinical trials EFSPI Comments Page General Priority (H/M/L) Comment The concept to develop

More information

5/4/18. PSYC315: Chapter 10. Reasoning. Reasoning and the Brain

5/4/18. PSYC315: Chapter 10. Reasoning. Reasoning and the Brain PSYC315: Chapter 10 Dr. Elizabeth Schwaiger Reasoning How do people reason about situations described in conditional language (e.g., if then )? How do people reason about situations described with quantifiers

More information

PLANNING THE RESEARCH PROJECT

PLANNING THE RESEARCH PROJECT Van Der Velde / Guide to Business Research Methods First Proof 6.11.2003 4:53pm page 1 Part I PLANNING THE RESEARCH PROJECT Van Der Velde / Guide to Business Research Methods First Proof 6.11.2003 4:53pm

More information

Expert System Profile

Expert System Profile Expert System Profile GENERAL Domain: Medical Main General Function: Diagnosis System Name: INTERNIST-I/ CADUCEUS (or INTERNIST-II) Dates: 1970 s 1980 s Researchers: Ph.D. Harry Pople, M.D. Jack D. Myers

More information

How people differ in syllogistic reasoning

How people differ in syllogistic reasoning How people differ in syllogistic reasoning Sangeet Khemlani 1 and P.N. Johnson-Laird 2,3 sangeet.khemlani@nrl.navy.mil, phil@princeton.edu 1 Naval Research Laboratory, Washington, DC 20375 USA 2 Princeton

More information

Sawtooth Software. The Number of Levels Effect in Conjoint: Where Does It Come From and Can It Be Eliminated? RESEARCH PAPER SERIES

Sawtooth Software. The Number of Levels Effect in Conjoint: Where Does It Come From and Can It Be Eliminated? RESEARCH PAPER SERIES Sawtooth Software RESEARCH PAPER SERIES The Number of Levels Effect in Conjoint: Where Does It Come From and Can It Be Eliminated? Dick Wittink, Yale University Joel Huber, Duke University Peter Zandan,

More information

A POWER STRUGGLE: BETWEEN- VS. WITHIN-SUBJECTS DESIGNS IN DEDUCTIVE REASONING RESEARCH

A POWER STRUGGLE: BETWEEN- VS. WITHIN-SUBJECTS DESIGNS IN DEDUCTIVE REASONING RESEARCH Psychologia, 2004, 47, 277 296 A POWER STRUGGLE: BETWEEN- VS. WITHIN-SUBJECTS DESIGNS IN DEDUCTIVE REASONING RESEARCH Valerie A. THOMPSON 1) and Jamie I. D. CAMPBELL 1) 1) University of Saskatchewan, Canada

More information

Everyday conditional reasoning: A working memory dependent tradeoff between counterexample and likelihood use

Everyday conditional reasoning: A working memory dependent tradeoff between counterexample and likelihood use Memory & Cognition 2005, 33 (1), 107-119 Everyday conditional reasoning: A working memory dependent tradeoff between counterexample and likelihood use NIKI VERSCHUEREN, WALTER SCHAEKEN, and GERY D YDEWALLE

More information

CFSD 21 st Century Learning Rubric Skill: Critical & Creative Thinking

CFSD 21 st Century Learning Rubric Skill: Critical & Creative Thinking Comparing Selects items that are inappropriate to the basic objective of the comparison. Selects characteristics that are trivial or do not address the basic objective of the comparison. Selects characteristics

More information

CHAPTER 3 DATA ANALYSIS: DESCRIBING DATA

CHAPTER 3 DATA ANALYSIS: DESCRIBING DATA Data Analysis: Describing Data CHAPTER 3 DATA ANALYSIS: DESCRIBING DATA In the analysis process, the researcher tries to evaluate the data collected both from written documents and from other sources such

More information

Why Models Rather Than Rules Give a Better Account of Prepositional Reasoning: A Reply to Bonatti and to O'Brien, Braine, and Yang

Why Models Rather Than Rules Give a Better Account of Prepositional Reasoning: A Reply to Bonatti and to O'Brien, Braine, and Yang Psychological Review 1994. Vol. 101, No. 4, 734-739 Copyright 1994 by the American Psychological Association, Inc. 0033-295X/94/S3.00 Why Models Rather Than Rules Give a Better Account of Prepositional

More information

Response to the ASA s statement on p-values: context, process, and purpose

Response to the ASA s statement on p-values: context, process, and purpose Response to the ASA s statement on p-values: context, process, purpose Edward L. Ionides Alexer Giessing Yaacov Ritov Scott E. Page Departments of Complex Systems, Political Science Economics, University

More information

FULL REPORT OF RESEARCH ACTIVITIES. Background

FULL REPORT OF RESEARCH ACTIVITIES. Background FULL REPORT OF RESEARCH ACTIVITIES Background There has been a recent upsurge of interest in individual differences in reasoning which has been well summarised by Stanovich & West (2000). The reason for

More information

Directionality of conditionals in the context of visual priming

Directionality of conditionals in the context of visual priming Review of Psychology, 2013, Vol. 20, No. 1-2, 61-68 UDC 159.9 Directionality of conditionals in the context of visual priming IGOR BAJŠANSKI, PAVLE VALERJEV and TANJA GULAN The theory of mental models

More information

Basis for Conclusions: ISA 230 (Redrafted), Audit Documentation

Basis for Conclusions: ISA 230 (Redrafted), Audit Documentation Basis for Conclusions: ISA 230 (Redrafted), Audit Documentation Prepared by the Staff of the International Auditing and Assurance Standards Board December 2007 , AUDIT DOCUMENTATION This Basis for Conclusions

More information

LSAT India Analytical Reasoning 2019

LSAT India Analytical Reasoning 2019 Sample Questions with Answers. LSAT India Analytical Reasoning 2019 Five Sample Analytical Reasoning Questions and Explanations Directions: Each group of questions in this section is based on a set of

More information

This is an Author's Original Manuscript of an article submitted to Behavior & Brain Science and may differ from the final version which is available here: http://journals.cambridge.org/action/displayabstract?frompage=online&aid=8242505

More information

A Computational Model of Counterfactual Thinking: The Temporal Order Effect

A Computational Model of Counterfactual Thinking: The Temporal Order Effect A Computational Model of Counterfactual Thinking: The Temporal Order Effect Clare R. Walsh (cwalsh@tcd.ie) Psychology Department, University of Dublin, Trinity College, Dublin 2, Ireland Ruth M.J. Byrne

More information

Different developmental patterns of simple deductive and probabilistic inferential reasoning

Different developmental patterns of simple deductive and probabilistic inferential reasoning Memory & Cognition 2008, 36 (6), 1066-1078 doi: 10.3758/MC.36.6.1066 Different developmental patterns of simple deductive and probabilistic inferential reasoning Henry Markovits Université du Québec à

More information

What do External Representations Tell about Mental Models? An Exploratory Study in Deductive Reasoning

What do External Representations Tell about Mental Models? An Exploratory Study in Deductive Reasoning What do External Representations Tell about Mental Models? An Exploratory Study in Deductive Reasoning Barbara Bazzanella (B.Bazzanella@studenti.unitn.it) University of Trento LASDEC experimental laboratory,

More information

Organizing Scientific Thinking Using the QuALMRI Framework

Organizing Scientific Thinking Using the QuALMRI Framework Organizing Scientific Thinking Using the QuALMRI Framework Written by Kevin Ochsner and modified by others. Based on a scheme devised by Steve Kosslyn. This handout outlines a structured process for generating,

More information

What is the Scientific Method?

What is the Scientific Method? Scientific Method What is the Scientific Method? It s a way to solve/explain a problem or natural phenomenon, while removing human bias and opinion. It is a critical procedure that allows validity and

More information

Experimental Psychology

Experimental Psychology Title Experimental Psychology Type Individual Document Map Authors Aristea Theodoropoulos, Patricia Sikorski Subject Social Studies Course None Selected Grade(s) 11, 12 Location Roxbury High School Curriculum

More information

9 research designs likely for PSYC 2100

9 research designs likely for PSYC 2100 9 research designs likely for PSYC 2100 1) 1 factor, 2 levels, 1 group (one group gets both treatment levels) related samples t-test (compare means of 2 levels only) 2) 1 factor, 2 levels, 2 groups (one

More information

Individual Differences and the Belief Bias Effect: Mental Models, Logical Necessity, and Abstract Reasoning

Individual Differences and the Belief Bias Effect: Mental Models, Logical Necessity, and Abstract Reasoning THINKING AND REASONING, 1999, THE 5 (1), BELIEF 1 28 BIAS EFFECT 1 Individual Differences and the Belief Bias Effect: Mental Models, Logical Necessity, and Abstract Reasoning Donna Torrens and Valerie

More information

Psychology 205, Revelle, Fall 2014 Research Methods in Psychology Mid-Term. Name:

Psychology 205, Revelle, Fall 2014 Research Methods in Psychology Mid-Term. Name: Name: 1. (2 points) What is the primary advantage of using the median instead of the mean as a measure of central tendency? It is less affected by outliers. 2. (2 points) Why is counterbalancing important

More information

Process of Designing & Implementing a Research Project

Process of Designing & Implementing a Research Project Research Question, Hypothesis, Variables Dr. R.M. Pandey Prof & Head Department of Biostatistics A.I.I.M.S., New Delhi rmpandey@yahoo.com Process of Designing & Implementing a Research Project 2 HYPOTHESIS

More information

Cognitive processes underlying the continuity effect in spatial reasoning

Cognitive processes underlying the continuity effect in spatial reasoning Cognitive processes underlying the continuity effect in spatial reasoning Jelica Nejasmic (jelica.nejasmic@psychol.uni-giessen.de) Antje Krumnack (antje.krumnack@psychol.uni-giessen.de) Leandra Bucher

More information

On the Relation Between Representations Constructed From Text Comprehension and Transitive Inference Production

On the Relation Between Representations Constructed From Text Comprehension and Transitive Inference Production Journal of Experimental Psychology: l.~a'ning, Memory, and Cognition 2000, Vol. 26, No. 1,187-203 Copyright 2000 by the American Psychological Association, Inc. 0278-7393/00/$5.00 DOI: 10.1037//0278-7393.26.1.187

More information

Cognitive domain: Comprehension Answer location: Elements of Empiricism Question type: MC

Cognitive domain: Comprehension Answer location: Elements of Empiricism Question type: MC Chapter 2 1. Knowledge that is evaluative, value laden, and concerned with prescribing what ought to be is known as knowledge. *a. Normative b. Nonnormative c. Probabilistic d. Nonprobabilistic. 2. Most

More information

Remarks on Bayesian Control Charts

Remarks on Bayesian Control Charts Remarks on Bayesian Control Charts Amir Ahmadi-Javid * and Mohsen Ebadi Department of Industrial Engineering, Amirkabir University of Technology, Tehran, Iran * Corresponding author; email address: ahmadi_javid@aut.ac.ir

More information

What Causes war? C h. 1 : T e r m i n o l o g y & Methodology. Notes by Denis Bašić

What Causes war? C h. 1 : T e r m i n o l o g y & Methodology. Notes by Denis Bašić What Causes war? C h. 1 : T e r m i n o l o g y & Methodology Notes by Denis Bašić What is called wisdom is concerned with primary causes. Aristotle The Scientific Method: Theory Theories in the social

More information

A to Z OF RESEARCH METHODS AND TERMS APPLICABLE WITHIN SOCIAL SCIENCE RESEARCH

A to Z OF RESEARCH METHODS AND TERMS APPLICABLE WITHIN SOCIAL SCIENCE RESEARCH A to Z OF RESEARCH METHODS AND TERMS APPLICABLE WITHIN SOCIAL SCIENCE RESEARCH QUANTATIVE RESEARCH METHODS Are concerned with trying to quantify things; they ask questions such as how long, how many or

More information

Is it possible to gain new knowledge by deduction?

Is it possible to gain new knowledge by deduction? Is it possible to gain new knowledge by deduction? Abstract In this paper I will try to defend the hypothesis that it is possible to gain new knowledge through deduction. In order to achieve that goal,

More information

Special guidelines for preparation and quality approval of reviews in the form of reference documents in the field of occupational diseases

Special guidelines for preparation and quality approval of reviews in the form of reference documents in the field of occupational diseases Special guidelines for preparation and quality approval of reviews in the form of reference documents in the field of occupational diseases November 2010 (1 st July 2016: The National Board of Industrial

More information

A Verbal Reasoning Theory for Categorical Syllogisms

A Verbal Reasoning Theory for Categorical Syllogisms A Verbal Reasoning Theory for Categorical Syllogisms Thad A. Polk and Alien Newell 01July9210:14 DRAFT: Please do not quote or distribute Introduction Human beings are constantly faced with the problem

More information

Engineering Science & VALIDITY

Engineering Science & VALIDITY Engineering Science & VALIDITY Today we will look at: 1. Scientific foundations 2. Validation 3. Reliability 4. Logic 5. Industrial validation 6. MSc relevance February 24, 2014 1 The linked image cannot

More information

IMPROVING PROBLEM SOLVING EFFICIENCY: THE WHAT AND HOW OF CAUTION

IMPROVING PROBLEM SOLVING EFFICIENCY: THE WHAT AND HOW OF CAUTION IMPROVING PROBLEM SOLVING EFFICIENCY: THE WHAT AND HOW OF CAUTION By MARTIN E. KNOWLES A DISSERTATION PRESENTED TO THE GRADUATE SCHOOL OF THE UNIVERSITY OF FLORIDA IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS

More information

ISA 540, Auditing Accounting Estimates, Including Fair Value Accounting Estimates, and Related Disclosures Issues and Task Force Recommendations

ISA 540, Auditing Accounting Estimates, Including Fair Value Accounting Estimates, and Related Disclosures Issues and Task Force Recommendations Agenda Item 1-A ISA 540, Auditing Accounting Estimates, Including Fair Value Accounting Estimates, and Related Disclosures Issues and Task Force Recommendations Introduction 1. Since the September 2016

More information

Does momentary accessibility influence metacomprehension judgments? The influence of study judgment lags on accessibility effects

Does momentary accessibility influence metacomprehension judgments? The influence of study judgment lags on accessibility effects Psychonomic Bulletin & Review 26, 13 (1), 6-65 Does momentary accessibility influence metacomprehension judgments? The influence of study judgment lags on accessibility effects JULIE M. C. BAKER and JOHN

More information

Author's response to reviews

Author's response to reviews Author's response to reviews Title: Physiotherapy interventions in scientific physiotherapy publications focusing on interventions for children with cerebral palsy: A qualitative phenomenographic approach.

More information

Author's response to reviews

Author's response to reviews Author's response to reviews Title: Diabetes duration and health-related quality of life in individuals with onset of diabetes in the age group 15-34 years - a Swedish population-based study using EQ-5D

More information

MODELING DISEASE FINAL REPORT 5/21/2010 SARAH DEL CIELLO, JAKE CLEMENTI, AND NAILAH HART

MODELING DISEASE FINAL REPORT 5/21/2010 SARAH DEL CIELLO, JAKE CLEMENTI, AND NAILAH HART MODELING DISEASE FINAL REPORT 5/21/2010 SARAH DEL CIELLO, JAKE CLEMENTI, AND NAILAH HART ABSTRACT This paper models the progression of a disease through a set population using differential equations. Two

More information

Think Like You Don t Know: A Form of Belief Bias in Judgments of Bayesian Rationality

Think Like You Don t Know: A Form of Belief Bias in Judgments of Bayesian Rationality Think Like You Don t Know: A Form of Belief Bias in Judgments of Bayesian Rationality Richard Anderson Department of Psychology Bowling Green State University Bowling Green, Ohio 1 INTRODUCTION 2 INTEGRATING

More information

On the diversity principle and local falsifiability

On the diversity principle and local falsifiability On the diversity principle and local falsifiability Uriel Feige October 22, 2012 1 Introduction This manuscript concerns the methodology of evaluating one particular aspect of TCS (theoretical computer

More information

5.1 Standard Form, Mood & Figure

5.1 Standard Form, Mood & Figure Unit Five Categorical Syllogisms Page 1 Unit Five Categorical Syllogisms A Categorical Syllogism is a deductive argument consisting of two premises and a conclusion in which three terms each appear twice.

More information

Neuroscience and Generalized Empirical Method Go Three Rounds

Neuroscience and Generalized Empirical Method Go Three Rounds Bruce Anderson, Neuroscience and Generalized Empirical Method Go Three Rounds: Review of Robert Henman s Global Collaboration: Neuroscience as Paradigmatic Journal of Macrodynamic Analysis 9 (2016): 74-78.

More information

Assignment 2: Experimental Design

Assignment 2: Experimental Design Assignment 2: Experimental Design Description In this assignment, you will follow the steps described in the Step-by-Step Experimental Design lecture to design an experiment. These steps will provide you

More information

Are There Two Kinds of Reasoning?

Are There Two Kinds of Reasoning? Are There Two Kinds of Reasoning? Evan Heit (E.Heit@warwick.ac.uk) Department of Psychology, University of Warwick Coventry CV4 7AL, UK Caren M. Rotello (caren@psych.umass.edu) Department of Psychology,

More information