The Cognitive and Communicative Demands of Cooperation

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "The Cognitive and Communicative Demands of Cooperation"

Transcription

1 Chapter 1 The Cognitive and Communicative Demands of Cooperation Peter Gärdenfors Abstract I argue that the analysis of different kinds of cooperation will benefit from an account of the cognitive and communicative functions required for that cooperation. I review different models of cooperation in game theory reciprocal altruism, indirect reciprocity, cooperation about future goals, and conventions with respect to their cognitive and communicative prerequisites. The cognitive factors considered include recognition of individuals, memory capacity, temporal discounting, prospective cognition, and theory of mind. Whereas many forms of cooperation require no communication or just simple communication, more advanced forms that are unique to humans presuppose full symbolic communication. 1.1 The span of cooperation in game theory The evolution of cooperation remains an enigma. In surprisingly many situations, both animals and humans fail to behave as predicted by game theory. For example, humans cooperate more in prisoner s dilemma games than would be expected from logical analysis. Several explanations for this mismatch have been suggested, ranging from the claim that animals and humans are not fully rational to the claim that the kind of rationality presumed in classical game theory is not relevant to evolutionary arguments. The purpose of this chapter is to argue that the behavior of various agents must be judged in relation to their cognitive and communicative capacities. In my opinion, these factors have not been sufficiently considered in game theory. There are many ways of defining cooperation. A broad definition is that it consists of joint actions that confer mutual benefits. 1 Peter Gärdenfors Lund University Cognitive Science, Kungshuset, Lundagård S Lund, Sweden Peter.Gardenfors@lucs.lu.se 1 A stronger criterion, focused on human cooperation, is formulated by Bowles and Gintis [8]: An individual behavior that incurs personal costs in order to engage in a joint activity that confers ben- 1

2 2 Peter Gärdenfors A narrower definition concerns situations in which joint action poses a dilemma, so that, in the short run, an individual would be better off not cooperating, even though in the long run cooperation may be preferable [65, p. 358]. The typical example of such a situation is some variant on the prisoner s dilemma game. In this chapter, the focus will be on the narrower concept. Conventionally, cooperation has been studied from two perspectives. First, in traditional game theory, cooperation has been assumed to take place between individuals of the species Homo economicus, who are ideally rational. Homo economicus is presumed to have a perfect theory of mind: that is, the capacity to judge the beliefs, desires, and intentions of the other players. In a Bayesian framework, this amounts to assuming that all the other players are Bayesian decision makers. In the case of Homo sapiens, that theory of mind is well developed, at least in comparison to other animal species, but it is far from perfect [26]. Second, cooperative games have been studied from an evolutionary perspective. The classical accounts are found in Axelrod and Hamilton [2] and Maynard Smith [51]. Here, the players are the genes of various animal species. The genes are assumed to have absolutely no rationality nor any cognitive capacities. However, their strategies can slowly adapt, via the mechanisms of natural selection, over repeated interactions and generations. In the evolutionary framework, the theory of mind of the players is either not accounted for or not considered relevant. The differences in cognitive and communicative demands between these two perspectives are seldom discussed. For example, in Lehmann and Keller s [44] classification of models for the evolution of cooperation and altruism, only two parameters related to cognition and communication are included: a one-period memory parameter m defined as the probability that an individual knows the investment into helping of its partner at the previous round and a reputation parameter q defined as the probability that an individual knows the image score of its partner [44, p. 1367]. I believe that the analysis of different kinds of cooperative games would benefit from a richer account of the cognitive and communicative functions required for the cooperation. The cognitive factors to be considered include recognition of individuals, memory capacity, temporal discounting, prospective cognition, and theory of mind. The relevant communication ranges from simple signaling to full symbolic communication. I will argue that, whereas many forms of cooperation require only very limited cognitive capacities and no communication, more advanced forms, unique to humans, presuppose a high awareness of future needs, a rich understanding of the minds of others, and symbolic communication. For example, the reputation mechanism used in Nowak and Sigmund s [57] model of indirect reciprocity assumes that the individuals can recognize each other, remember previous interactions, have at least some aspects of a theory of mind, and possess a communication system that, among other things, can refer to individuals in their absence and describe the roles of donor and receiver in interactions. efits exceeding these costs to other members of one s group. It should be noted that joint activity need not imply that the actions are performed simultaneously: they can be done in sequence.

3 1 The Cognitive and Communicative Demands of Cooperation Cognitive requirements for different kinds of cooperation In this section, I will outline different kinds of cooperation. I will take as my point of departure the forms of cooperation that have been studied within game theory in particular evolutionary game theory though I will also borrow some themes from animal behavior. The paradigmatic game in my analysis will be that of the prisoner s dilemma, mainly in its iterated form, although I will occasionally refer to other games. A reason to focus on variations of the prisoner s dilemma is that such games frequently arise in biological/ecological settings. Biological players often cooperate considerably more than the total defection predicted by any strictly rationalistic analysis: a finding that generates much of the interest in studying these games. A bio-cognitively oriented analysis faces the problem of identifying those factors that promote cooperation. I believe that they include varying forms of cognition and communication. I shall present the different kinds of cooperation I discuss roughly in order of increasing cognitive demands. My list is far from exhaustive; I have merely selected some forms of cooperation where the cognitive and communicative components can readily be identified, at least to some degree. Finer distinctions could be made for several of the items on my list; those distinctions are not, however, of interest here Flocking behavior Flocking behavior is a cognitively low-level form of cooperation. Flocking is found in many species, and its function is often to minimise predation. Simulation models of flocking (e.g. [64, 50, 39]) show that the sophisticated behavior of the flock can emerge from the behaviors of single individuals following simple rules. Only two rules seem to be required for birds to fly in a flock: (a) position yourself as closely as possible to the centre of the flock and (b) maintain a certain minimum distance from your neighbors. Such rules require no cognitive capacities beyond basic visual perception. (Other senses such as echolocation could, in principle, be used as well) In-group versus out-group One simple way for a player to increase cooperation in an iterated prisoner s dilemma game is to divide the other individuals into an in-group and an out-group. Then, the basic strategy is to cooperate with everybody in the in-group while defecting against everybody in the out-group. The only cognitive requirements of this strategy is that you be able to separate members of the in-group from the out-group. In nature this is often accomplished via olfaction: for example, bees from a different hive have a different smell and are therefore treated with aggression. Meanwhile Dunbar [17] speculates that dialects have evolved to serve as markers of the in-

4 4 Peter Gärdenfors group among humans: a more advanced version of the same idea. The ubiquity and strength of in-group mechanisms throughout the animal kingdom provide good reason to suspect that the mechanisms are at least partially genetically determined [42]. Consider a special case. The spatial prisoner s dilemma games studied by, among others, Nowak and May [56], Lindgren and Nordahl [49], Hauert [34], Brandt et al. [9] can be seen as a form of in-group cooperation. In these games, players are organised spatially so that one can only interact with one s neighbors. The results of these studies show that the spatial structure is manipulated so as to promote cooperation. Cooperators survive by forming clusters, creating spatially defined in-groups that defect against outliers. It seems fairly clear that the evolutionary origin of in-group formation is kinship selection. In a kin group, the outcome of a prisoner s dilemma game cannot be judged solely by the benefits accruing to single players. This is because of the genetic relatedness of the individuals; in many cases, kinship mechanisms make cooperation the only evolutionarily stable strategy. In other words, a prisoner s dilemma game that is seemingly irrational or less than fully rational at the individual agent level may be perfectly cooperative when the genes are taken as the players. Kin groups can form kernels from which larger cooperative groups can subsequently develop [48, p. 351]. The in-group requires some form of marker, be it just physical proximity, to distinguish the in-group from the out-group. Evolutionary biologists (e.g. [88]) stress that such markers should be hard to fake in order to exclude free riders from the in-group. Another way of generating an in-group is to identify a common enemy. West et al. [86] present empirical evidence that when a group playing an iterated prisoner s dilemma game competes with another group, within-group cooperation will increase. Bernhard et al. [4] present an anthropological study of two groups in Papua New Guinea; it supports the same conclusion. The downside of an in-groupversus-out-group mechanism, as Hamilton [32] notes, is that what favors cooperation within groups will, at the same time, favor hostility between groups. A parallel example can be found among apes. A troop of chimpanzees in the Gombe forest in Tanzania became divided into a northern and a southern group. The chimpanzees in the two groups, who had earlier played and groomed together, started fighting lethally against each other [12] Reciprocal altruism In an iterated prisoner s dilemma game, one player can retaliate against another s previous defection. Trivers [81] argues that this possibility can make cooperation more attractive and lead to what he calls reciprocal altruism. In their seminal paper, Axelrod and Hamilton [2] used computer simulations to show that cooperation can evolve through multiple iterations of the prisoner s dilemma game. A Nash equilibrium strategy, such as the well-known Tit-for-Tat, can lead to reciprocal cooperative behavior among individuals who encounter each other frequently. The minimal cog-

5 1 The Cognitive and Communicative Demands of Cooperation 5 nitive capacities required for this strategy are the ability to recognize the individual one interacts with and a memory of previous outcomes (see below for further specification of these criteria). Trust may be an emotional correlate of reciprocity that strengthens reciprocal behavior. Frank [21] suggests that such an emotion may become selected for and thus genetically grounded in a species that engages in reciprocal altruism. On this point, Van Schaik and Kappeler [84, p. 17] write that we must expect the presence of derived psychological mechanisms that provide the proximate control mechanisms for these cooperative tendencies... [T]he evidence suggests a critical role for unique emotions as the main mechanisms. Extreme vigilance toward cheaters, a sense of gratitude upon receiving support, a sense of guilt upon being detected at free riding, willingness to engage in donation of help and zeal to dole out altruistic punishment at free riders all these are examples of mechanisms and the underlying emotions that are less developed in even our closest relatives. Meanwhile Trivers [82, p. 76] writes about his 1971 paper on reciprocity that its most important contribution was that it laid the foundation for understanding how a sense of justice evolved. If the players in an iterated prisoner s dilemma game choose their moves synchronously, then the size of available memory does not seem to affect which strategies are successful [1, 47, 48, 35]. However, for so-called alternating iterated prisoner s dilemma games in which players take turns choosing their moves, it seems that the best strategies depend on the size of memory for previous moves [22, 55]. Field studies of fish [63], vampire bats [87], and primates [69], among others, have revealed the presence of reciprocal altruism. Still, the evidence for reciprocal altruism in non-human species is debated, and the results of some laboratory experiments seem to argue against it [76]. In line with this, Stevens and Hauser [77] argue that the cognitive demands of reciprocal altruism have been underestimated (see also [33]). They claim that reciprocal altruism will be evolutionarily stable in a species only if (a) the temporal discounting of future rewards is not too steep, (b) members of the species have sufficient ability to discriminate the value of the rewards so as to judge that what an altruist receives back is comparable to what it has given, and (c) there is sufficient memory capacity to keep track of interactions with several individuals. Temporal discounting refers to the tendency to discount the future value of a reward, the further removed it is in time. Studies reveal that the rates of temporal discounting differ drastically between species [41, 15]. Humans have the lowest rate, a prerequisite for the prospective planning that will be discussed below. New studies on apes reveal that, in food contexts, apes are at level with humans [68, 60]. What factors (ecological, cognitive, neurological, etc.) explain the discounting rate of a particular species is an interesting problem that should receive more attention within evolutionary game theory. According to Stevens and Hauser [77], cognitive demands explain why reciprocal altruism is difficult to establish in species other than Homo sapiens. Weighing against their argument, one may present the three types of reciprocity proposed Waal and Brosnan [13, pp ]: (1) Individuals reciprocate on the basis of symmetrical features of dyadic relationships (kinship, similarities in age,

6 6 Peter Gärdenfors or sameness of gender). De Waal and Bosnan say that this is the cognitively least demanding form: it requires no scorekeeping since reciprocation is based on preexisting features of the relationship. [...] All that is required is an aversion to major, lasting imbalance in incoming and outgoing benefits (2) Next comes attitudinal reciprocity, where individual willingness to cooperate depends on the attitude the partner has recently shown. Cognitively, the involvement of memory and scorekeeping seems rather minimal, as the critical variable is general social disposition rather than specific costs and benefits of exchanged behavior [13, p. 104]. (3) Finally there is calculated reciprocity, in which individuals reciprocate on a behavioral one-on-one basis with a significant time interval. This is the cognitively most demanding form of reciprocity, since it requires memory of previous events, some degree of score-keeping, [and] partner-specific contingency between favors given and received [13, p. 104]. Reciprocity as discussed by Stevens and Hauser [77] is most similar to this third form. It is not surprising that it would be the most difficult to achieve. When analyzing to what extent different species exhibit reciprocal Waal and Brosnan s [13] distinctions must be kept in mind. Meanwhile, attitudinal reciprocity as defined by de Waal [13] involves cognitively fairly minimal capacities: individuals must be recognized over time and their attitude as a partner remembered. Understanding the attitude of a partner requires some kind of theory of mind, with at least the capacity to understand the desires of the other (see [26]). Understanding the attitude of a partner is a good general mechanism for improving cooperation. Charness and Dufwenberg [11, p. 1580] write of guilt aversion as a way to explain why individuals behave more cooperatively than predicted by game theory in prisoner s-dilemma-type (and similar) games. To wit: decision makers experience guilt if they believe they let others down. By considering the expectations of your partner(s) and having an emotional predisposition to avoid letting a partner down, your payoff matrix in a prisoner s dilemma game changes, and you end up being much more cooperative than traditional game theory would predict. For Charness and Dufwenberg (ibid.) guilt aversion requires beliefs about the beliefs of others. However, this claim about the theory of mind of the decision maker seems to be too strong for the mechanism they are trying to explain. Surely it is sufficient that the decision maker understand the desires of the other just far enough to realize that the other is let down. This caveat aside, the notion of guilt aversion seems key to analyzing many forms of human cooperative behavior, and it merits further investigations, both theoretical and experimental. The question arises as to what extent guilt aversion can be shown to exist in other species. At the least, the capacity to understand the desires of others should be within the cognitive reach of many species.

7 1 The Cognitive and Communicative Demands of Cooperation Indirect reciprocity Reciprocal altruism can be rendered in slogan form: scratch my back and I ll scratch yours. As we have seen, this principle makes sound evolutionary sense. However, in humans one often finds more extreme forms of altruism: If I help you, somebody else will help me. Such cooperation has been called indirect reciprocity, and it seems to be unique to humans. Nowak and Sigmund [57] show that, at least under certain conditions, indirect reciprocity can be given an evolutionary grounding (see also [45]). However, as we shall see, their explanation depends on very strong assumptions concerning the communication of the inter-actors (which may explain why indirect reciprocity is only found in humans). In Nowak and Sigmund s [57] account of indirect reciprocity, any two players are meant to interact at most once with each other. This is, of course, an idealising assumption; but it has the useful effect that the recipient of a defection (cheat) in a prisoner s dilemma game cannot retaliate. In this way, all strategies that have been considered for the iterated prisoner s dilemma game are excluded. So the question becomes: under what conditions can cooperation evolve as an evolutionarily stable strategy (ESS) by means of indirect reciprocity? Nowak and Sigmund note that indirect reciprocity (as we saw, earlier, with attitudinal reciprocity) seems to require some kind of theory of mind. An individual watching a second individual (the donor) helping (or failing to help) a third (the receiver) (or not helping a third in need) must be able to judge that the donor does something good ( bad ) to the receiver. 2 The form of intersubjectivity required for such comparisons is related closely to empathy [62, 26]. The key concept in Nowak and Sigmund s evolutionary model of indirect reciprocity is that of the reputation of an individual. 3 An individual s reputation i is built up by members of the society observing i s behavior towards third parties and then spreading this information to other members of the society. To wit, gossip becomes a way of achieving societal consensus about reputation [17, 73]. In this way the reputation for i being a selfless helper can be known by more or less all the members of the group. The level of i s reputation can then be used by any individual when deciding whether or not to assist i in a situation of need. 4 Reputation is not, of course, something immediately visible to others in the way of such status markers as a raised tail among wolves. Instead each individual must keep a private account of the reputation of all others with whom she interacts. Semmann et al. [70] provide a nice experimental demonstration that building a reputation through cooperation is valuable for future social interactions, not only within but also beyond one s social group. 2 This is in contrast to kinship-based altruism, where what an individual experiences as good can be that which improves her own reproductive fitness. 3 A precursor to this concept, foreshadowing it, is Sugden s [79] notion of good standing. 4 The in-group behavior discussed in Section 2.2 can be understood as a limiting case of indirect reciprocity whereby all in-group members are treated as having a good reputation and all out-group members as having a bad one. Turned the other way around, indirect reciprocity becomes a flexible way of determining the membership of the in-group.

8 8 Peter Gärdenfors It is important to distinguish in these interactions between justified and unjustified defections. If a potential receiver has defected repeatedly in the past, the donor may be justified in defecting: e.g., as a form of punishment. However, the donor runs a risk that his own reputation may drop. To prevent this, the donor should communicate his reason for defecting: i.e., the receiver has a bad reputation. A range of more sophisticated strategies is available for distinguishing between justified and unjustified defections. Nowak and Sigmund [57] call a strategy first order if the assessment of an individual i in the group depends only on i s own actions. A strategy is second order if it depends on the reputation of the receiver and third order if it depends additionally on the reputation of the donor. Nowak and Sigmund argue that only eight of the possible strategies all of which depend on the distinction between justified and unjustified defection are evolutionarily stable. Thus, the success of indirect reciprocity depends heavily on determining reputation. This means that indirect reciprocity, in Nowak and Sigmund s [57] model, requires several cognitive and communicative mechanisms. The minimal cognitive requirements are (a) recognising the relevant individuals over time, (b) remembering and updating the reputation scores of these individuals, and (c) judging by means of empathy whether a particular donor action is good or bad. The minimal communicative requirements are (d) being able socially to identify individuals in their absence, e.g. by name; (e) being able to express that x was good to y and y was bad to x. No non-human communication system seems able to handle these requirements. It should come as no surprise that Homo sapiens is the only species exhibiting indirect reciprocity. 5 The communication system need not be a humanstyle language with full syntax; a form of protolanguage along the lines discussed by Bickerton [5] is sufficient. The communication could be symbolic, but it is possible that a system based on miming [16, 89] would be adequate. The trust that is built up through reciprocal altruism is dyadic: that is, constituting a relation between two individuals. In contrast, reputation is an emergent social notion involving everybody in the group. Nowak and Sigmund [57, p. 1296] write: Indirect reciprocity is situated somewhere between direct reciprocity and public goods. On the one hand it is a game between two players, but it has to be played within a larger group. As noted above, a potential donor should signal that a potential recipient has a bad reputation before defecting, in order not to lose reputation himself. This is another requirement on communication: the ability to form expressions of the type y has a bad reputation. Nowak and Sigmund s [57] model considers only two kinds of reputation: good and bad. It goes without saying that, in real groups, communication about reputation is far more nuanced. Of course, the need for communication is dependent on the size of the group that is facing the prisoner s dilemma situations. In a small, tightly connected group where everybody sees everybody else most of the time, no reputation mechanism is 5 In contrast, Van Schaik and Kappeler [84, p. 15] write: the three basic conditions for reputation are individual recognition, variation in personality traits, and curiosity about the outcome of interactions involving third parties. In my opinion, however, these criteria are too weak, since they place no requirement on reputation to be communicated.

9 1 The Cognitive and Communicative Demands of Cooperation 9 needed. One can look at the way within-group ranking is established. If I observe that x has higher rank than y and I know that y has higher rank than I do, there is no need for (aggressive) interaction or for communication to establish the relative ranking. However, in large and loosely connected groups, these mechanisms are not sufficient, and some form of communication about non-present individuals is required. This displacement of the message is one of the criteria that Hockett [40] uses to identify symbolic language (see also [24]). Still other mechanisms may exist that influence the reputation of an individual. In many situations, people are willing to cooperate but also to punish free riders. Punishment behavior is difficult to explain because it is costly, and the cooperative non-punisher benefits [20]. Thus, in general, punishment should decrease in frequency. 6 Barclay [3] presents evidence that the reputation of a punisher increases, and that people are more willing to cooperate with punishers. In this way, punishment behavior may be rewarded in the long run (see also [71, 36, 37, 54] and can stabilize cooperative behavior in iterated prisoner s dilemma games [48]. For all its cost, punishment behavior seems to be something that all human populations are willing to use, to varying degrees. Using computer simulations, Hauert et al. [36] show that, if participants not only have the choice to cooperate, to defect, or to punish, but also to stand aside, defectors will eventually be eliminated from the population. Surprisingly, if standing aside is not an option, then, in the long run, the defectors take over. Hauert at al. conclude that compulsory joint enterprises are less likely to lead to cooperation than voluntary ones. These results clearly show that Nowak and Sigmund s idealizing assumption about one-shot interactions is too strong. In real life it is important to be able, at least sometimes, to retaliate. No evidence exists for altruistic punishment among animals in nature ([84], Waal and Brosnan [13] report experimentally induced refusal to cooperate that is costly for the non-cooperative individual) Cooperation to achieve future goals Cooperation often occurs over an extended timespan and requires a form of planning. One must distinguish between immediate planning that concerns present needs and prospective planning that concerns future ones. Humans can predict that they will be hungry tomorrow and so should save some food. They can imagine that the winter will be cold and so should start building a shelter already in the summer. The cognition of most other animals appears concerned almost exclusively with the here and now, while humans live both here and now and in the future. The central cognitive aspect of prospective planning is the capacity to represent future needs. Prospective thinking is sometimes also called mental time travel (e.g. [66]). 6 In line with Frank [21], Fehr and Gächter [20] say that negative emotions towards defectors are the proximate causes of altruistic punishment.

10 10 Peter Gärdenfors Bischof [6] and Bischof-Köhler [7] argue that non-human animals cannot anticipate future needs or drive states (see also [31]). Their cognition is therefore bound to their present motivational state (see also [78]). This so-called Bischof-Köhler hypothesis had seemed supported by the previously available evidence on planning in non-human animals. However, recent experimental results on non-human primates [53, 66, 60] as well as recent observations of spontaneous planning behaviors [58] demonstrate that the hypothesis no longer can be upheld. For most forms of cooperation one may find among animals, mental representations for the goal of the cooperation are not needed. If the goal is immediately present in the environment for example as food to be eaten or an antagonist to be fought the collaborators need no mutual representation of the goal before acting. If, on the other hand, the goal is distant in time or space, a mutual representation of it must be produced before cooperative action can be taken. So building a shared dwelling requires coordinated planning of how to obtain the building materials and advanced collaboration during the construction. In general, cooperating on future goals requires that the conceptual spaces of the individuals be coordinated. A mutual representation of a future goal changes a situation from a cooperative dilemma into a game where the cooperative strategy is the equilibrium solution. For example, if my group lives in a very dry area, each individual (or each family) will benefit from digging a well. However, if my neighbor digs a well, I may defect, and take all my water from his well instead of digging my own. Meanwhile, if nobody digs a well, we are all worse off than if everybody does so. Now, if somebody suggests that we cooperate in digging a communal well, then such a well, by being potentially much deeper, could yield much more water than all the individual wells taken together. Once such cooperation is established, the incentive to defect may either disappear or at least be significantly reduced, since everybody stands to benefit more from supporting the common goal. In game-theoretic terms, digging a communal well may work out to be a new equilibrium strategy. This example shows how the capacity for sharing detached future goals can strongly enhance the value of cooperative strategies within the group. Strategies based on future goals may introduce new equilibria that are beneficial to all participants. The cognitive requirements for cooperating on future goals crucially involve the capacity to represent future drives or wishes: that is, they require prospective planning. Even if water is currently plentiful, you can foresee the coming dry season. This representation, and not any current drive state, forms the driving force behind a wish to cooperate in digging a well. What are the communicative requirements for such (shared) representations? Symbolic language is the primary tool by which agents can make their personal representations known to each other. In previous work [10, 24, 25, 28], I have proposed a strong connection between the evolution of prospective cognition and the evolution of symbolic communication. In brief, symbolic language makes it possible to cooperate on future goals in an efficient way. Again, such communication involves any complex syntactic structures; protolanguage [5] will serve perfectly well.

11 1 The Cognitive and Communicative Demands of Cooperation 11 An important feature of the use of symbols in cooperation is the way they set the cooperators free from the goals that are immediately available in the environment. This requires that present goals can be suppressed, which depends upon the executive functions of the frontal brain lobes [43]. Future goals and the means to reach them can then be picked out and shared through symbolic communication. This kind of sharing gives humans an enormous cooperative advantage in comparison to other species. I propose that symbolic communication and cooperation on future goals have co-evolved (cf. the ratchet effect discussed by Tomasello [80, pp ]). That said, without the prior presence of prospective cognition, the selective pressures that resulted in symbolic communication would not have emerged Commitments and contracts Commitments and contracts are special cases of cooperating about the future. They rely on an advanced theory of mind that allows for joint beliefs. 7 Joint beliefs form the basis for much of human culture. They make many new forms of cooperation possible. For example, one might promise to do something, which only means that you intend to do it. On the other hand, when you commit to another person to perform an action, the other person normally wants you to do it and intends to check that you do so. Furthermore, the two parties share joint beliefs concerning these intentions and desires [18]. Unlike promises, commitments cannot arise unless the parties have such joint beliefs and possess prospective cognition. It has been argued in several places (e.g. [80, 24, 26]) that the capacity for joint beliefs is only found in humans. Interestingly, studies show that three-year-olds already have some understanding of joint commitments [30]. For similar reasons, contracts cannot be established without joint beliefs and prospective cognition. Deacon [14] argues that marriage is the first example of cooperation where symbolic communication is needed. It should be obvious that marriage is a form of contract. Even though I do not know of any evidence that marriage agreements came first, I still find this idea interesting in the discussion of early prospective cognition. Any sort of pair-bonding agreement implicitly determines which future behaviors are allowed and not allowed. These expectations concerning future behavior do not only involve the pair, but also the other members of the social group who are supposed to support the relationship, and not to disturb it by cheating. Anybody who breaks the agreement risks punishment by the entire group. Thus in order to maintain such bonds as marital bonds, they must be linked to social sanctions. 7 For an analysis of different levels of a theory of mind, see Gärdenfors [24], ch. 4 and Gärdenfors [27].

12 12 Peter Gärdenfors Cooperation based on conventions In human societies, many forms of cooperation are based on conventions. Conventions assume common beliefs (often called common knowledge). If two cars meet on a narrow gravel road in Australia, then both drivers know that this co-ordination problem has been solved numerous times before by passing on the left. Both know that both know this, both know that both know that both know this, etc., and so they pass on the left without any hesitation [46]. Many conventions are established without explicit communication; but, of course, communication makes the presence of a convention clearer. Conventions function as virtual governors in a society. Successful conventions create equilibrium points that, once established, tend to be stable. The convention of driving on the left forces me to get into step and drive on the left. The same applies to language itself: a new member of any society must adjust to the predominant language of the community. The collective meaning of all the linguistic utterances emerges from individuals individual meanings. 8 There is, of course, a potentially infinite number of possible equilibrium languages in a society. The point is that, once a language has developed, it will both strongly constrain and have strong explanatory effects regarding the behavior of individuals in the society. Similarly, the existence of money depends on a web of conventions. Money requires cooperation in the form of a mutual agreement to accept e.g. certain decorative pieces of paper as a medium of exchange for goods or labor. As a member of a monetary society, or as a visitor to one, I must get into step and accept the conventional medium of exchange as legal tender. Money is an example of social software [61] that improves the cooperation within a society. Actually, there are many similarities between language and money as tools for cooperation. Humans have been trading goods for as long as they have existed. When a monetary system does emerge, it makes certain transactions more efficient. The same applies to language: hominids were communicating long before they had a language, but language makes the exchange of information more efficient. The analogy carries further. When money is introduced into a society, a stable system of prices normally emerges. Similarly, when linguistic communication is introduced, individuals come to share a relatively stable space of meanings: i.e., components of their private worlds that, as communicators, they can publicly exchange between each other. In this way, language fosters a common structure to the private worlds of the individual members in a society (see [29]). In general, the social framework we construct, in the form of e.g. our institutions, increases the possibilities for establishing contracts, conventions, and other matters of the social good. 8 This emergence of a social dimension to language is analysed in detail in Gärdenfors [23] and Gärdenfors and Warglien [29].

13 1 The Cognitive and Communicative Demands of Cooperation The cooperation of Homo economicus Homo economicus, the rational human, is an idealization, typically assumed to have perfect reasoning powers. He is fully logically consistent, a perfect Bayesian when it comes to probability judgements, and a devoted maximiser of utility. He possesses a complete theory of mind: he can put himself fully into the shoes of his opponents (as they can with him) and see them as fellow perfect Bayesians reasoning about the possible equilibrium strategies in the game in which he is playing. When he communicates, his messages have a logically unambiguous meaning. He cooperates, if and only if such cooperation maximizes his utility according to the rules of the game. Similar idealizations are made in analysing cooperation, using epistemic and deontic logics or so called belief-desire-intention logics. The semantics is, typically, formulated in terms of possible worlds. This leads, of course, to unrealistic assumptions of strict logical consistency, unbounded self-reflective powers, and unlimited recursive knowledge attribution as Verbrugge [85, p. 657] points out. The traditional logical approaches cannot be used as realistic models of human cooperation. Several suggestions have recently been presented for how one might generalize the logical approach to provide such models [83, 85]. The problem with Homo economicus is that he seldom faces up to the complexities of reality, where the rules of the game are not well defined, where the possible outcomes and available strategies may vary from minute to minute, where the utilities of the various outcomes are uncertain if not unknown, where reasoning time and memory resources are limited, where communication is vague and prone to misunderstandings, and where his opponents are idiosyncratic and have all manner of cognitive shortcomings. Trivers [82, p. 79] writes: I know of no species, humans included, that leaves any part of its biology at the laboratory door; not prior expectations, nor natural proclivities, nor ongoing physiology, nor arms or legs, nor whatever. Game theory has, almost exclusively, studied strategies within a fixed and clearly defined game. In nature, it is more realistic to speak of strategies that can be used in a variety of different but related games. How should one rationally act when meeting an opponent face to face, given all kinds of biological constraints, knowing that one s opponent is not fully rational, but not knowing what the opponent s exact limitations? Game theory without biology is esoteric at best; with biology, it becomes as complicated as life itself (see e.g. [19]). 1.3 The effects of communication on cooperation I want to distinguish between, on the one hand, communication that involves a choice (conscious or not) by some individual to send some signal; and, on the other

14 14 Peter Gärdenfors hand, mere signaling without such intention. 9 Thus a caterpillar, though by its bright colors signals that it is poisonous, is not communicating. By this definition, communication becomes, in itself, a trust-based cooperative strategy. (Of course, communication can be abused: what the sender communicates may be a deliberate lie intended to mislead the receiver.) When a communicator sends a message, the receiver may not, initially, be able to interpret the intended meaning of the message. However, over iterated interactions, a message may develop a fairly fixed meaning. Lewis [46] introduced a gametheoretic account to conventions of meaning, according to which signals transmit information as a result of an evolutionary process. A variety of computer simulations and robotic experiments (e.g. [74, 75]), have shown how a stable communication system can emerge out of iterated interactions between (natural or) artificial agents, even though nobody determines any rules for the communications. The greater the number of signalers and recipients involved, the stronger the convergence of reference and the faster the convergence is attained. The addition of communication to a prisoner s-dilemma-type game changes the space of strategies in the game. In game theory, it has widely been assumed that signals that cost nothing are of no significance to any games that are not purely of common interest; even while evolutionary biologists have emphasized signals that are designed to be so costly that they (effectively) cannot be faked [88]. In contrast, Skyrms [72] shows how, in the stag hunt game and in another bargaining game, costless signals have dramatic effects on the game dynamics compared to the same games. The mere presence of signals creates new equilibria and shifts the basins of attraction of old equilibria. To wit: even if communication is not strictly necessary for all of the forms of cooperation listed above, adding it to a game may drastically change the game s structure. Such an effect was first pointed out by Robson [67] with respect to a population of defectors in an evolutionary setting of the prisoner s dilemma game. A signal that is not used by the population at large can be used by mutant members as a kind of secret handshake to identify an in-group. Mutants can then cooperate with those who share the secret handshake and defect against the others. They would perform better than pure defectors and invade the population. Without the availability of signaling, pure defection would be the evolutionarily more stable strategy. Van Schaik and Kappeler [84, p. 9] argue that, even without anything as sophisticated as a secret handshake, communication about the intentions of each player before the interactions and negotiation with them about payoffs is likely to make reciprocity much more stable than under the conditions of prisoner s dilemma games. Thus communication before engaging in risky cooperation is frequently observed in primates. In traditional game theory, the moves in a game are assumed to be fixed. Either the players cannot communicate at all, or else they have access to full linguistic communication. From an evolutionary perspective such extremes are not very realistic. In many natural settings, the inter-actors can communicate in some at least limited 9 This is in contrast to e.g. Hauser [38], who uses communication to also include all forms of signals.

15 1 The Cognitive and Communicative Demands of Cooperation 15 way, and there is almost always the possibility to create a new signal, which immediately multiplies the number of possible moves in the game. Taking these factors into account means that a game-theoretic analysis done originally along traditional lines becomes immensely more complicated. Already the simple communication strategies analysed by Skyrms [72] bear witness of this. An animal can communicate in various ways without employing much in the way of cognitive capacity. A system of signals can reach a communicative equilibrium without actively exploiting any cognitive capacities of the participants. However, as soon as one introduces the theory of mind and the strong tendency to assign meanings to signals that one finds in humans, the game-theoretic situation becomes yet more complex again. To give but one example of the powerful effects of communication: Mohlin and Johannesson [52] investigated the effects of communication on a dictator variation of the prisoner s dilemma game, where the dictator decides how much of an allotted amount to give to a recipient. They compared one-way written communication from an anonymous recipient to no communication, and found that communication increases donations by more than 70 percent. In order to eliminate any relationship effect from communication, another test condition was designed, to allow communication from a third party. donations were still about 40 percent higher than in the condition with no communication, suggesting that even the impersonal content of communication affects donations. Charness and Dufwenberg s [11] notion of guilt aversion provides one possible rationale for the effects of this endogenous communication : the dictator suffers from guilt if he hurts the recipients relative to what they believe that they will receive. By taking guilt into account, the dictator can be seen to exhibit some understanding of the minds of his subjects, or at least of their desires. Communication may affect the dictator s beliefs and, in this way, influence any allocation to the recipient. One might reasonably expect that, on such an account, communication from a bystander will have less effect than a direct message from a recipient, even an anonymous one. 1.4 Conclusion Traditional analysis of cooperation in game theory assumes fully rational and fully intersubjective participants. In contrast, evolutionary game theory assumes no rationality and no intersubjectivity, but relies on evolutionary mechanisms for the establishment of cooperation. However, for most forms of animal and human cooperation, the truth falls somewhere in between. I have shown how different forms of cooperation build on different cognitive and communicative capacities. The reason why certain forms of cooperation are so far found only among humans is that those forms of cooperation presuppose a high awareness of future needs, a rich understanding of the minds of others, and availability of symbolic communication.

16 16 Peter Gärdenfors The somewhat eclectic list of forms of cooperation and their cognitive and communicative prerequisites, as presented above, is summarized in the following table: Type of cooperation Cognitive demands Communicative demands Flocking behavior Perception None In-group out-group Reciprocal altruism (attitudinal reciprocity) Reciprocal altruism (calculated reciprocity) Indirect reciprocity Cooperation about future goals Recognition of group member None Individual recognition, minimal memory, understanding the desires None of others Individual recognition, memory, slow temporal None discounting, value comparison Individual recognition, memory, slow temporal Proto-symbolic (mimetic) communication discounting, value comparison, minimal theory of mind (empathy) Individual recognition, memory, prospective Symbolic communication (protolanguage) planning, value comparison, more advanced theory of mind Individual recognition, Symbolic communication (protolanguage) Commitment and contract memory, prospective planning, joint belief Cooperation based on conventions The cooperation of Homo economicus Full theory of mind, perfect rationality Theory of mind that allows common knowledge None, but enhanced by symbolic communication Perfect symbolic communication Table 1: The cognitive and communicative demands of different forms of cooperation. The different kinds of cooperation presented here are ordered according to increasing cognitive demands. They certainly do not exhaust the field of possibilities, and there is a real need to make finer divisions within the forms presented. Nevertheless,

17 1 The Cognitive and Communicative Demands of Cooperation 17 the table clearly shows how cognitive and communicative constraints are important factors when analysing evolutionary aspects of cooperation. Only humans are known to clearly exhibit reciprocal altruism, indirect reciprocity, cooperation on future goals, and cooperation based on conventions. 10 This correlates well with the cognitive factors that are required for these forms of cooperation. The analysis, or a more detailed version of it, can be used to make predictions about the forms of cooperation to be found in different species. For example, if a monkey species can be shown to be able to recognize members of one s own troop, and to remember and evaluate the results of previous encounters with individual members, even though two monkeys of that species cannot communicate about a third member, then the prediction is to expect reciprocal altruism but not indirect reciprocity between the members of the species. In this way, a causal link from cognitive capacities to cooperative behaviors can be established. Conversely, but perhaps less reliably, if a species does not exhibit a particular form of cooperative behavior, it can be expected not to possess the required cognitive or communicative capacities. The analysis can also be turned into a tool for predictions about the evolution of cognition in hominids. Osvath and Gärdenfors [59] argue that the first traces of prospective planning are to be found during the Oldowan culture 2.5 million years ago. It is reasonable to assume that the forms of cooperation toward future goals that depend on this form of cognition had already been established by then. Conversely, if the archaeological record of some hominid activities provides evidence for certain types of cooperation, one can reasonably assume that the hominids had developed the cognitive and communicative skills necessary for that form of cooperation. This may, in turn, generate predictions concerning brain structure and other matters of physiology. Acknowledgements This article is an expanded and updated version of an article by the same title that was published electronically in the Festschrift Hommage à Wlodek for Wlodek Rabinowicz in January 2007 (see It also overlaps with Gärdenfors [27]. I would like to thank two anonymous referees as well as Barbara Dunin-Kȩplicz, Jan van Eijck, Martin van Hees, Kristian Lindgren, Erik Olsson, Mathias Osvath, Rohit Parikh, Erik Persson, Wlodek Rabinowicz, Robert Sugden, Rineke Verbrugge, and Annika Wallin. I would also thank the members of the seminars in cognitive science and philosophy at Lund University and the members of the project group on Games, Action and Social Software at the Netherlands Institute for Advanced Studies for very helpful comments on drafts of the paper. I also want to thank the Netherlands Institute for Advanced Studies for excellent 10 As mentioned above, whether other species engage in reciprocal altruism is open to some controversy.

Games, Actions, and Social Software JAN VAN EIJCK AND RINEKE VERBRUGGE (EDS.)

Games, Actions, and Social Software JAN VAN EIJCK AND RINEKE VERBRUGGE (EDS.) Games, Actions, and Social Software JAN VAN EIJCK AND RINEKE VERBRUGGE (EDS.) AUGUST 22, 2010 Contents Chapter 1. The Cognitive and Communicative Demands of Cooperation 5 1. The span of cooperation in

More information

Altruism. Why Are Organisms Ever Altruistic? Kin Selection. Reciprocal Altruism. Costly Signaling. Group Selection?

Altruism. Why Are Organisms Ever Altruistic? Kin Selection. Reciprocal Altruism. Costly Signaling. Group Selection? Altruism Nepotism Common-Pool Resource (CPR) Tragedy of the Commons Public Good Free-riders Competitive Altruism A 1987 Florida news story reported that 22 blood donors who had false positives on an HIV

More information

The Evolution of Cooperation

The Evolution of Cooperation Cooperative Alliances Problems of Group Living The Evolution of Cooperation The problem of altruism Definition of reproductive altruism: An individual behaves in such a way as to enhance the reproduction

More information

Reciprocity, Cooperation, and Reputation

Reciprocity, Cooperation, and Reputation Reciprocity, Cooperation, and Reputation Reciprocal altruism Prisoner s dilemma: repeated play allows cooperation Generosity, punishment, spite (Ultimatum games) Reputation Collective action and punishment

More information

Strong Reciprocity and Human Sociality

Strong Reciprocity and Human Sociality Notes on Behavioral Economics 1 Strong Reciprocity and Human Sociality Human groups are highly social despite a low level of relatedness. There is an empirically identifiable form of prosocial behavior

More information

Title. Author(s)Takahashi, Nobuyuki. Issue Date Doc URL. Type. Note. File Information. Adaptive Bases of Human Rationality

Title. Author(s)Takahashi, Nobuyuki. Issue Date Doc URL. Type. Note. File Information. Adaptive Bases of Human Rationality Title Adaptive Bases of Human Rationality Author(s)Takahashi, Nobuyuki SOCREAL 2007: Proceedings of the International Works CitationJapan, 2007 / editor Tomoyuki Yamada: 1(71)-34(104) Issue Date 2007 Doc

More information

Book review: The Calculus of Selfishness, by Karl Sigmund

Book review: The Calculus of Selfishness, by Karl Sigmund Book review: The Calculus of Selfishness, by Karl Sigmund Olle Häggström Leading game theorist Karl Sigmund calls his latest book The Calculus of Selfishness, although arguably The Calculus of Cooperation

More information

Literature Henrich, Joseph, and Natalie Henrich Why Humans Cooperate A Cultural and Evolutionary Explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press

Literature Henrich, Joseph, and Natalie Henrich Why Humans Cooperate A Cultural and Evolutionary Explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press INSTITUTIONS AND INSTITUTIONAL DESIGN Erling Berge Henrich and Henrich 2007 Why Humans Cooperate Literature Henrich, Joseph, and Natalie Henrich. 2007. Why Humans Cooperate A Cultural and Evolutionary

More information

Indirect Reciprocity and the Evolution of Moral Signals

Indirect Reciprocity and the Evolution of Moral Signals Indirect Reciprocity and the Evolution of Moral Signals Department of Logic and Philosophy of Science University of California, Irvine Evolution of Psychological Categories - IMBS March 16, 2008 Moral

More information

Social Norms and Reciprocity*

Social Norms and Reciprocity* Social Norms and Reciprocity* Andreas Diekmann Institut für Soziologie Universität Bern Thomas Voss Institut für Soziologie Universität Leipzig [ March 2003 ] Paper presented on the session Solidarity

More information

Irrationality in Game Theory

Irrationality in Game Theory Irrationality in Game Theory Yamin Htun Dec 9, 2005 Abstract The concepts in game theory have been evolving in such a way that existing theories are recasted to apply to problems that previously appeared

More information

Reciprocity, Cooperation, and Reputation

Reciprocity, Cooperation, and Reputation Reciprocity, Cooperation, and Reputation Reciprocal altruism Prisoner s dilemma: repeated play allows cooperation Generosity, punishment, spite (Ultimatum games) Reputation Before next lecture, see intentionality

More information

Conditional behavior affects the level of evolved cooperation in public good games

Conditional behavior affects the level of evolved cooperation in public good games Center for the Study of Institutional Diversity CSID Working Paper Series #CSID-2013-007 Conditional behavior affects the level of evolved cooperation in public good games Marco A. Janssen Arizona State

More information

CONCEPT OF PROSOCIAL BEHAVIOR

CONCEPT OF PROSOCIAL BEHAVIOR FAQ CONCEPT OF PROSOCIAL BEHAVIOR 1Q: Explain prosocial behavior, helping behavior and altruism. What is the difference between helping behavior and altruism? Ans: As the word indicates, prosocial behavior

More information

good reputation, and less chance to be chosen as potential partners. Fourth, not everyone values a good reputation to the same extent.

good reputation, and less chance to be chosen as potential partners. Fourth, not everyone values a good reputation to the same extent. English Summary 128 English summary English Summary S ocial dilemmas emerge when people experience a conflict between their immediate personal interest and the long-term collective interest of the group

More information

The Evolutionary Foundations of Strong Reciprocity

The Evolutionary Foundations of Strong Reciprocity Analyse & Kritik 29/2005 ( c Lucius & Lucius, Stuttgart) p. xxx xxx J. McKenzie Alexander The Evolutionary Foundations of Strong Reciprocity To say that people cooperate, trust, offer more than is logically

More information

Altruistic Behavior: Lessons from Neuroeconomics. Kei Yoshida Postdoctoral Research Fellow University of Tokyo Center for Philosophy (UTCP)

Altruistic Behavior: Lessons from Neuroeconomics. Kei Yoshida Postdoctoral Research Fellow University of Tokyo Center for Philosophy (UTCP) Altruistic Behavior: Lessons from Neuroeconomics Kei Yoshida Postdoctoral Research Fellow University of Tokyo Center for Philosophy (UTCP) Table of Contents 1. The Emergence of Neuroeconomics, or the Decline

More information

Clicker quiz: Should the cocaine trade be legalized? (either answer will tell us if you are here or not) 1. yes 2. no

Clicker quiz: Should the cocaine trade be legalized? (either answer will tell us if you are here or not) 1. yes 2. no Clicker quiz: Should the cocaine trade be legalized? (either answer will tell us if you are here or not) 1. yes 2. no Economic Liberalism Summary: Assumptions: self-interest, rationality, individual freedom

More information

IN THE iterated prisoner s dilemma (IPD), two players

IN THE iterated prisoner s dilemma (IPD), two players IEEE TRANSACTIONS ON EVOLUTIONARY COMPUTATION, VOL. 11, NO. 6, DECEMBER 2007 689 Multiple Choices and Reputation in Multiagent Interactions Siang Yew Chong, Member, IEEE, and Xin Yao, Fellow, IEEE Abstract

More information

Institutions and Cooperative Behavior

Institutions and Cooperative Behavior Institutions and Cooperative Behavior by Arild Vatn Department of International Environmental and Development Studies Norwegian University of Life Sciences Complexity Economics for Sustainability Seminar

More information

University of Zurich. The social side of Homo economicus. Zurich Open Repository and Archive. Rankin, D J. Year: 2011

University of Zurich. The social side of Homo economicus. Zurich Open Repository and Archive. Rankin, D J. Year: 2011 University of Zurich Zurich Open Repository and Archive Winterthurerstr. CH-0 Zurich http://www.zora.uzh.ch Year: 0 The social side of Homo economicus Rankin, D J Rankin, D J (0). The social side of Homo

More information

The Game Prisoners Really Play: Preference Elicitation and the Impact of Communication

The Game Prisoners Really Play: Preference Elicitation and the Impact of Communication The Game Prisoners Really Play: Preference Elicitation and the Impact of Communication Michael Kosfeld University of Zurich Ernst Fehr University of Zurich October 10, 2003 Unfinished version: Please do

More information

Indirect reciprocity and the evolution of moral signals

Indirect reciprocity and the evolution of moral signals Biol Philos (2010) 25:33 51 DOI 10.1007/s10539-009-9175-9 Indirect reciprocity and the evolution of moral signals Rory Smead Received: 2 November 2008 / Accepted: 23 June 2009 / Published online: 9 July

More information

By Olivia Smith and Steven van de Put Third Year, Second Prize

By Olivia Smith and Steven van de Put Third Year, Second Prize Are humans always the rational, self-interested agents that mainstream economics assumes them to be? Discuss, using ideas of reciprocity, altruism and fairness By Olivia Smith and Steven van de Put Third

More information

Introduction to Game Theory Autonomous Agents and MultiAgent Systems 2015/2016

Introduction to Game Theory Autonomous Agents and MultiAgent Systems 2015/2016 Introduction to Game Theory Autonomous Agents and MultiAgent Systems 2015/2016 Ana Paiva * These slides are based on the book by Prof. M. Woodridge An Introduction to Multiagent Systems and the online

More information

Jakub Steiner The University of Edinburgh. Abstract

Jakub Steiner The University of Edinburgh. Abstract A trace of anger is enough: on the enforcement of social norms Jakub Steiner The University of Edinburgh Abstract It is well documented that the possibility of punishing free-riders increases contributions

More information

Emanuela Carbonara. 31 January University of Bologna - Department of Economics

Emanuela Carbonara. 31 January University of Bologna - Department of Economics Game Theory, Behavior and The Law - I A brief introduction to game theory. Rules of the game and equilibrium concepts. Behavioral Games: Ultimatum and Dictator Games. Entitlement and Framing effects. Emanuela

More information

Further Properties of the Priority Rule

Further Properties of the Priority Rule Further Properties of the Priority Rule Michael Strevens Draft of July 2003 Abstract In Strevens (2003), I showed that science s priority system for distributing credit promotes an allocation of labor

More information

The Evolution of Cooperation: The Genetic Algorithm Applied to Three Normal- Form Games

The Evolution of Cooperation: The Genetic Algorithm Applied to Three Normal- Form Games The Evolution of Cooperation: The Genetic Algorithm Applied to Three Normal- Form Games Scott Cederberg P.O. Box 595 Stanford, CA 949 (65) 497-7776 (cederber@stanford.edu) Abstract The genetic algorithm

More information

A Comment on the Absent-Minded Driver Paradox*

A Comment on the Absent-Minded Driver Paradox* Ž. GAMES AND ECONOMIC BEHAVIOR 20, 25 30 1997 ARTICLE NO. GA970508 A Comment on the Absent-Minded Driver Paradox* Itzhak Gilboa MEDS KGSM, Northwestern Uni ersity, E anston, Illinois 60201 Piccione and

More information

INTERVIEWS II: THEORIES AND TECHNIQUES 5. CLINICAL APPROACH TO INTERVIEWING PART 1

INTERVIEWS II: THEORIES AND TECHNIQUES 5. CLINICAL APPROACH TO INTERVIEWING PART 1 INTERVIEWS II: THEORIES AND TECHNIQUES 5. CLINICAL APPROACH TO INTERVIEWING PART 1 5.1 Clinical Interviews: Background Information The clinical interview is a technique pioneered by Jean Piaget, in 1975,

More information

Autonomy as a Positive Value Some Conceptual Prerequisites Niklas Juth Dept. of Philosophy, Göteborg University

Autonomy as a Positive Value Some Conceptual Prerequisites Niklas Juth Dept. of Philosophy, Göteborg University Philosophical Communications, Web Series, No. 28 Dept. of Philosophy, Göteborg University, Sweden ISSN 1652-0459 Autonomy as a Positive Value Some Conceptual Prerequisites Niklas Juth Dept. of Philosophy,

More information

An Experimental Investigation of Self-Serving Biases in an Auditing Trust Game: The Effect of Group Affiliation: Discussion

An Experimental Investigation of Self-Serving Biases in an Auditing Trust Game: The Effect of Group Affiliation: Discussion 1 An Experimental Investigation of Self-Serving Biases in an Auditing Trust Game: The Effect of Group Affiliation: Discussion Shyam Sunder, Yale School of Management P rofessor King has written an interesting

More information

Today s lecture. A thought experiment. Topic 3: Social preferences and fairness. Overview readings: Fehr and Fischbacher (2002) Sobel (2005)

Today s lecture. A thought experiment. Topic 3: Social preferences and fairness. Overview readings: Fehr and Fischbacher (2002) Sobel (2005) Topic 3: Social preferences and fairness Are we perfectly selfish? If not, does it affect economic analysis? How to take it into account? Overview readings: Fehr and Fischbacher (2002) Sobel (2005) Today

More information

Comments on David Rosenthal s Consciousness, Content, and Metacognitive Judgments

Comments on David Rosenthal s Consciousness, Content, and Metacognitive Judgments Consciousness and Cognition 9, 215 219 (2000) doi:10.1006/ccog.2000.0438, available online at http://www.idealibrary.com on Comments on David Rosenthal s Consciousness, Content, and Metacognitive Judgments

More information

A Foundation for Behavioral Economics

A Foundation for Behavioral Economics A Foundation for Behavioral Economics Jessica L. Cohen and William T. Dickens The Brookings Institution Paper Presented at the Meetings of the American Economics Association December 2001 Later Published

More information

Models of Parent-Offspring Conflict Ethology and Behavioral Ecology

Models of Parent-Offspring Conflict Ethology and Behavioral Ecology Models of Parent-Offspring Conflict Ethology and Behavioral Ecology A. In this section we will look the nearly universal conflict that will eventually arise in any species where there is some form of parental

More information

Reinforcement Learning : Theory and Practice - Programming Assignment 1

Reinforcement Learning : Theory and Practice - Programming Assignment 1 Reinforcement Learning : Theory and Practice - Programming Assignment 1 August 2016 Background It is well known in Game Theory that the game of Rock, Paper, Scissors has one and only one Nash Equilibrium.

More information

Why we cooperate? The evolution of collective action" " Autonomous Agents and MultiAgent Systems, 2014/15!

Why we cooperate? The evolution of collective action  Autonomous Agents and MultiAgent Systems, 2014/15! Why we cooperate? The evolution of collective action" " Autonomous Agents and MultiAgent Systems, 2014/15! Francisco C. Santos Instituto Superior Técnico, Universidade de Lisboa & GAIPS / INESC-ID, Portugal

More information

Answers to end of chapter questions

Answers to end of chapter questions Answers to end of chapter questions Chapter 1 What are the three most important characteristics of QCA as a method of data analysis? QCA is (1) systematic, (2) flexible, and (3) it reduces data. What are

More information

UNCORRECTED PAGE PROOFS

UNCORRECTED PAGE PROOFS 462 U2 AOS1: Interpersonal behaviour Research methods and ethics Case study 1 Emotional and behavioural responses to racism Kawakami and colleagues (2009) predicted that one reason why racism and prejudice

More information

reward based power have ability to give you what you want. coercive have power to punish

reward based power have ability to give you what you want. coercive have power to punish Chapter 7 Finding and Using Negotiation Power Why Power Important to Negotiators? Seeking power in negotiations from 1 of 2 perceptions: 1. Negotiator believes he has less power than other party 2. Negotiator

More information

Cooperation and Collective Action

Cooperation and Collective Action Cooperation and Collective Action A basic design Determinants of voluntary cooperation Marginal private benefits Group size Communication Why do people cooperate? Strategic cooperation Cooperation as a

More information

Assignment 4: True or Quasi-Experiment

Assignment 4: True or Quasi-Experiment Assignment 4: True or Quasi-Experiment Objectives: After completing this assignment, you will be able to Evaluate when you must use an experiment to answer a research question Develop statistical hypotheses

More information

ULTIMATUM GAME. An Empirical Evidence. Presented By: SHAHID RAZZAQUE

ULTIMATUM GAME. An Empirical Evidence. Presented By: SHAHID RAZZAQUE 1 ULTIMATUM GAME An Empirical Evidence Presented By: SHAHID RAZZAQUE 2 Difference Between Self-Interest, Preference & Social Preference Preference refers to the choices people make & particularly to tradeoffs

More information

A Note On the Design of Experiments Involving Public Goods

A Note On the Design of Experiments Involving Public Goods University of Colorado From the SelectedWorks of PHILIP E GRAVES 2009 A Note On the Design of Experiments Involving Public Goods PHILIP E GRAVES, University of Colorado at Boulder Available at: https://works.bepress.com/philip_graves/40/

More information

Color Cues and Viscosity in. Iterated Prisoner s Dilemma

Color Cues and Viscosity in. Iterated Prisoner s Dilemma Color Cues and Viscosity in Iterated Prisoner s Dilemma Michael Joya University of British Columbia Abstract The presence of color tag cues and a viscous environment have each been shown to foster conditional

More information

Koji Kotani International University of Japan. Abstract

Koji Kotani International University of Japan. Abstract Further investigations of framing effects on cooperative choices in a provision point mechanism Koji Kotani International University of Japan Shunsuke Managi Yokohama National University Kenta Tanaka Yokohama

More information

Evolutionary game theory and cognition

Evolutionary game theory and cognition Evolutionary game theory and cognition Artem Kaznatcheev School of Computer Science & Department of Psychology McGill University November 15, 2012 Artem Kaznatcheev (McGill University) Evolutionary game

More information

The Social Maintenance of Cooperation through Hypocrisy

The Social Maintenance of Cooperation through Hypocrisy The Social Maintenance of Cooperation through Hypocrisy Todd J Bodnar, Marcel Salathé Department of Biology, Penn State University University Park, PA 18062, USA *Corresponding authors: Marcel Salathé,

More information

Social Status and Group Norms: Indirect Reciprocity in a Helping Experiment

Social Status and Group Norms: Indirect Reciprocity in a Helping Experiment Social Status and Group Norms: Indirect Reciprocity in a Helping Experiment Ingrid Seinen and Arthur Schram CREED Department of Economics and Econometrics University of Amsterdam Roetersstraat 11 1018

More information

Lee's Martial Arts. The Five Principles. Principle #1: Preventive Defense. Principle #2: Awareness

Lee's Martial Arts. The Five Principles. Principle #1: Preventive Defense. Principle #2: Awareness The Five Principles Principle #1: Preventive Defense Preventive Defense is to always respect. Do not offend anyone verbally or physically to cause a confrontation. Respect Rule 1: Watch what you think,

More information

The Attribute Index - Leadership

The Attribute Index - Leadership 26-Jan-2007 0.88 / 0.74 The Attribute Index - Leadership Innermetrix, Inc. Innermetrix Talent Profile of Innermetrix, Inc. http://www.innermetrix.cc/ The Attribute Index - Leadership Patterns Patterns

More information

The function or adaptive value of signals has been broken down into the following classes:

The function or adaptive value of signals has been broken down into the following classes: Communication notes.doc 1 Communication and signals an action on the part of one animal that alters the behavior of another (Wilson 1975). The essence of communication is the relationship between signaler

More information

Effective Intentions: The Power of Conscious Will

Effective Intentions: The Power of Conscious Will Book Review Effective Intentions: The Power of Conscious Will Alfred R. Mele Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2009 Marco Fenici* fenici@unisi.it Mele s book is a concise analysis of much research in neurophysiology

More information

Evolution of Cooperation

Evolution of Cooperation Evolution of Cooperation 5 and 7 Abstract Nature has produced cooperating communities in virtually every environment independently. This suggests that there are very simple, elegant rules that sustain

More information

5.8 Departure from cognitivism: dynamical systems

5.8 Departure from cognitivism: dynamical systems 154 consciousness, on the other, was completely severed (Thompson, 2007a, p. 5). Consequently as Thompson claims cognitivism works with inadequate notion of cognition. This statement is at odds with practical

More information

Trust and Reciprocity, Interdisciplinary Lessons from Experimental Research

Trust and Reciprocity, Interdisciplinary Lessons from Experimental Research Page 1 Trust and Reciprocity, Interdisciplinary Lessons from Experimental Research By Elinor Ostrom and James Walker SUMMARY Elinor Ostrom and James Walker wrote Trust and Reciprocity on the results of

More information

An Escalation Model of Consciousness

An Escalation Model of Consciousness Bailey!1 Ben Bailey Current Issues in Cognitive Science Mark Feinstein 2015-12-18 An Escalation Model of Consciousness Introduction The idea of consciousness has plagued humanity since its inception. Humans

More information

Benchmarks 4th Grade. Greet others and make introductions. Communicate information effectively about a given topic

Benchmarks 4th Grade. Greet others and make introductions. Communicate information effectively about a given topic Benchmarks 4th Grade Understand what it means to be a 4-H member Participate in 4-H club meetings by saying pledges, completing activities and being engaged. Recite the 4-H pledge from memory Identify

More information

Reduce Tension by Making the Desired Choice Easier

Reduce Tension by Making the Desired Choice Easier Daniel Kahneman Talk at Social and Behavioral Sciences Meeting at OEOB Reduce Tension by Making the Desired Choice Easier Here is one of the best theoretical ideas that psychology has to offer developed

More information

How rational are your decisions? Neuroeconomics

How rational are your decisions? Neuroeconomics How rational are your decisions? Neuroeconomics Hecke CNS Seminar WS 2006/07 Motivation Motivation Ferdinand Porsche "Wir wollen Autos bauen, die keiner braucht aber jeder haben will." Outline 1 Introduction

More information

utility is Simon Blackburn: Ruling Passions ChaPter 6 Game Theory and Rational choice $ Philosophical Egoism The principle of maximizingexpected

utility is Simon Blackburn: Ruling Passions ChaPter 6 Game Theory and Rational choice $ Philosophical Egoism The principle of maximizingexpected Simon Blackburn: Ruling Passions ChaPter 6 Game Theory and Rational choice $ Philosophical Egoism The principle of maximizingexpected utility is definitional: a grid imposed uponthe processes of interpreting

More information

A Cognitive Model of Strategic Deliberation and Decision Making

A Cognitive Model of Strategic Deliberation and Decision Making A Cognitive Model of Strategic Deliberation and Decision Making Russell Golman (rgolman@andrew.cmu.edu) Carnegie Mellon University, Pittsburgh, PA. Sudeep Bhatia (bhatiasu@sas.upenn.edu) University of

More information

Why do Psychologists Perform Research?

Why do Psychologists Perform Research? PSY 102 1 PSY 102 Understanding and Thinking Critically About Psychological Research Thinking critically about research means knowing the right questions to ask to assess the validity or accuracy of a

More information

How to stop Someone who is ADDICTED ENABLING

How to stop Someone who is ADDICTED ENABLING stop ENABLING Table of Contents 2 Are You an Enabler? What if the steps you were taking to help a friend or family member through a problem or crisis were actually the very things hurting them most? And,

More information

In his essay The Truth in Psychological Egoism, Hugh Lafollette uses a modified version

In his essay The Truth in Psychological Egoism, Hugh Lafollette uses a modified version Ashton Payne 100832968 Moral Psychology: PHIL2550 July 25 th, 2014 Part I: In his essay The Truth in Psychological Egoism, Hugh Lafollette uses a modified version of psychological egoism (henceforth PE)

More information

BIRKMAN REPORT THIS REPORT WAS PREPARED FOR: JOHN Q. PUBLIC (D00112) ANDREW DEMO (G526VC) DATE PRINTED February

BIRKMAN REPORT THIS REPORT WAS PREPARED FOR: JOHN Q. PUBLIC (D00112) ANDREW DEMO (G526VC) DATE PRINTED February BIRKMAN REPORT THIS REPORT WAS PREPARED FOR: JOHN Q. PUBLIC (D00112) ANDREW DEMO (G526VC) DATE PRINTED February 28 2018 Most of what we hear is an opinion, not a fact. Most of what we see is a perspective,

More information

Resource Management: INSTITUTIONS AND INSTITUTIONAL DESIGN. SOS3508 Erling Berge. A grammar of institutions. NTNU, Trondheim.

Resource Management: INSTITUTIONS AND INSTITUTIONAL DESIGN. SOS3508 Erling Berge. A grammar of institutions. NTNU, Trondheim. Resource Management: INSTITUTIONS AND INSTITUTIONAL DESIGN SOS3508 Erling Berge A grammar of institutions NTNU, Trondheim Fall 2009 Erling Berge 2009 Fall 2009 1 Literature Ostrom, Elinor 2005, Understanding

More information

STRONG RECIPROCITY, HUMAN COOPERATION, AND THE ENFORCEMENT OF SOCIAL NORMS

STRONG RECIPROCITY, HUMAN COOPERATION, AND THE ENFORCEMENT OF SOCIAL NORMS STRONG RECIPROCITY, HUMAN COOPERATION, AND THE ENFORCEMENT OF SOCIAL NORMS Ernst Fehr, Urs Fischbacher University of Z~irich and Simon G~ichter University of St. Gallen This paper provides strong evidence

More information

DIFFERENCES IN THE ECONOMIC DECISIONS OF MEN AND WOMEN: EXPERIMENTAL EVIDENCE*

DIFFERENCES IN THE ECONOMIC DECISIONS OF MEN AND WOMEN: EXPERIMENTAL EVIDENCE* DIFFERENCES IN THE ECONOMIC DECISIONS OF MEN AND WOMEN: EXPERIMENTAL EVIDENCE* Catherine C. Eckel Department of Economics Virginia Tech Blacksburg, VA 24061-0316 Philip J. Grossman Department of Economics

More information

ETHICAL CONSIDERATION OF CONSTRUCTION UNION STRATEGIES IN JURISDICTIONAL DISPUTES BASED ON AN AGENT-BASED MODELING (ABM) AND A GAME THEORY

ETHICAL CONSIDERATION OF CONSTRUCTION UNION STRATEGIES IN JURISDICTIONAL DISPUTES BASED ON AN AGENT-BASED MODELING (ABM) AND A GAME THEORY ETHICAL CONSIDERATION OF CONSTRUCTION UNION STRATEGIES IN JURISDICTIONAL DISPUTES BASED ON AN AGENT-BASED MODELING (ABM) AND A GAME THEORY Borinara Park* Associate Professor, Construction Management Program,

More information

Groups in Organizations. Overview of topics

Groups in Organizations. Overview of topics Groups in Organizations Overview of topics 1 Plan of today s lecture Groups general aspects Links with individual behavior Cohesion & conformity Decision making in groups 2 Characteristics of Groups Groups

More information

Team Reasoning and a Rank-Based Function of Team s Interests

Team Reasoning and a Rank-Based Function of Team s Interests Team Reasoning and a Rank-Based Function of Team s Interests Jurgis Karpus Mantas Radzvilas April 2015 Abstract Orthodox game theory is sometimes criticized for its failure to single out intuitively compelling

More information

Behavioral Game Theory

Behavioral Game Theory Outline (September 3, 2007) Outline (September 3, 2007) Introduction Outline (September 3, 2007) Introduction Examples of laboratory experiments Outline (September 3, 2007) Introduction Examples of laboratory

More information

Affective Social Ties without the Need to Belong?

Affective Social Ties without the Need to Belong? RMM Vol. 4, 2013, 20 27 Special Topic: Coevolving Relationships between Political Science and Economics Edited by Herbert David, Hartmut Kliemt and Elinor Ostrom http://www.rmm-journal.de/ Matthias Greiff

More information

SOCIAL PSYCHOLOGY. Social Influences on the Self. Self Concept. How do we see ourselves? How do we see others?

SOCIAL PSYCHOLOGY. Social Influences on the Self. Self Concept. How do we see ourselves? How do we see others? SOCIAL PSYCHOLOGY Social Cognition and Influence (how we think about ourselves) Social Influences on the Self How do we see ourselves? How do we see others? How do we compare ourselves with others? Self

More information

The scope of perceptual content, II: properties

The scope of perceptual content, II: properties The scope of perceptual content, II: properties Jeff Speaks November 16, 2009 1 What are the candidates?............................ 1 2 Arguments for inclusion............................. 2 2.1 From

More information

Lecture 2: Learning and Equilibrium Extensive-Form Games

Lecture 2: Learning and Equilibrium Extensive-Form Games Lecture 2: Learning and Equilibrium Extensive-Form Games III. Nash Equilibrium in Extensive Form Games IV. Self-Confirming Equilibrium and Passive Learning V. Learning Off-path Play D. Fudenberg Marshall

More information

SUPPLEMENTARY INFORMATION

SUPPLEMENTARY INFORMATION Supplementary Statistics and Results This file contains supplementary statistical information and a discussion of the interpretation of the belief effect on the basis of additional data. We also present

More information

Topic 3: Social preferences and fairness

Topic 3: Social preferences and fairness Topic 3: Social preferences and fairness Are we perfectly selfish and self-centered? If not, does it affect economic analysis? How to take it into account? Focus: Descriptive analysis Examples Will monitoring

More information

WORKING PAPER GAME DYNAMICAL ASPECTS OF THE PRISONER'S DILEMMA WP December Martin Novak Karl Sigmund

WORKING PAPER GAME DYNAMICAL ASPECTS OF THE PRISONER'S DILEMMA WP December Martin Novak Karl Sigmund WORKING PAPER GAME DYNAMICAL ASPECTS OF THE PRISONER'S DILEMMA Martin Novak Karl Sigmund December 1988 WP-88-125 L International Institute for Applied Systems Analysis GAME DYNAMICAL ASPECTS OF THE PRISONER'S

More information

The iterated Prisoner s dilemma

The iterated Prisoner s dilemma The iterated Prisoner s dilemma U. Sperhake DAMTP, University of Cambridge PHEP Seminar, University of Cambridge 22 nd March 2013 U. Sperhake (DAMTP, University of Cambridge) The iterated Prisoner s dilemma

More information

Chapter 2 Various Types of Social Dilemma

Chapter 2 Various Types of Social Dilemma Chapter 2 Various Types of Social Dilemma In order to examine the pragmatic methods of solving social dilemmas, it is important to understand the logical structure of dilemmas that underpin actual real-life

More information

A conversation with Professor David Chalmers, May 20, 2016 Participants

A conversation with Professor David Chalmers, May 20, 2016 Participants A conversation with Professor David Chalmers, May 20, 2016 Participants Professor David Chalmers Professor of Philosophy, New York University (NYU) Luke Muehlhauser Research Analyst, Open Philanthropy

More information

Managing Conflicts Around Medical Futility

Managing Conflicts Around Medical Futility Managing Conflicts Around Medical Futility Robert M. Taylor, MD Medical Director, OSUMC Center for Palliative Care Associate Professor of Neurology The Ohio State University James Cancer Hospital Objectives

More information

The weak side of informal social control Paper prepared for Conference Game Theory and Society. ETH Zürich, July 27-30, 2011

The weak side of informal social control Paper prepared for Conference Game Theory and Society. ETH Zürich, July 27-30, 2011 The weak side of informal social control Paper prepared for Conference Game Theory and Society. ETH Zürich, July 27-30, 2011 Andreas Flache Department of Sociology ICS University of Groningen Collective

More information

Marzano s Nine Top Strategies (part 1) *Similarities and Differences *Summarizing and Note Taking *Reinforcing Effort and Providing Recognition

Marzano s Nine Top Strategies (part 1) *Similarities and Differences *Summarizing and Note Taking *Reinforcing Effort and Providing Recognition Marzano s Nine Top Strategies (part 1) *Similarities and Differences *Summarizing and Note Taking *Reinforcing Effort and Providing Recognition Categories of Instructional Strategies That Affect Student

More information

Homo economicus is dead! How do we know how the mind works? How the mind works

Homo economicus is dead! How do we know how the mind works? How the mind works Some facts about social preferences, or why we're sometimes nice and sometimes not Karthik Panchanathan buddha@ucla.edu Homo economicus is dead! It was a mistake to believe that individuals and institutions

More information

Animal Behavior. How can we explain behavior? Behavior. Innate or instinctive behavior. Instinctive behavior. Instinctive behavior 11/26/2017

Animal Behavior. How can we explain behavior? Behavior. Innate or instinctive behavior. Instinctive behavior. Instinctive behavior 11/26/2017 Animal Behavior Chapter 51 How can we explain behavior? How it works physiologically Proximate answer The adaptive value of the behavior Ultimate answer So, behavioral scientists study what behavior an

More information

GUEN DONDÉ HEAD OF RESEARCH INSTITUTE OF BUSINESS ETHICS

GUEN DONDÉ HEAD OF RESEARCH INSTITUTE OF BUSINESS ETHICS WHAT DOES ETHICS AT WORK MEAN TO EMPLOYEES? GUEN DONDÉ HEAD OF RESEARCH INSTITUTE OF BUSINESS ETHICS IBE 05/07/2018 1 ABOUT THE IBE The IBE was established in 1986 to promote high standards of business

More information

Step 2 Challenging negative thoughts "Weeding"

Step 2 Challenging negative thoughts Weeding Managing Automatic Negative Thoughts (ANTs) Step 1 Identifying negative thoughts "ANTs" Step 2 Challenging negative thoughts "Weeding" Step 3 Planting positive thoughts 'Potting" Step1 Identifying Your

More information

INTRODUCTION TO SYMBOLIC INTERACTION: SYMBOLIC INTERACTION, PERSPECTIVES AND REFERENCE GROUPS LECTURE OUTLINE

INTRODUCTION TO SYMBOLIC INTERACTION: SYMBOLIC INTERACTION, PERSPECTIVES AND REFERENCE GROUPS LECTURE OUTLINE WEEK THREE Mon Sept 28, 2009 Tues Sept 29, 2009 INTRODUCTION TO SYMBOLIC INTERACTION: SYMBOLIC INTERACTION, PERSPECTIVES AND REFERENCE GROUPS LECTURE OUTLINE PART 1: INTRODUCTION TO SYMBOLIC INTERACTION:

More information

Guilt-aversion: a servant of two masters

Guilt-aversion: a servant of two masters SINTELNET Working Group 4: Socio-technical Epistemology Guilt-aversion: a servant of two masters Luca Tummolini Istituto di Scienze e Tecnologie della Cognizione - CNR luca.tummolini@istc.cnr.it Goal-oriented

More information

Endogeneity is a fancy word for a simple problem. So fancy, in fact, that the Microsoft Word spell-checker does not recognize it.

Endogeneity is a fancy word for a simple problem. So fancy, in fact, that the Microsoft Word spell-checker does not recognize it. Jesper B Sørensen August 2012 Endogeneity is a fancy word for a simple problem. So fancy, in fact, that the Microsoft Word spell-checker does not recognize it. Technically, in a statistical model you have

More information

Cooperation in Prisoner s Dilemma Game: Influence of Social Relations

Cooperation in Prisoner s Dilemma Game: Influence of Social Relations Cooperation in Prisoner s Dilemma Game: Influence of Social Relations Maurice Grinberg (mgrinberg@nbu.bg) Evgenia Hristova (ehristova@cogs.nbu.bg) Milena Borisova (borisova_milena@abv.bg) Department of

More information

The Logic of Data Analysis Using Statistical Techniques M. E. Swisher, 2016

The Logic of Data Analysis Using Statistical Techniques M. E. Swisher, 2016 The Logic of Data Analysis Using Statistical Techniques M. E. Swisher, 2016 This course does not cover how to perform statistical tests on SPSS or any other computer program. There are several courses

More information

Choosing Life: Empowerment, Action, Results! CLEAR Menu Sessions. Substance Use Risk 5: Drugs, Alcohol, and HIV

Choosing Life: Empowerment, Action, Results! CLEAR Menu Sessions. Substance Use Risk 5: Drugs, Alcohol, and HIV Choosing Life: Empowerment, Action, Results! CLEAR Menu Sessions Substance Use Risk 5: This page intentionally left blank. Session Aims: (70 Minutes) To understand the health consequences of drugs and

More information