Kohlberg and Piaget on Stages and Moral Reasoning

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Kohlberg and Piaget on Stages and Moral Reasoning"

Transcription

1 Developmental Review 20, (2000) doi: /drev , available online at on Kohlberg and Piaget on Stages and Moral Reasoning Jeremy I. M. Carpendale Simon Fraser University, Burnaby, British Columbia, Canada Kohlberg s theory of moral development has been criticized because it predicts greater consistency in moral reasoning than has been observed. This prediction follows from Kohlberg s conception of stages, which also entails a view of the process of reasoning as the application of a moral principle to a dilemma to derive a solution. Although Kohlberg emphasized the importance of perspective taking in moral reasoning, his view of stages is inconsistent with this position. A modification of Kohlberg s conception of stages drawing on Piagetian theory would result in a view of moral reasoning as a process of coordinating all perspectives involved in a moral dilemma. For various reasons this ideal process may be constrained, restricting an individual s ability to fully consider all other perspectives involved and, thus, leading to inconsistency in reasoning Academic Press Key Words: moral development; stages; Piaget; Kohlberg; universality; relativism. The study of morality within developmental psychology has been dominated by Kohlberg s (e.g., 1969, 1981) theory of moral development. Kohlberg s extensive influence has also been accompanied by criticisms of his theory. The criticism I address is the finding that moral reasoning is not as consistent across different content as predicted by Kohlberg s theory. This expectation of consistency in reasoning follows from Kohlberg s conception of stages because these assumptions about stages entail a particular view of the process of moral reasoning. Although Kohlberg often emphasizes the importance of perspective taking in the process of moral reasoning, his conception of stages is, I argue, incompatible with such a view of reasoning and, instead, entails a view of reasoning as the application of moral principles to moral dilemmas to generate solutions. If moral reasoning was based on perspective taking consistency in reasoning would not be predicted. Rather, it should be expected that moral reasoning would be influenced by factors I acknowledge the influence of Michael Chapman and Dennis Krebs on the approach taken in this article, and I thank Michael Glassman, Mark Tappan, Bill Turnbull, and James Youniss for comments on earlier versions of this article. Address correspondence and reprint requests to Psychology Department, Simon Fraser University, 8888 University Drive, Burnaby, B.C., Canada, V5A 1S6. Fax: (604) jcarpend@sfu.ca /00 $35.00 Copyright 2000 by Academic Press All rights of reproduction in any form reserved.

2 182 JEREMY I. M. CARPENDALE that either hinder or facilitate perspective taking. Thus, two aspects of Kohlberg s theory his conception of stages and his account of the process of reasoning appear to be incompatible. Kohlberg s conception of stages and the prediction of consistency in reasoning is based on Piaget s (1960) theory of cognitive development. This is a common view of the nature of reasoning, and Piaget s theory of cognitive development is usually interpreted in this way. However, an alternative interpretation of Piagetian theory (Chapman, 1988, 1991), based on Piaget s insight that thought originates in action, does not lead to a prediction of consistency in reasoning. This approach would modify Kohlberg s theory in a way that would be consistent with Kohlberg s emphasis on perspective taking. From a Piagetian perspective, moral reasoning is viewed as a process of coordinating all perspectives involved in a moral dilemma (Davidson & Youniss, 1991, 1995; Youniss & Damon, 1992). Of course, this is an ideal process that can be constrained due to the nature of the situation, restricting an individual s ability to fully consider all other perspectives and resulting in inconsistency in reasoning. I briefly present some of Kohlberg s central assumptions, review evidence relevant to these assumptions revealing difficulties with Kohlberg s theory, and then discuss ways in which Piagetian theory could potentially resolve these problems. I conclude by considering the central issue of universality versus relativism in moral judgment, arguing that employing a Piagetian view of moral judgment as a process of coordinating perspectives, which involves dialogue, does provide a universal process in the preconditions for social interaction and, therefore, does not entail moral relativism. Kohlberg s Theory of Moral Development Kohlberg s influential theory of moral development brought attention to the psychological study of morality after Piaget s (1932/1965) early work on moral judgment from the 1930s had fallen into neglect. In Kohlberg s dissertation in 1958, he drew much of his inspiration and methodology from Piaget s earlier work. Kohlberg followed Piaget in rejecting an explanation of moral development as a simple transmission of moral rules from parents to children as incomplete because this view cannot account for how such moral norms arise in the first place, and it simply equates morality with conformity to moral rules. Both Piaget and Kohlberg argued that moral development is not simply a process of stamping in cultural expectations. Instead of being passed on from previous generations, the aspect of morality that goes beyond mere conformity to traditional rules must be constructed by individuals. Beyond this initial level of agreement, however, Kohlberg s theory of moral development differs considerably from Piaget s. The aspects of these theories that I focus on are the nature of stages and the process of moral reasoning. These two aspects of theories are intimately intertwined; concep-

3 KOHLBERG AND PIAGET 183 tions of the nature of stages entail views of the process of reasoning. Kohlberg cited Piaget (1960) as the source of his criteria for stages, and Kohlberg s interpretation of Piaget s structure of the whole criterion as implying consistency in reasoning across different content is the way that Piaget has usually been understood. Kohlberg s conception of stages based on Piaget s (1960) theory of cognitive development differs considerably from Piaget s (1932/1965) view of stages or forms of moral reasoning in The Moral Judgement of the Child (Wright, 1983), and Kohlberg (1963; Kohlberg, Higgins, Tappan, & Schrader, 1984, p. 656; Tappan, Kohlberg, Schrader, Higgins, Armon, & Lei, 1987, p. 319) did discuss the ways in which his theory differed from Piaget s work on moral judgment. Although Kohlberg endorsed the usual interpretation of Piaget s notion of stages, Chapman (1988) has argued convincingly that this is not, in fact, what Piaget meant by the concept of a structure. This is because Piaget argued that structures develop through the interiorization of action, and since action is content specific we should expect that children would develop at different rates in different domains (Chapman, 1988; Lourenço & Machado, 1996). That is, inconsistency in reasoning should be expected. In contrast, the standard interpretation of Piaget s stages leads to predictions of consistency in reasoning and is most commonly assumed to entail a view of the process of reasoning as mental logic. From this perspective, reasoning consists of applying logical principles to problems or, in the case of moral reasoning, moral principles. Ironically, this may not be the way Kohlberg wanted to conceptualize the process of moral reasoning. Yet it is this underlying assumption about the nature of reasoning that is tied up with his criteria for stages and results in predictions of consistency in reasoning across different content. I first discuss Kohlberg s conception of stages of moral reasoning and then turn to the process of moral reasoning. Kohlberg s Conception of Stages: Predictions of Consistency Kohlberg s theory provides a description of a sequence of progressively more adequate forms of reasoning about moral dilemmas. According to Kohlberg, in the process of developing moral knowledge individuals progress through this series of stages in an invariant sequence. Cultural factors may speed up, slow down, or stop development, but they do not change its sequence (Colby & Kohlberg, 1987, p. 6). The principles that define the stage an individual has reached form a coherent pattern or structured whole that provides a general description of his or her moral thought. Thus, a given stage response on a task does not represent simply a specific response determined by knowledge and familiarity with that task or tasks similar to it; rather, it represents an underlying thought organization (Colby & Kohlberg, 1987, p. 6). In Kohlberg s transformational model of stages, higher stages displace (or, rather, integrate) the structures found at lower stages (Colby & Kohlberg, 1987, p. 7); that is, an individual s pattern of

4 184 JEREMY I. M. CARPENDALE thought is reorganized in the development of the next higher stage (Colby & Kohlberg, 1987). A clear prediction following from Kohlberg s view of stages is that once an individual has developed a form of moral reasoning he or she would be expected to apply this way of thinking, or set of moral principles, to all moral conflicts encountered. That is, in addition to sequence, stages must meet the criterion of consistency implied by the notion of a structured whole (Kohlberg, 1969, p. 388). Although Kohlberg acknowledged that people do not always use their highest stage of moral reasoning in resolving moral dilemmas, he did expect that the thinking exhibited will be quite internally consistent, and with the exception of some very slight decalage, will form a structured whole across widely varying content (Colby & Kohlberg, 1987, p. 8). In other words, Kohlberg s theory predicts considerable consistency in moral reasoning across different content. Although individuals demonstrate consistency in their moral reasoning across the several moral dilemmas in Kohlberg s Moral Judgment Interview (Colby & Kohlberg, 1987), there is considerable evidence of inconsistency in moral judgment on other types of moral dilemmas. People often fail to use their highest stage of moral judgment when reasoning about the moral dilemmas encountered in everyday life. For example, in studies comparing moral reasoning on Kohlberg s dilemmas with reasoning on moral dilemmas set in a business context (Carpendale & Krebs, 1992, 1995) or involving drinking and driving (Denton & Krebs, 1990), participants tend to employ much lower stages of moral reasoning, typically Stage 2. In this series of studies it was possible to classify participants responses to non-kohlberg dilemmas with Colby and Kohlberg s (1987) extensive scoring manual. Experienced raters found criterion judgments in the scoring manual that matched participants interview judgments (i.e., the same form of reasoning was used). This finding supports Kohlberg s classification of forms of moral thought. However, participants often used lower stages of moral reasoning when resolving the non-kohlberg dilemmas than they used on Kohlberg s dilemmas (for reviews and detailed descriptions of this research see, e.g., Bartek, Krebs, & Taylor, 1993; Krebs, Vermeulen, Carpendale, & Denton, 1991; Krebs, Denton, Vermeulen, Carpendale, & Bush, 1991). This empirical evidence of inconsistency in moral reasoning across different types of moral dilemmas is inconsistent with Kohlberg s theory and requires an explanation, and, I argue, a modification of Kohlberg s view of stages. Kohlberg explained the fact that people do not always use their highest stage of moral reasoning by employing a distinction between competence and performance. That is, although Kohlberg s Moral Judgment Interview is designed to assess individuals highest level of competence in moral reasoning, in actual situations their performance may not reach this level. Lower stages, however, are used only in situations with a significant downward press, such as convicts living in what may be called the low-level moral

5 KOHLBERG AND PIAGET 185 atmosphere of a traditional prison (Colby & Kohlberg, 1987, p. 8). This example of a situation in which people may not use their full competence is fairly extreme, and this explanation seems inadequate when we consider the extent of the research evidence of inconsistency in moral reasoning in real-life contexts such as family and business. It is worthwhile, I argue, to consider an alternative approach to this problem with Kohlberg s theory by reconceptualizing Kohlberg s view of moral stages drawing on Piaget s earlier work on moral judgment and interpretations of Piaget s theory that go beyond the standard view of his theory (e.g., Chapman, 1988; Davidson & Youniss, 1991, 1995; Lourenço & Machado, 1996; Youniss & Damon, 1992). It may appear paradoxical to suggest that difficulties with Kohlberg s theory can be resolved with insights drawn from Piaget when it is commonly assumed that Kohlberg s theory is an extension of Piaget s work on moral development. However, although Kohlberg was inspired by Piaget and he did draw much of his ideas concerning the nature of development from Piaget, Kohlberg (e.g., 1963) explicitly rejected important aspects of Piaget s theory. In fact, Piaget did not believe that it is possible to characterize an individual as being at one particular stage in the moral domain. Piaget classified forms of moral reasoning, but he argued that both children and adults use different forms of moral reasoning in different situations (Piaget, 1932/1965, p. 85). Rather than drawing on Piaget s work on moral judgment, Kohlberg (1969) based his view of stages on Piaget s (1960) theory of cognitive development (Kohlberg, 1963; Kohlberg, Higgins, Tappan, & Schrader, 1984; Tappan, Kohlberg, Schrader, Higgins, Armon, & Lei, 1987; Wright, 1983). Kohlberg (e.g., 1969; Colby & Kohlberg, 1987) stated that his view of stages, including the notion of structures of the whole, was drawn from Piaget (1960). Kohlberg drew on the way that Piaget s theory of cognitive development is usually interpreted. According to this standard view, individuals progress through stages, which are assumed to be based on general structures that are applied across different content. This standard view of Piaget s theory predicts consistency in reasoning across content and it has also been criticized because of considerable evidence of inconsistency in reasoning across different content. Although this is a common interpretation of Piaget, Chapman (1988) argued that what Piaget meant by structures d ensemble, or structure of the whole, does not imply generality or consistency in reasoning across widely varying content. This is because structures develop through the interiorization of action, which is necessarily content specific. In a footnote, Colby and Kohlberg (1987) acknowledge that although the stage concept is an essential part of Kohlberg s theory, the specific stage model adopted is subject to revision (p. 36). It is this stage model and the model of reasoning that it entails that, I argue, requires revision. I now turn to Kohlberg s view of the process of moral reasoning.

6 186 JEREMY I. M. CARPENDALE Moral Reasoning: Principles or Process? There is some ambivalence in Kohlberg s position regarding how to describe the process of moral reasoning. It is not clear whether Kohlberg thought of moral reasoning as a process of coordinating conflicting perspectives or as the application of moral principles to generate solutions to moral dilemmas. In an early article, Kohlberg (1963, p. 28) remarked in a footnote that it is historically true that all philosophic formulations of moral principles, such as those just mentioned [i.e., the Golden Rule, the utilitarian principle (the greatest good for the greatest number) and Kant s categorical imperative ], are variations of a basic prescription to take the role of all others involved in the moral situations. Furthermore, an assumption that Kohlberg states he shares with Dewey, Mead, Baldwin, and Piaget is that stages of moral development represent successive modes of taking the role of others in social situations (Kohlberg, 1981, p. 134, italics in original, see also Kohlberg, 1969, pp ). More recently, Colby and Kohlberg (1987, p. 30) described the sociomoral perspective of Stage 6 as that of the moral point of view, a point of view that ideally all humans should take toward one another as free and equal autonomous persons. This means equal consideration of the claims or points of view of each person affected by the moral decision to be made. Colby and Kohlberg (1987) go on to describe several formalizations of procedures designed to ensure this moral point of view. Rawls s (1971) veil of ignorance is one such formalization, according to which moral decisions must be made without the individual knowing his or her position in society, thus encouraging a decision that should be equally good for all involved. Kohlberg s conception of moral musical chairs is a similar procedure. Moral musical chairs means going around the circle of perspectives involved in a moral dilemma to test one s claims of right or duty until only the equilibrated or reversible claims survive (Kohlberg, 1981, p. 199). Colby and Kohlberg (1987) then mention Habermas notion of an ideal communication situation, consisting of dialogue among equals in which all involved state their position and listen to others points of view. Ironically, Colby and Kohlberg s (1987) list of formalizations of procedures fails to include Piaget, the theory on which it is commonly assumed that Kohlberg s theory was based. Although Kohlberg emphasized the importance of perspective taking, this view of reasoning is, I argue, incompatible with his conception of stages. Instead, Kohlberg s conception of stages entails a view of moral reasoning as the application of a moral principle or rule to a dilemma in order to generate a solution. This is because if reasoning consists of understanding and coordinating conflicting perspectives in a moral dilemma, consistency in reasoning across different situations should not be expected. Rather, we should expect that situations or relationships that either constrain or facilitate the ability to

7 KOHLBERG AND PIAGET 187 understand others perspectives would influence moral reasoning. In contrast, consistency in reasoning would be expected if the process of reasoning is conceived of as the application of principles to problems. Once a child has developed a particular principle we would expect that it would generally be applied in all relevant circumstances. Habermas (1983/1990) also pointed out that some of Kohlberg s statements are inconsistent with a procedural approach to moral reasoning. For example, Kohlberg (1981, pp ) states that a morality on which universal agreement could be based would require a different foundation. It would require that moral obligation be directly derived from a substantive moral principle which can define the choices of any man without conflict or inconsistency. The nature of stages and the process of reasoning has also been discussed in the area of children s concrete operational reasoning; therefore, we should consider what can be learned from that earlier debate. I consider Piaget s conceptions of stages and reasoning in the area of cognitive development before turning to Piaget s work on moral judgment. Parallels with Theories of Reasoning in Other Domains Piaget s theory of cognitive development has generally been interpreted as a theory of mental logic. According to this standard view of Piaget s theory, reasoning consists of the application of a logical rule to a problem to derive a solution. A developmental implication of this view of reasoning is that if a child has demonstrated the development of such a rule he or she should be able to apply this rule to other problems of a similar nature. This assumption about the nature of reasoning also underlies Kohlberg s theory and results in an expectation of consistency in reasoning across different content. A serious problem with this view of reasoning is that it is difficult to see why children who demonstrate the use of a particular rule on some tasks fail to solve very similar tasks that appear to involve the very same logical principle. For example, children tend to solve transitivity problems concerning length some years before they can solve transitivity problems involving weight, yet both problems involve the very same logical principle (i.e., A B and B CsoA C) (Chapman, 1988). There is considerable evidence of this inconsistency in reasoning across different content domains, or horizontal decalage, and this evidence has been considered problematic for Piaget s theory. Evidence of inconsistency in reasoning in both cognitive and moral development has been extensively discussed. For example, Siegler (1996) pointed out that the amount of variability in forms of reasoning observed is inconsistent with most stage theories of development. This rejection of stage theories is, however, based on what has become the standard interpretation of Piagetian theory. In contrast to this standard view of Piaget s notion of stages, Chapman (1988) argued that evidence of inconsistency in reasoning is only a problem for an interpretation of Piaget s theory as a theory of mental logic. From the

8 188 JEREMY I. M. CARPENDALE perspective of an interpretation that is consistent with Piaget s underlying constructivist epistemology emphasizing the origins of thought in action, horizontal decalage is not problematic and should actually be expected. The common view of Piagetian stages as overall structures explaining reasoning in different areas may have been partially due to Piaget s discussion of two performances as involving the same structure. However, Chapman (1988) pointed out that structures may be the same in the sense that they are formally analogous, but these structures may be functionally distinct. That is, structures may have the same form but they are not the same structure. For example, children s reasoning about transitivity problems may involve the separate development of structures involving length and weight. These structures will be separate because they develop through the interiorization of action with the different materials, but the structures will have the same form (Chapman, 1988; Lourenço & Machado, 1996). This point becomes clearer when we keep in mind Piaget s account of the development of structures as involving the interiorization of action. When content-specific actions are interiorized and grouped together as operations, the resulting structures accordingly retain the content specificity of the operations of which they are composed (Chapman, 1988, p. 343). Piaget did consider the possibility of general stages but he stated that he had found no evidence for such general stages. In Piaget s (1941/1952, p. 204) words, a formal structure... will not be acquired all at once, irrespective of its content, but will need to be reacquired as many times as there are different contents to which it is applied. Thus, Piaget never did make claims about consistency in reasoning across different content, and expectations of consistency in reasoning do not follow from Piaget s theory (Chapman, 1988). Chapman (1988, p. 347) concluded that contrary to widely accepted interpretations of his theory Piaget did not believe in general stages of development characterized by developmental synchrony across domains of content and such an interpretation of stage development cannot be derived from the concept of structures d ensemble. The idea that structures d ensemble imply developmental synchrony results from a confusion of Piaget s specific concept of structures d ensemble as relational totalities with the notion of structural unity across domains of content. This latter notion he specifically denied. Thus, evidence of inconsistency in reasoning is not a challenge for Piaget s theory (see also Lourenço & Machado, 1996). In contrast to the standard interpretation of Piaget, Chapman (1999; Carpendale, McBride, & Chapman, 1996) emphasized Piaget s insight that thought develops from action rather than the particular logic used by Piaget to describe reasoning. Instead of considering reasoning as the application of a rule or logical principle to solve a problem, in Chapman s operational semantic theory, reasoning is assumed to consist of the process of combining and coordinating internalized actions, or operations. From this perspective, transitive reasoning about the relative lengths of a series of sticks would

9 KOHLBERG AND PIAGET 189 involve implicitly performing the operations of comparing the sticks by aligning their ends and checking to see if one protrudes beyond the other. These implicit operations would then be combined to generate the solution. In the answer that children generate we can see an instance of a logical rule (i.e., A B and B CsoA C), but rather than being applied to solve the problem, a particular instance of this rule is created in the process of combining the operations (Carpendale, McBride, & Chapman, 1996; Chapman & Lindenberger, 1992). This interpretation of Piaget theory, based on his underlying constructivist view of the development of knowledge, leads to a view of stages that does not imply consistency in reasoning, as assumed by Kohlberg and others. Rather than being problematic, horizontal decalage should be expected from a constructivist epistemology, according to which thought develops from action, because action is necessarily content specific (Chapman, 1988). This interpretation of Piagetian theory, developed in the area of children s concrete operational reasoning, is relevant for the parallel problem of inconsistency in reasoning about moral matters. From this perspective, resolving a moral dilemma does not consist of applying a moral principle and calculating an answer (in a manner analogous to the mental logic theory of reasoning). Rather, it is a process of coordinating all the perspectives involved and generating a solution through this process that is fair to all concerned. The solution generated could be described in terms of a moral principle, but it is a particular instance of that principle that was generated by a process of coordinating viewpoints rather than a principle that was applied in order to derive the solution. This view of stages and the process of moral reasoning is consistent with Piaget s underlying insight that thought originates in action (Chapman, 1988). This position is also clear in Piaget s (1932/1965, p. 119) work on moral judgment where he states that there can be no doubt that verbal thought lags behind active thought. I now turn to Piaget s view of stages and the process of reasoning in his work on moral judgment. Piaget s Theory of Moral Judgment: The Role of Social Interaction One of the contexts in which Piaget investigated the development of moral judgment was in children s understanding of the rules of games, primarily boys playing the game of marbles. Piaget s (1932/1965, p. 13) justification for this unusual approach was that all morality consists in a system of rules, and the essence of all morality is to be sought for in the respect which the individual acquires for these rules. The question is how children come to respect rules and how children s understanding of the nature of rules changes. Social games are an appropriate context for this study because, in contrast to many of the moral rules children learn from adults, the rules of games are passed on and elaborated by children. Although Piaget s interest in subject object interaction is well known, his interest in the role of social interaction in development is, unfortunately,

10 190 JEREMY I. M. CARPENDALE relatively unknown (e.g, Chapman, 1986, 1988; Piaget, 1923/1955, 1924/ 1928, 1965/1995; Smith, 1995; Youniss & Damon, 1992). In fact, it has been commonly assumed that Piaget completely neglected the role of social interaction in development. Perhaps this partial view of Piaget will be corrected by the recent publication of the first English translation of Piaget s (1965/1995) Sociological Studies. In this book Piaget clearly states that human intelligence is subject to the action of social life at all levels of development from the first to the last day of life (Piaget, 1965/1995, p. 278). However, Piaget (1965/1995, p. 278) also refused to accept that society or social life are sufficiently precise concepts to be employed in psychology. This is because social interaction influences individuals in quite different ways at different points in their development. It is also because there are different forms of social interaction. In all spheres, two types of social relations must be distinguished: constraint and cooperation. The first implies an element of unilateral respect, of authority and prestige; the second is simply the intercourse between individuals on an equal footing (Piaget, 1932/1965, p. 61). Much of the work from a Piagetian perspective on the influence of peers and social interaction on cognitive and moral development has been primarily concerned with peers as a source of social cognitive conflict leading to disequilibrium, which results in further development (e.g., Doise & Mugny, 1984; Forman & Kraker, 1985; for a review see Chapman & McBride, 1992). Kohlberg (e.g., 1969) also acknowledged the importance of social interaction, primarily because opportunities for role taking provide a source of disequilibrium, promoting development of more complete, but still partial, forms of equilibrium. It is less commonly mentioned that as well as social interaction as a source of disequilibrium, Piaget (1932/1965) was also concerned with how the nature of relationships may influence children s ability to reach an understanding of other s perspectives (Kruger & Tomasello, 1986; Tomasello, Kruger, & Ratner, 1993; Tudge & Rogoff, 1989). For social interaction to be effective, children must be able to understand the other points of view that conflict with their own perspective. This understanding of other perspectives may be facilitated or constrained by the nature of the relationship. It is this second role of social interaction in the way relationships differentially influence perspective taking and moral reasoning that I am primarily concerned with. From Piaget s perspective, children construct their social and moral intelligence through managing their social interaction. From this it follows that for the development of social intelligence we should look at the structure of the relationships that children experience because different relationships allow for different forms of development. 1 1 Other authors have also emphasized the role of relationships in moral development. In particular, Gilligan and Wiggins (1987) proposed a theory in which the relationships of inequality and attachment, which they suggest are typically differentially experienced by boys and girls, influence the development of two moralities: justice and care. In 1932 Piaget men-

11 KOHLBERG AND PIAGET 191 Of the two general types of relationships that Piaget (1932/1965) described, the first relationship children experience is with their parents, which tends to involve unilateral respect, one-sided authority, and constraint. Adults impose rules on children and, because of the lack of equality, adults may not feel obligated to justify their rules or listen to children s points of view. Children follow these moral rules due to the respect they feel for adults or older children. According to Piaget, children s respect for adults is based on a mixture of fear and affection. In this type of relationship children cannot reach an understanding of the purpose of the rules, and, therefore, they see rules as external and unchangeable. Piaget described young children s understanding of rules as sacred and untouchable, something passed down from previous generations, and ultimately from God. Kohlberg assumed that Piaget was claiming that young children feel a deep reverence for the adult World Order (Kohlberg, 1963, p. 20). Instead, Kohlberg argued on the basis of his own research that it is simpler to characterize young children s understanding of morality as merely a desire to avoid punishment a basically hedonistic view of right or wrong (p. 21) rather than as a deep reverence for adults. What Piaget meant by sacred, however, was an understanding of moral rules as completely external to the child and, thus, beyond change by human hands. Young children understand rules in this way because they are in relationships of adult constraint and cannot understand the purpose of the rules. In fact, in Piaget s (1932/1965) research on children s understanding of the rules of marbles he found that young children thought of the rules for marbles as sacred (i.e., unchangeable), but at the same time they did, in fact, change them continually because they did not put these rules into practice in any systematic way. That is, even though young children think of rules as external and unchangeable their play does not actually conform to the rules. Small children play according to their understanding but consider the rules as intangible and sacred (Piaget, 1965/1995, p. 303). Piaget (1932/1965, p. 74) recognized that children very rarely reflect on the original institution of the game of marbles. However, when questioned their answers concerning the adult origin and unchanging nature of the rules indicates that these young children tioned the moralists discussion of a conflict between justice and love. Piaget acknowledged that love (or care ) might be in conflict with short-sighted justice but he argued that between the more refined forms of justice, such as equity and love properly so called, there is no longer any real conflict (Piaget, 1932/1965, p. 324). That is, in relationships of mutual respect justice and care would not be in conflict; rather, concerns with equity would involve both justice and care. Gilligan s distinction between justice and care is part of a wider discussion in the philosophical literature. In the past these principles have served as core elements of two contrary traditions in moral philosophy.... Hegel was the first to argue that we misperceive the basic moral phenomenon if we isolate the two aspects, assigning opposite principles to each (Habermas, 1983/1990, p. 201). Habermas argued that these two principles are internally connected within moral argumentation and that morality thus cannot protect the one without the other (Habermas, 1983/1990, p. 200).

12 192 JEREMY I. M. CARPENDALE think that the laws of the game must be left alone (Piaget, 1932/1965, p. 75). At the same time that children experience relationships of constraint with their parents, they also experience a different form of relationship with their peers. In these relationships they are among equals, and this form of relationship allows for the possibility of cooperation, although there will be beginning phases where collaboration among children is not yet possible since children lack the instruments necessary for coordination (Piaget, 1965/ 1995, p. 305). Ideally, interaction among peers cannot be dominated by one child because they are equals, and, therefore, they must cooperate. Piaget argued that morality develops in situations that involve cooperation because it is in these relationships that children are able to take the perspectives of others. In cooperative relationships individuals must understand each other s perspectives, and this requires listening to others and explaining one s own position. Cooperation alone can shake the child out of its initial state of unconscious egocentrism (Piaget, 1932/1965, p. 187). Within such cooperative relationships children develop an understanding of rules as based on mutual agreement. Therefore, rules can be changed as long as everyone concerned agrees. According to Piaget (1932/1965), the two moral worlds of constraint and cooperation coexist in childhood and continue to exist in adulthood, although there is a gradual shift from one to the other. This view of parent child relationships as involving constraint is not all negative and it may arise from positive motivations because parents must protect young children from trialand-error learning (Davidson & Youniss, 1995). At early ages children may not be able to understand the reason for many rules, but parent child relationships tend to change with the development of the child (Youniss & Smollar, 1985). Although Piaget introduced the two relationships of constraint and cooperation as a dichotomy, he clearly acknowledged that most relationships consist of some mixture of the two types and the proportions will vary. Actually, of course, there are innumerable intermediate stages between these two attitudes of obedience and collaboration, but it is useful for the purposes of analysis to emphasize the real opposition that exists between them (Piaget, 1932/1965, p. 138). Relationships among children can also involve constraint and the imposition of power because even in the relations between children, the authority of older ones will outweigh equality (Piaget, 1932/ 1965, p. 316). On the other hand, parent child relationships can vary in the degree of cooperation that is encouraged. This Piagetian view of the differential role of relationships in development provides an explanation for the influence of different parenting styles on development, and Piaget (1932/1965, e.g., p. 137, p. 267) did suggest that different family backgrounds might differentially affect the development of the idea of equality. Piaget (1932/1965) described two types of morality in his investigation of children s moral judgment that are associated with these two forms of

13 KOHLBERG AND PIAGET 193 social interaction. A morality of constraint and a morality of cooperation: relations of constraint, whose characteristic is to impose upon the individual from outside a system of rules with obligatory content, and relations of cooperation whose characteristic is to create within people s minds the consciousness of ideal norms at the back of all rules (Piaget, 1932/1965, p. 395). Piaget did not claim that these two types of moral thought form separate stages; rather, these forms of moral judgment tend to overlap. With respect to children s understanding of the rules of games, Piaget (1932/1965, p. 85) stated that there are no inclusive stages which define the whole of a subject s mental life at a given point of his evolution. Further, the material cannot be said to embody stages properly so called, and it may even happen that one and the same child judges sometimes one way, sometimes the other (Piaget, 1932/1965, p. 124). There can therefore be no question of two real stages. All we can say is that objective responsibility is a phenomenon frequently to be found among the younger children but subsequently diminishing in importance (Piaget, 1932/1965, p. 156). Again, when referring to the development of children s understanding of retributive and distributive justice, Piaget (1932/1965, p. 267) stated that there can be no question of clear cut stages in moral development. The gradual shift observed from one morality to the other as children develop is partially due to changes in the kinds of relationships that an individual typically experiences. Piaget (1932/1965) did not, however, claim that the features of morality from relationships of constraint completely vanish in adults. There may be situations involving cooperation in childhood and relationships of constraint experienced by adults. Both forms of morality exist in the child and in the adult; it is simply a question of the proportions in which they are mixed (Piaget, 1932/1965, p. 85). Piaget argued that adults and children use both types of moral reasoning, only the proportion differs, and the type used depends on the situation or relationship rather than on the individual being in a particular stage. This implies that if social interaction varies in terms of constraint versus cooperation adults would tend to use different levels of moral reasoning. That is, the nature of the relationship individuals experience may influence moral reasoning due to either facilitating or inhibiting the process of perspective taking. Piaget (1932/1965, p. 76) asked, how is it that democratic practice is so developed in the games of marbles played by boys of 11 to 13, whereas it is still so unfamiliar to the adult in many spheres of life? His answer was that since the game of marbles was generally dropped by the age of 14, these 11- to 13-year-olds had no seniors to impose rules through weight of authority. Thus, they experienced a relationship of cooperation rather than constraint and were able to develop an understanding of rules as being based on mutual agreement. Within a cooperative relationship among equals these children engaged in dialogue in which they were able to coordinate their interests and reach

14 194 JEREMY I. M. CARPENDALE an agreement that was acceptable to all of them concerning the rules they were going to use to coordinate their game. One of Piaget s research participants [Ross (11)] responded to the question, How did these rules begin? by saying, Some boys came to an agreement amongst themselves and made them (Piaget, 1932/1965, p. 66). After a discussion with three boys about the complexities of the rules and the differences between rules in different districts another research participant, Vua (13), said, The fact is that sometimes people play differently. Then you ask each other what you want to do. Piaget asked what happens if you can t agree? and Vua s response was, We scrap for a bit and then we fix things up, which, according to Piaget, means they cooperate (Piaget, 1932/1965, p. 49). Stage of moral reasoning is not, however, determined completely by the structure of the relationship. Children also have to develop to the point where they can participate cooperatively and understand others perspectives. Piaget described two types of egocentrism that constrain children s moral reasoning. Egocentrism can be due to the structure of the relationship constraining individuals ability to take others perspectives as well as due to a lack of knowledge on the child s part. There can be a combination of egocentrism due to the child s immaturity of thought as well as egocentrism due to constraint resulting from the structure of the relationship. Young children overcome their egocentrism through participating in cooperative relationships among equals. But the egocentrism due the structure of relationships involving constraint may still influence the moral reasoning of adolescents and adults. Thus, this approach accounts for observed development in moral reasoning as well as inconsistency in reasoning across situations. As mentioned above, Piaget studied children s understanding of and respect for rules in the context of children s games, in particular the game of marbles. He concluded that psychologically, the same rule is a completely different reality for the child of 7 who regards it as sacred and untouchable and for the child of 12 who, without interfering with it, regards it as valid only after it has been mutually agreed upon (Piaget, 1932/1965, pp ). Thus, it could be argued that Piaget s view of moral development was not based on respect for moral rules as external and unchanging but rather based only on respect for rules that all involved have decided are fair and thus really on respect for the persons who agree upon the rules. In cooperative relationships mutual respect for persons will lead to generating solutions by a process of considering all other positions and coordinating conflicting viewpoints. This theoretical perspective considers the nature of the relationship in constraining moral reasoning and, thus, does not predict consistency in stage of moral reasoning regardless of the structure of the relationship (i.e., the extent of equality or cooperation vs constraint). Therefore, this perspective accounts for the evidence of inconsistency in moral reasoning discussed above.

15 KOHLBERG AND PIAGET 195 The emphasis here is on the process through which a decision is reached rather than on structural descriptions of the principles which define forms of reasoning. Although we could describe the outcome of moral reasoning in terms of a moral principle, from this perspective, the actual process of moral reasoning does not involve applying a preexisting principle to a problem. Instead it involves considering all the points of view involved in a moral conflict by listening to the other people concerned, justifying one s own view, and reaching a solution agreeable to all. This process would generate a particular instance of a moral principle, but it is not a preexisting moral principle that is applied to a dilemma to generate a solution. As Piaget (1932/ 1965) argued, what children need in a changing world is not a set of moral rules defining what to do in particular situations that may no longer be applicable, but a process for resolving moral conflicts. As mentioned above, Kohlberg (e.g., 1969) also wrote that moral reasoning is based on perspective taking. However, this account of the process of reasoning is incompatible with Kohlberg s conception of stages. If moral reasoning was based on perspective taking, then variability in moral reasoning should be expected due to factors that influence perspective taking by either constraining or facilitating the ability to understand the perspectives of others involved in the conflict. On the other hand, consistency in reasoning across situations would be expected if reasoning involves the application of a principle. One of Kohlberg s (1969) key criteria for stages from Piaget (1960) is the notion of a structured whole, which for Kohlberg implies consistency in reasoning. Kohlberg s conception of stages appears to entail a view of moral reasoning as the application of a principle to a moral problem, which involves a process of calculating or deriving a solution to a moral dilemma. This conception of reasoning follows from Kohlberg s transformational model of stage development and it encounters problems because it predicts more consistency than we observe. As I have argued, however, an interpretation of Piaget s theory that is more consistent with his underlying epistemology leads to a view of stages that does not imply consistency (Chapman, 1988), and a corresponding view of moral reasoning as the coordination of perspectives. This process could be influenced by situations that either constrain or facilitate perspective taking. From the approach proposed here, moral reasoning is assumed to be based on dialogue, but at lower stages it departs to varying degrees from the ideal situation for free and open communication between people. That is, for various reasons the perspectives of some participants in the moral dilemma may not be considered or given equal weight. The distinction between accounts of moral reasoning as either a process of coordinating perspectives or as the application of a moral principle can be illustrated with an example. One way of characterizing Stage 3 in Kohlberg s theory is in terms of the Golden Rule: do unto others as you would have

16 196 JEREMY I. M. CARPENDALE others do unto you (Colby & Kohlberg, 1987, p. 27). That is, we can describe the justifications people offer for their moral decisions in terms of this moral principle. However, this does not necessarily mean that a decision was reached through a process of applying this moral principle to a dilemma. Another possibility is that the process of reasoning involves understanding and coordinating the conflicting perspectives and, thus, reaching decisions that are reversible. Although the outcome of such a process could be described in terms of the Golden Rule, this is a moment in a process that generates a particular instance of this moral principle rather than a preexisting principle that is somehow present in the mind and applied to problems. This Piagetian view of morality as a process of coordinating perspectives rather than applying a set of moral principles is consistent with Habermas s view of morality based on discourse ethics. Habermas s (1983/1990) view of discourse ethics is based on the notion of an idealized form of communication without repression, coercion, and inequality. Within this ideal communication situation everyone with the capacity to take part in moral argumentation should be given the opportunity for equal participation. In this context of ideal or unrestricted communication everyone concerned can speak and express their attitudes, desires, and needs, and everyone can question any assertion. From this perspective, moral norms must be justified through a process of argumentation in which everyone concerned must be free to state their position. Participants in such moral argumentation must reach a common decision that is equally good for all involved. Habermas s (1983/1990, p. 93) principle of discourse ethics states that only those norms can claim to be valid that meet (or could meet) with the approval of all affected in their capacity as participants in a practical discourse. According to Habermas s (1983/1990) principle of universalization, all affected by a moral norm can accept its consequences, which will be equally good for all involved. The process necessary to justify moral norms is cooperative argumentation, in which understanding is reached because all involved have a chance to state their position and an obligation to listen to and question others. Habermas argued that the reason that these are not just cultural conventions is that they are universal and necessary presuppositions of argumentation. Piaget s cooperative relationships approximate Habermas s idealized conditions for communication. In cooperative relationships among peers everyone is equal. There is no imbalance of power in this idealized relationship, and, due to mutual respect, everyone concerned will listen to others points of view in order to understand their concerns and will feel obligated to explain their own position. Of course, just as Piaget recognized that any actual relationship will involve varying degrees of constraint, Habermas (1983/ 1990) realizes that these ideal conditions will rarely be completely met. Although not all actual discourses conform to these conditions, these idealized conditions are presupposed by participants in argumentation to be at least adequately approximated.

file://c:\documents and Settings\gketcham\Local Settings\Temp\Turnitin_Originality_Report_

file://c:\documents and Settings\gketcham\Local Settings\Temp\Turnitin_Originality_Report_ Page 1 of 8 Turnitin Originality Report DAB sample by Gregory Ketcham From "DAB test" (200740 - SS111-V1 - History of Western Civ I) Processed on 04-08-08 11:01 AM EDT ID: 6501446 Word Count: 1782 Overall

More information

Lawrence Kohlberg (1958) agreed with Piaget's (1932) theory of moral development in principle but wanted to develop his ideas further.

Lawrence Kohlberg (1958) agreed with Piaget's (1932) theory of moral development in principle but wanted to develop his ideas further. Kohlberg www.simplypsychology.org /kohlberg.html Saul McLeod Lawrence Kohlberg (1958) agreed with Piaget's (1932) theory of moral development in principle but wanted to develop his ideas further. He used

More information

The idea of an essentially contested concept is incoherent.

The idea of an essentially contested concept is incoherent. Daniel Alexander Harris 1 The idea of an essentially contested concept is incoherent. Daniel Alexander Harris (2015) Daniel Alexander Harris 2 This essay will demonstrate the idea of an essentially contested

More information

INTERVIEWS II: THEORIES AND TECHNIQUES 5. CLINICAL APPROACH TO INTERVIEWING PART 1

INTERVIEWS II: THEORIES AND TECHNIQUES 5. CLINICAL APPROACH TO INTERVIEWING PART 1 INTERVIEWS II: THEORIES AND TECHNIQUES 5. CLINICAL APPROACH TO INTERVIEWING PART 1 5.1 Clinical Interviews: Background Information The clinical interview is a technique pioneered by Jean Piaget, in 1975,

More information

Martha C. Nussbaum Creating Capabilities. The Human Development Approach Cambrigde Mass.-London, The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 2011

Martha C. Nussbaum Creating Capabilities. The Human Development Approach Cambrigde Mass.-London, The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 2011 Martha C. Nussbaum Creating Capabilities. The Human Development Approach Cambrigde Mass.-London, The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 2011 Sergio Filippo Magni 1. Creating Capabilities is conceived

More information

Ascertaining the Impact of Relativism on Moral Reasoning

Ascertaining the Impact of Relativism on Moral Reasoning Western University Scholarship@Western Electronic Thesis and Dissertation Repository October 2012 Ascertaining the Impact of Relativism on Moral Reasoning Claire B. Henderson The University of Western

More information

Personal identity is cultural identity. Culture is a powerful organizer of

Personal identity is cultural identity. Culture is a powerful organizer of Thomas (Culture) 4682-01.qxd 4/15/2005 5:56 PM Page 1 1 Framework Personal identity is cultural identity. Culture is a powerful organizer of people s lives. How we view ourselves and who we are as individuals

More information

Moral Development November 7, 2006

Moral Development November 7, 2006 Slide 1 Moral Development November 7, 2006 Slide 2 What Is Moral Development? Changes in thoughts, feelings, and behaviors regarding standards of right and wrong An intrapersonal dimension: regulates activities

More information

METHODOLOGY FOR DISSERTATION

METHODOLOGY FOR DISSERTATION METHODOLOGY FOR DISSERTATION In order to expose the methods of scientific work, it is necessary to briefly clarify the terms of methodology, methods and scientific methods. The methodology comes from the

More information

P H E N O M E N O L O G Y

P H E N O M E N O L O G Y P H E N O M E N O L O G Y In the literature, phenomenology is often contrasted with positivist inspired approaches in research. Positivism is associated with the idea of their being objective, independent

More information

OPÚSCULO Edmund Husserl s later phenomenology: an approach to mental disorders

OPÚSCULO Edmund Husserl s later phenomenology: an approach to mental disorders OPÚSCULO 1 - Pequenos textos de Filosofia, Ciência e Filosofia da Ciência - Edmund Husserl s later phenomenology: an approach to mental disorders ~ António Fragoso Fernandes CENTRO DE FILOSOFIA DAS CIÊNCIA

More information

Why do Psychologists Perform Research?

Why do Psychologists Perform Research? PSY 102 1 PSY 102 Understanding and Thinking Critically About Psychological Research Thinking critically about research means knowing the right questions to ask to assess the validity or accuracy of a

More information

2014 Philosophy. National 5. Finalised Marking Instructions

2014 Philosophy. National 5. Finalised Marking Instructions National Qualifications 2014 2014 Philosophy National 5 Finalised Marking Instructions Scottish Qualifications Authority 2014 The information in this publication may be reproduced to support SQA qualifications

More information

Eliminative materialism

Eliminative materialism Michael Lacewing Eliminative materialism Eliminative materialism (also known as eliminativism) argues that future scientific developments will show that the way we think and talk about the mind is fundamentally

More information

Discussion. Re C (An Adult) 1994

Discussion. Re C (An Adult) 1994 Autonomy is an important ethical and legal principle. Respect for autonomy is especially important in a hospital setting. A patient is in an inherently vulnerable position; he or she is part of a big and

More information

Patient Autonomy in Health Care Ethics-A Concept Analysis

Patient Autonomy in Health Care Ethics-A Concept Analysis Patient Autonomy in Health Care Ethics Patient Autonomy in Health Care Ethics-A Concept Analysis Yusrita Zolkefli 1 1 Lecturer, PAPRSB Institute of Health Sciences, Universiti Brunei Darussalam Abstract

More information

Between Micro and Macro: Individual and Social Structure, Content and Form in Georg Simmel

Between Micro and Macro: Individual and Social Structure, Content and Form in Georg Simmel Michela Bowman Amy LeClair Michelle Lynn Robert Weide Classical Sociological Theory November 11, 2003 Between Micro and Macro: Individual and Social Structure, Content and Form in Georg Simmel Through

More information

1. Red flag words contribute to reducing instances of miscommunication. True False

1. Red flag words contribute to reducing instances of miscommunication. True False 1. Red flag words contribute to reducing instances of miscommunication. 1. Red flag words contribute to reducing instances of miscommunication. 2. A major cause that underlies poor listening habits is

More information

Autonomy as a Positive Value Some Conceptual Prerequisites Niklas Juth Dept. of Philosophy, Göteborg University

Autonomy as a Positive Value Some Conceptual Prerequisites Niklas Juth Dept. of Philosophy, Göteborg University Philosophical Communications, Web Series, No. 28 Dept. of Philosophy, Göteborg University, Sweden ISSN 1652-0459 Autonomy as a Positive Value Some Conceptual Prerequisites Niklas Juth Dept. of Philosophy,

More information

Standard 3 Cognition Students will understand how organisms adapt to their environment through learning, information processing and memory.

Standard 3 Cognition Students will understand how organisms adapt to their environment through learning, information processing and memory. PSYCHOLOGY This course provides students the opportunity to explore psychology as the scientific study of mental processes and behavior. Areas of study include the scientific method, development, cognition,

More information

COUNSELING FOUNDATIONS INSTRUCTOR DR. JOAN VERMILLION

COUNSELING FOUNDATIONS INSTRUCTOR DR. JOAN VERMILLION COUNSELING FOUNDATIONS INSTRUCTOR DR. JOAN VERMILLION LEARNING OBJECTIVE #1 Apply principles of sensation and perception, motivation theory, & learning theory to the development of emotions, thoughts,

More information

We Can Test the Experience Machine. Response to Basil SMITH Can We Test the Experience Machine? Ethical Perspectives 18 (2011):

We Can Test the Experience Machine. Response to Basil SMITH Can We Test the Experience Machine? Ethical Perspectives 18 (2011): We Can Test the Experience Machine Response to Basil SMITH Can We Test the Experience Machine? Ethical Perspectives 18 (2011): 29-51. In his provocative Can We Test the Experience Machine?, Basil Smith

More information

Strategic Application of Human Development Applying Positive Psychology. The Principles of Developmental Psychology

Strategic Application of Human Development Applying Positive Psychology. The Principles of Developmental Psychology Strategic Application of Human Development Applying Positive Psychology The Principles of Developmental Psychology 6.1 Introduction Life-span developmental psychology is the field of psychology which involves

More information

THE IMPORTANCE OF MENTAL OPERATIONS IN FORMING NOTIONS

THE IMPORTANCE OF MENTAL OPERATIONS IN FORMING NOTIONS THE IMPORTANCE OF MENTAL OPERATIONS IN FORMING NOTIONS MARIA CONDOR MONICA CHIRA monica.chira@orange_ftgroup.com Abstract: In almost every moment of our existence we are engaged in a process of problem

More information

Installing a Moral Learning Process Integrity Beyond Traditional Ethics Training

Installing a Moral Learning Process Integrity Beyond Traditional Ethics Training Installing a Moral Learning Process Integrity Beyond Traditional Ethics Training Can civil servants be trained to make better decisions? Can government agencies steeped in bureaucracy become agile, learning

More information

Measuring and Assessing Study Quality

Measuring and Assessing Study Quality Measuring and Assessing Study Quality Jeff Valentine, PhD Co-Chair, Campbell Collaboration Training Group & Associate Professor, College of Education and Human Development, University of Louisville Why

More information

Discussion on David Olson s book Psychological Theory and Educational Reform, Cambridge University Press, 2003.

Discussion on David Olson s book Psychological Theory and Educational Reform, Cambridge University Press, 2003. 1 Discussion on David Olson s book Psychological Theory and Educational Reform, Cambridge University Press, 2003. a) Points I have in common with David Olson: It is necessary to develop a theory of schooling.

More information

Durkheim. Durkheim s fundamental task in Rules of the Sociological Method is to lay out

Durkheim. Durkheim s fundamental task in Rules of the Sociological Method is to lay out Michelle Lynn Tey Meadow Jane Jones Deirdre O Sullivan Durkheim Durkheim s fundamental task in Rules of the Sociological Method is to lay out the basic disciplinary structure of sociology. He begins by

More information

UNIT 1. THE DIGNITY OF THE PERSON

UNIT 1. THE DIGNITY OF THE PERSON Ethical Values 3ºESO Department of Philosophy IES Nicolás Copérnico UNIT 1. THE DIGNITY OF THE PERSON 1. What is a person? The Universal Declaration of Human Rights concedes the status of person to every

More information

Roskilde University. Publication date: Document Version Early version, also known as pre-print

Roskilde University. Publication date: Document Version Early version, also known as pre-print Roskilde University Diagnosis and Pedagogical work Gaps and Relations between Individual Categorizations and Social Situations in Children s Everyday Lives. Røn Larsen, Maja Publication date: 2012 Document

More information

Basis for Conclusions: ISA 230 (Redrafted), Audit Documentation

Basis for Conclusions: ISA 230 (Redrafted), Audit Documentation Basis for Conclusions: ISA 230 (Redrafted), Audit Documentation Prepared by the Staff of the International Auditing and Assurance Standards Board December 2007 , AUDIT DOCUMENTATION This Basis for Conclusions

More information

What is analytical sociology? And is it the future of sociology?

What is analytical sociology? And is it the future of sociology? What is analytical sociology? And is it the future of sociology? Twan Huijsmans Sociology Abstract During the last few decades a new approach in sociology has been developed, analytical sociology (AS).

More information

1.1 FEATURES OF THOUGHT

1.1 FEATURES OF THOUGHT SEC 1 Page 1 of 7 1.1 FEATURES OF THOUGHT Thought can refer to the ideas or arrangements of ideas that result from thinking, the act of producing thoughts, or the process of producing thoughts. Despite

More information

School of Nursing, University of British Columbia Vancouver, British Columbia, Canada

School of Nursing, University of British Columbia Vancouver, British Columbia, Canada Data analysis in qualitative research School of Nursing, University of British Columbia Vancouver, British Columbia, Canada Unquestionably, data analysis is the most complex and mysterious of all of the

More information

UNDERSTANDING CAPACITY & DECISION-MAKING VIDEO TRANSCRIPT

UNDERSTANDING CAPACITY & DECISION-MAKING VIDEO TRANSCRIPT I m Paul Bourque, President and CEO of the Investment Funds Institute of Canada. IFIC is preparing materials to assist advisors and firms in managing effective and productive relationships with their aging

More information

Transforming Judgmental Thinking

Transforming Judgmental Thinking 180 Restoring Hope Transforming Judgmental Thinking I don t like that man. I must get to know him better. Abraham Lincoln Dealing with difficult people can evoke and sustain judgmental thinking, which

More information

Temporalization In Causal Modeling. Jonathan Livengood & Karen Zwier TaCitS 06/07/2017

Temporalization In Causal Modeling. Jonathan Livengood & Karen Zwier TaCitS 06/07/2017 Temporalization In Causal Modeling Jonathan Livengood & Karen Zwier TaCitS 06/07/2017 Temporalization In Causal Modeling Jonathan Livengood & Karen Zwier TaCitS 06/07/2017 Introduction Causal influence,

More information

Moral Personality Exemplified. Lawrence J. Walker. University of British Columbia

Moral Personality Exemplified. Lawrence J. Walker. University of British Columbia 09.29.06 Lawrence Walker 1 Moral Personality Exemplified Lawrence J. Walker University of British Columbia Contemporary explanations of moral functioning have emerged within the context of the influence

More information

Materialism and the Mind and Body Problem:

Materialism and the Mind and Body Problem: Materialism and the Mind and Body Problem: A Critical Analysis SeanAgius The philosophy of mind has become dominated by the mind and body problem: the relation between the physical (the body) and the mental

More information

VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW IN BRIEF

VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW IN BRIEF VIRGINIA LAW REVIEW IN BRIEF VOLUME 96 JUNE 15, 2010 PAGES 35 39 REPLY GOOD INTENTIONS MATTER Katharine T. Bartlett * W HILE writing the article to which Professors Mitchell and Bielby have published responses,

More information

IAQM2007, Banff, Canada, September 22, 2007 Qualitative and Quantitative Methods are Not Different from a Structural Constructivist Perspective

IAQM2007, Banff, Canada, September 22, 2007 Qualitative and Quantitative Methods are Not Different from a Structural Constructivist Perspective IAQM2007, Banff, Canada, September 22, 2007 Qualitative and Quantitative Methods are Not Different from a Structural Constructivist Perspective Prof. Hirofumi TAKAGI, Ph.D. School of Nursing, Faculty of

More information

Social-semiotic externalism in Can robot understand values?

Social-semiotic externalism in Can robot understand values? Social-semiotic externalism in Can robot understand values? English presentation seminar Prof. Minao Kukika November 20, 2015 Seiichiro Yasuda 1 List of acronyms (for your reference) SGP: ESGP: AMA: AI:

More information

Ideas RESEARCH. Theory, Design Practice. Turning INTO. Barbara Fawcett. Rosalie Pockett

Ideas RESEARCH. Theory, Design Practice. Turning INTO. Barbara Fawcett. Rosalie Pockett Turning Ideas INTO RESEARCH & Theory, Design Practice Barbara Fawcett Rosalie Pockett 00_Fawcett_BAB1410B0218_Prelims.indd 3 3/23/2015 6:32:36 PM ONE Why do research? In this chapter we look at the many

More information

PLANNING THE RESEARCH PROJECT

PLANNING THE RESEARCH PROJECT Van Der Velde / Guide to Business Research Methods First Proof 6.11.2003 4:53pm page 1 Part I PLANNING THE RESEARCH PROJECT Van Der Velde / Guide to Business Research Methods First Proof 6.11.2003 4:53pm

More information

Spiritual, Moral, Social and Cultural Development at The Grove Primary School

Spiritual, Moral, Social and Cultural Development at The Grove Primary School at The Grove Primary School Giving pupils the opportunity to explore values and beliefs, including religious beliefs, including religious beliefs, and the way in which they impact on people s lives; Where

More information

Using Your Brain -- for a CHANGE Summary. NLPcourses.com

Using Your Brain -- for a CHANGE Summary. NLPcourses.com Using Your Brain -- for a CHANGE Summary NLPcourses.com Table of Contents Using Your Brain -- for a CHANGE by Richard Bandler Summary... 6 Chapter 1 Who s Driving the Bus?... 6 Chapter 2 Running Your Own

More information

Group Assignment #1: Concept Explication. For each concept, ask and answer the questions before your literature search.

Group Assignment #1: Concept Explication. For each concept, ask and answer the questions before your literature search. Group Assignment #1: Concept Explication 1. Preliminary identification of the concept. Identify and name each concept your group is interested in examining. Questions to asked and answered: Is each concept

More information

Abstracts. An International Journal of Interdisciplinary Research. From Mentalizing Folk to Social Epistemology

Abstracts. An International Journal of Interdisciplinary Research. From Mentalizing Folk to Social Epistemology Proto Sociology s An International Journal of Interdisciplinary Research 3 Vol. 16, 2002 Understanding the Social: New Perspectives from Epistemology Contents From Mentalizing Folk to Social Epistemology

More information

Spiritual, moral, social and cultural development policy

Spiritual, moral, social and cultural development policy Spiritual, moral, social and cultural development policy St Peter s Eaton Square C of E Primary School St Peter s School is a place where every person has the right to be themselves and to be included

More information

WSC 2018 SCIENCE. Science of Memory

WSC 2018 SCIENCE. Science of Memory WSC 2018 SCIENCE Science of Memory Schema 101 A schema describes a pattern of thought or behavior that organizes categories of information and the relationships among them. It can also be described as

More information

Major Ethical Theories

Major Ethical Theories Ethical theories provide frameworks and specific values for assessing situations and guiding decision-making processes, so the relative differences between right and wrong are understood, and appropriate

More information

INTRODUCTION TO SYMBOLIC INTERACTION: GEORGE HERBERT MEAD PART ONE: THEORETICAL APPROACH OF SYMBOLIC INTERACTIONISM

INTRODUCTION TO SYMBOLIC INTERACTION: GEORGE HERBERT MEAD PART ONE: THEORETICAL APPROACH OF SYMBOLIC INTERACTIONISM WEEK TWO Mon Sept 21, 2009 Tues Sept 22, 2009 INTRODUCTION TO SYMBOLIC INTERACTION: GEORGE HERBERT MEAD LECTURE OUTLINE PART ONE: THEORETICAL APPROACH OF SYMBOLIC INTERACTIONISM 1. Pragmatism as a Theoretical

More information

Socialization Peter L. Berger

Socialization Peter L. Berger Socialization What happens in socialization is that the social world is internalized within the child. The same process, though perhaps weaker in quality, occurs every time the adult is initiated into

More information

The interplay of domain-specific and domain general processes, skills and abilities in the development of science knowledge

The interplay of domain-specific and domain general processes, skills and abilities in the development of science knowledge The interplay of domain-specific and domain general processes, skills and abilities in the development of science knowledge Stella Vosniadou Strategic Professor in Education The Flinders University of

More information

Youth Participation in Decision Making

Youth Participation in Decision Making Youth Participation in Decision Making Thought piece prepared for the Baha i Community of Canada October 2015 The Bahá í community of Canada is a religious community dedicated to promoting the betterment

More information

Reviewer: Prof. Encho Gerganov, PhD

Reviewer: Prof. Encho Gerganov, PhD REVIEW of the dissertation RATIONAL AND EMOTIONAL INFLUENCES ON THE DEGREE OF SUCCESS OF MEDIATION, submitted by Yael Sne, Israel, a dissertation submitted in partial fulfilment of the requirements for

More information

Social inclusion as recognition? My purpose here is not to advocate for recognition paradigm as a superior way of defining/defending SI.

Social inclusion as recognition? My purpose here is not to advocate for recognition paradigm as a superior way of defining/defending SI. Social inclusion as recognition? My purpose here is not to advocate for recognition paradigm as a superior way of defining/defending SI. My purpose is just reflective: given tradition of thought and conceptual

More information

Child Mental Health: A Review of the Scientific Discourse

Child Mental Health: A Review of the Scientific Discourse Child Mental Health: A Review of the Scientific Discourse Executive Summary and Excerpts from A FrameWorks Research Report Prepared for the FrameWorks Institute by Nat Kendall-Taylor and Anna Mikulak February

More information

The four chapters in Part I set the stage. Chapter 1 moves from the implicit common sense theories of everyday life to explicit theories that are

The four chapters in Part I set the stage. Chapter 1 moves from the implicit common sense theories of everyday life to explicit theories that are Preface This volume is designed as a basic text for upper level and graduate courses in contemporary sociological theory. Most sociology programs require their majors to take at least one course in sociological

More information

DEVELOPMENTAL PSYCHOLOGY

DEVELOPMENTAL PSYCHOLOGY DEVELOPMENTAL PSYCHOLOGY Developmental Psychology is a subfield concerned with changes over the life span, in physiology, cognition, emotion, and social behavior 1. Stage Theories of Developmental Psychology

More information

Running Head: NARRATIVE COHERENCE AND FIDELITY 1

Running Head: NARRATIVE COHERENCE AND FIDELITY 1 Running Head: NARRATIVE COHERENCE AND FIDELITY 1 Coherence and Fidelity in Fisher s Narrative Paradigm Amy Kuhlman Wheaton College 13 November 2013 NARRATIVE COHERENCE AND FIDELITY 2 Abstract This paper

More information

Systems Theory: Should Information Researchers Even Care?

Systems Theory: Should Information Researchers Even Care? Association for Information Systems AIS Electronic Library (AISeL) SAIS 2016 Proceedings Southern (SAIS) 2016 Systems Theory: Should Information Researchers Even Care? Kane J. Smith Virginia Commonwealth

More information

But does the arbitrator or mediator also have moral duties and are these different to ethical duties.

But does the arbitrator or mediator also have moral duties and are these different to ethical duties. Moral perspectives on gender and successful mediation This Paper was originally presented at the C.I.Arb. Members Conference Our Profession Our Skills Our Institute at the Selsdon Park Hotel, Surrey, England

More information

COURSE: NURSING RESEARCH CHAPTER I: INTRODUCTION

COURSE: NURSING RESEARCH CHAPTER I: INTRODUCTION COURSE: NURSING RESEARCH CHAPTER I: INTRODUCTION 1. TERMINOLOGY 1.1 Research Research is a systematic enquiry about a particular situation for a certain truth. That is: i. It is a search for knowledge

More information

ISA 540, Auditing Accounting Estimates, Including Fair Value Accounting Estimates, and Related Disclosures Issues and Task Force Recommendations

ISA 540, Auditing Accounting Estimates, Including Fair Value Accounting Estimates, and Related Disclosures Issues and Task Force Recommendations Agenda Item 1-A ISA 540, Auditing Accounting Estimates, Including Fair Value Accounting Estimates, and Related Disclosures Issues and Task Force Recommendations Introduction 1. Since the September 2016

More information

Chapter 2 THEORIES OF CHILD DEVELOPMENT

Chapter 2 THEORIES OF CHILD DEVELOPMENT Chapter 2 THEORIES OF CHILD DEVELOPMENT THEORETICAL PERSPECTIVES INTERACTION. OFFER INSIGHT INTO WHY WE BEHAVE THE WAY WE DO AND HOW WE LEARN TO ACT IN NEW WAYS. A THEORY PROVIDES A FRAMEWORK OF GENERAL

More information

5.8 Departure from cognitivism: dynamical systems

5.8 Departure from cognitivism: dynamical systems 154 consciousness, on the other, was completely severed (Thompson, 2007a, p. 5). Consequently as Thompson claims cognitivism works with inadequate notion of cognition. This statement is at odds with practical

More information

Business Ethics Concepts & Cases

Business Ethics Concepts & Cases Business Ethics Concepts & Cases Manuel G. Velasquez Chapter One Basic Principles: Ethics and Business Ethics and Morality Ethics is the study of morality. Morality = The standards that an individual or

More information

Kohlberg: Implications for high school programs

Kohlberg: Implications for high school programs Kohlberg: Implications for high school programs Author: Robert R. Newton Persistent link: http://hdl.handle.net/2345/4397 This work is posted on escholarship@bc, Boston College University Libraries. Published

More information

Introducing Psychology $

Introducing Psychology $ Introducing Psychology $ INFLUENTIAL FIGURES IN THE HISTORY OF PSYCHOLOGY The formal study of Psychology dates from the late 1880s. The first proper Psychologists were Wilhelm Wundt, William James and

More information

Comments on David Rosenthal s Consciousness, Content, and Metacognitive Judgments

Comments on David Rosenthal s Consciousness, Content, and Metacognitive Judgments Consciousness and Cognition 9, 215 219 (2000) doi:10.1006/ccog.2000.0438, available online at http://www.idealibrary.com on Comments on David Rosenthal s Consciousness, Content, and Metacognitive Judgments

More information

THE STRUCTURE OF INTERDISCIPLINARY KNOWLEDGE: A POLANYIAN VIEW. Un-chol Shin Eastern Kentucky University ABSTRACT

THE STRUCTURE OF INTERDISCIPLINARY KNOWLEDGE: A POLANYIAN VIEW. Un-chol Shin Eastern Kentucky University ABSTRACT THE STRUCTURE OF INTERDISCIPLINARY KNOWLEDGE: A POLANYIAN VIEW Un-chol Shin Eastern Kentucky University ABSTRACT The five-part theoretical scheme that Erich Jantsch devised to describe interrelations among

More information

Student Interview Paper 2. College Student Affairs 503. Nick Pazdziorko. The Pennsylvania State University

Student Interview Paper 2. College Student Affairs 503. Nick Pazdziorko. The Pennsylvania State University Student Interview Paper 2, 1 Running Head: Student Interview Paper 2 Student Interview Paper 2 College Student Affairs 503 Nick Pazdziorko The Pennsylvania State University Student Interview Paper 2, 2

More information

U. T. Place, Is consciousness a brain process?

U. T. Place, Is consciousness a brain process? 24.09x Minds and Machines U. T. Place, Is consciousness a brain process? Excerpts from U.T. Place, Is consciousness a brain process?, British Journal of Psychology 47: 44-50, 1956. Place begins by noting

More information

Chapter 02 Developing and Evaluating Theories of Behavior

Chapter 02 Developing and Evaluating Theories of Behavior Chapter 02 Developing and Evaluating Theories of Behavior Multiple Choice Questions 1. A theory is a(n): A. plausible or scientifically acceptable, well-substantiated explanation of some aspect of the

More information

INTERVIEWS II: THEORIES AND TECHNIQUES 1. THE HUMANISTIC FRAMEWORK FOR INTERVIEWER SKILLS

INTERVIEWS II: THEORIES AND TECHNIQUES 1. THE HUMANISTIC FRAMEWORK FOR INTERVIEWER SKILLS INTERVIEWS II: THEORIES AND TECHNIQUES 1. THE HUMANISTIC FRAMEWORK FOR INTERVIEWER SKILLS 1.1. Foundation of the Humanistic Framework Research interviews have been portrayed in a variety of different ways,

More information

Standards for Sexuality Education in Europe: Frequently asked questions

Standards for Sexuality Education in Europe: Frequently asked questions Standards for Sexuality Education in Europe: Frequently asked questions 1. What is holistic sexuality education? From a global perspective, sexuality education programmes can basically be grouped into

More information

A-LEVEL General Studies B

A-LEVEL General Studies B A-LEVEL General Studies B Unit 3 (GENB3) Power Mark scheme 2765 June 2015 Version V1 Final Mark Scheme Mark schemes are prepared by the Lead Assessment Writer and considered, together with the relevant

More information

Decisions, Judgments, and Reasoning About Conflicts Between Friendship and Individualism in. Adolescence and Emerging Adulthood.

Decisions, Judgments, and Reasoning About Conflicts Between Friendship and Individualism in. Adolescence and Emerging Adulthood. 1 Decisions, Judgments, and Reasoning About Conflicts Between Friendship and Individualism in Adolescence and Emerging Adulthood Abstract Expectations for friends behavior (e.g., that friends should help

More information

Defining principles of Strategic family therapy

Defining principles of Strategic family therapy Roselyne Kattar Psychologist and coach http://www.coaching-kattar.com 1 Defining principles of Strategic family therapy Strategic therapy focuses on present observable behavioral interaction and uses deliberate

More information

Cambridge International Examinations Cambridge International Advanced Subsidiary and Advanced Level. Published

Cambridge International Examinations Cambridge International Advanced Subsidiary and Advanced Level. Published Cambridge International Examinations Cambridge International Advanced Subsidiary and Advanced Level SOCIOLOGY 9699/23 Paper 2 Theory and Methods May/June 2016 MARK SCHEME Maximum Mark: 50 Published This

More information

UNIT ONE Chapters One and Two

UNIT ONE Chapters One and Two Helping Clients Forgive An Online CEU Course UNIT ONE Chapters One and Two Unit One Content Summary As you will see in reading the text for this course, Helping Clients Forgive, perhaps the most important

More information

Artificial Intelligence: Its Scope and Limits, by James Fetzer, Kluver Academic Publishers, Dordrecht, Boston, London. Artificial Intelligence (AI)

Artificial Intelligence: Its Scope and Limits, by James Fetzer, Kluver Academic Publishers, Dordrecht, Boston, London. Artificial Intelligence (AI) Artificial Intelligence: Its Scope and Limits, by James Fetzer, Kluver Academic Publishers, Dordrecht, Boston, London. Artificial Intelligence (AI) is the study of how to make machines behave intelligently,

More information

Why Is It That Men Can t Say What They Mean, Or Do What They Say? - An In Depth Explanation

Why Is It That Men Can t Say What They Mean, Or Do What They Say? - An In Depth Explanation Why Is It That Men Can t Say What They Mean, Or Do What They Say? - An In Depth Explanation It s that moment where you feel as though a man sounds downright hypocritical, dishonest, inconsiderate, deceptive,

More information

Cross-Cultural Psychology: Critical Thinking and Comtemporary Applications

Cross-Cultural Psychology: Critical Thinking and Comtemporary Applications Cross-Cultural Psychology: Critical Thinking and Comtemporary Applications Shiraev, E ISBN-13: 9780205253234 Table of Contents Chapter 1: Understanding Cross-Cultural Psychology What Is Cross-Cultural

More information

Fall 2013 Day 1 S. Marshall Perry, Ph.D.

Fall 2013 Day 1 S. Marshall Perry, Ph.D. Fall 2013 Day 1 S. Marshall Perry, Ph.D. The study of human conduct The ultimate goal of ethics is to establish standards of conduct How should people conduct themselves? What is a good way to conduct

More information

Critical Thinking Assessment at MCC. How are we doing?

Critical Thinking Assessment at MCC. How are we doing? Critical Thinking Assessment at MCC How are we doing? Prepared by Maura McCool, M.S. Office of Research, Evaluation and Assessment Metropolitan Community Colleges Fall 2003 1 General Education Assessment

More information

This article, the last in a 4-part series on philosophical problems

This article, the last in a 4-part series on philosophical problems GUEST ARTICLE Philosophical Issues in Medicine and Psychiatry, Part IV James Lake, MD This article, the last in a 4-part series on philosophical problems in conventional and integrative medicine, focuses

More information

Guide to Rating Critical & Integrative Thinking for eportfolios Washington State University, Fall 2006

Guide to Rating Critical & Integrative Thinking for eportfolios Washington State University, Fall 2006 Guide to Rating Critical & Integrative Thinking for eportfolios Washington State University, Fall 2006 For each of the seven criteria below, assess the work by: a) circling specific phrases which describe

More information

"Games and the Good" Strategy

Games and the Good Strategy "Games and the Good" Hurka!1 Strategy Hurka argues that game-playing is an intrinsic good! He thinks game-playing as an intrinsic good is a "modern view value"! Hurka says he will "defend the value only

More information

The role of theory in construction management: a call for debate

The role of theory in construction management: a call for debate The role of theory in construction management: a call for debate Seymour, D, Crook, D and Rooke, JA http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/014461997373169 Title Authors Type URL The role of theory in construction management:

More information

The Common Priors Assumption: A comment on Bargaining and the Nature of War

The Common Priors Assumption: A comment on Bargaining and the Nature of War The Common Priors Assumption: A comment on Bargaining and the Nature of War Mark Fey Kristopher W. Ramsay June 10, 2005 Abstract In a recent article in the JCR, Smith and Stam (2004) call into question

More information

The Evolution of Well-Being and the Good: Part II: A Review of Happiness Donut: A Confucian Critique of Positive Psychology by Louise Sundararajan

The Evolution of Well-Being and the Good: Part II: A Review of Happiness Donut: A Confucian Critique of Positive Psychology by Louise Sundararajan The Evolution of Well-Being and the Good: Part II: A Review of Happiness Donut: A Confucian Critique of Positive Psychology by Louise Sundararajan Thomas Lombardo In the September issue of Wisdom and the

More information

FUNDAMENTALS OF FAMILY THEORY 5. DIFFERENTIATION OF SELF

FUNDAMENTALS OF FAMILY THEORY 5. DIFFERENTIATION OF SELF FUNDAMENTALS OF FAMILY THEORY 5. DIFFERENTIATION OF SELF 5.1. Introduction of Concept The first concept is Differentiation of Self, or the ability to separate feelings and thoughts. Undifferentiated people

More information

Denny Borsboom Jaap van Heerden Gideon J. Mellenbergh

Denny Borsboom Jaap van Heerden Gideon J. Mellenbergh Validity and Truth Denny Borsboom Jaap van Heerden Gideon J. Mellenbergh Department of Psychology, University of Amsterdam ml borsboom.d@macmail.psy.uva.nl Summary. This paper analyzes the semantics of

More information

PROBLEMATIC USE OF (ILLEGAL) DRUGS

PROBLEMATIC USE OF (ILLEGAL) DRUGS PROBLEMATIC USE OF (ILLEGAL) DRUGS A STUDY OF THE OPERATIONALISATION OF THE CONCEPT IN A LEGAL CONTEXT SUMMARY 1. Introduction The notion of problematic drug use has been adopted in Belgian legislation

More information

Good Question. An Exploration in Ethics. A series presented by the Kenan Institute for Ethics at Duke University

Good Question. An Exploration in Ethics. A series presented by the Kenan Institute for Ethics at Duke University Good Question An Exploration in Ethics A series presented by the Kenan Institute for Ethics at Duke University Beliefs PEOPLE HAVE DIFFICULTY DESCRIBING THEIR MORAL WORLDVIEW. DATA CAN HELP US COMPARE

More information

An overview of the verbatim argument in Husserl s Fifth Cartesian Meditation

An overview of the verbatim argument in Husserl s Fifth Cartesian Meditation An overview of the verbatim argument in Husserl s Fifth Cartesian Meditation There is a good degree of redundancy of explanation in the condensed overview below. A clearer statement of the logically necessary

More information

Making Ethical Decisions, Resolving Ethical Dilemmas

Making Ethical Decisions, Resolving Ethical Dilemmas Making Ethical Decisions, Resolving Ethical Dilemmas Gini Graham Scott Executive Book Summary by Max Poelzer Page 1 Overview of the book About the author Page 2 Part I: Introduction Overview Page 3 Ethical

More information

Psychotherapists and Counsellors Professional Liaison Group (PLG) 15 December 2010

Psychotherapists and Counsellors Professional Liaison Group (PLG) 15 December 2010 Psychotherapists and Counsellors Professional Liaison Group (PLG) 15 December 2010 Standards of proficiency for counsellors Executive summary and recommendations Introduction At the meeting on 19 October

More information